A Comparison of Monies


by Carl Watner and Dave Scotese1
From Issue 174 – 3rd Quarter, 2017, and revised March, 2020

 

Real Money Counterfeit Note2 Federal Reserve Note Bitcoin
What is it? Coins of gold or silver Piece of paper Piece of paper Generated by computer software
What is its essence? A specific weight and purity of precious metal Paper with ink Paper with ink sanctioned by government  

A cryptographic credit for protecting transaction data

How is it made? Made from a metallic element found in nature Fabricated from a man-made product without government sanction Fabricated from a man-made product at government-approved printing facilities Generated by computer algorithms within predetermined limits
 

What non-monetary uses does it have?

Industrial and ornamental uses make it valuable to people Has no use except as paper Has no use except as paper None
 

How do multiples compare to the original unit?

 

Multiples have proportionally greater weight than originals Multiples have different numbers printed on the same amount of paper Multiples have different numbers printed on the same amount of paper Multiples are generated by the same method as originals
Is acceptance forced or voluntary? Voluntary: historically a medium of exchange for at least 5,000 years  

Functions as a medium of exchange until its false nature is discovered

 

Functions as a medium of exchange by government edict (legal tender laws) Voluntary: trading began in 2009 after the creation of the computer software
On what does its exchange value depend? Exchange value depends on supply – as determined by the amount mined, and demand. Its exchange value has exhibited a remarkable stability over centuries. Presumed exchange value decreases with amounts created at the whim of the counterfeiter Presumed exchange value decreases with amounts created by the Federal Reserve  

Exchange value is determined by the market participants with reliance on the creation schedule of its finite supply

What special requirements must be met to use or accept it? Accepted by many millions of people all over the world, generally without hesitation Accepted until its counterfeit nature is discovered Accepted until confidence in the issuing government evaporates  

Must have appropriate internet connection and computer software or trust someone who does

 

Is there risk of counterfeit? Yes, but harder to counterfeit than paper notes. See footnote 2. 100% risk Cannot be distinguished from a perfect counterfeit Computer authentication makes it impossible to spend attempted counterfeits
What are the security risks? Location must be accessible. Must be protected against theft, but is not destroyed by fire, water, or wind. Same risks as Fed Res Note and will be seized and forfeited to the government if discovered. Location must be accessible and be protected against theft, fire, water, and wind. Private keys must be protected from disclosure. Computer communications with others necessary to execute transactions.

 

1An expansion of “A Comparison,” first published in Issue 115 (4 th Quarter 2002), page 8.
2This comparison only includes counterfeit paper notes, not attempted fakes of metallic coins. During the heyday of real money, numerous devices, described as counterfeit or fake money detectors, existed. In the United States the “Gold Prohibition Act of 1934 calling for the confiscation of all gold coins, except those considered ‘rare,’ marked the disappearance of the fake coin detector.” Their modern counterpart is available through Fisch Instruments. See www.thefisch.com and THE FISCH PRECIOUS METAL BUYERS GUIDE, 6th Edition, July 2012, page 5.
.

Meeting the State Head-On


by Anonymous

 

[Author’s Note: This article was sparked by recently reading two older voluntaryist essays by Carl Watner: “Highway Tax vs. Poll Tax: Some Thoreau Tax Trivia” (Issue 71), and “Charles Lane: Voluntaryist”, the Introduction to A VOLUNTARY POLITICAL GOVERNMENT: LETTERS FROM CHARLES LANE.]

In Henry David Thoreau’s famous essay “Civil Disobedience” (which was originally titled “Resistance to Civil Government”), he wrote that he had paid no poll-tax for six years. [1] The poll-tax or head-tax, as it was sometimes called, has been part of human history since the times of the ancient Egyptians and Romans. It was basically a capitation tax levied in a fixed amount on each “taxable” person. In colonial America this often meant that the male “head of household pa[id] the tax on himself, his wife, his children sixteen years of age and older, indentured servants, and slaves.” (Rabushka, 15) The poll-tax was epitomized in Jewish law which collected one-half shekel from every man regardless of his wealth: “the rich shall not pay more and the poor shall not pay less.” (Exodus 30:11-16)

In the Massachusetts of Thoreau’s day, the poll-tax amounted to $ 1.50 per year. [2] The basis for its assessment was found in the State Constitution of 1780 “which provided that ‘the public charges of government’ should be assessed ‘on polls and estates in the manner that has hitherto been practiced’.” (Broderick, 613) As recounted in TAXATION IN COLONIAL AMERICA, Alvin Rabushka observed that the poll tax was collected in nearly all the North American colonies, and in many cases refusal to pay resulted in distraint of one’s property. [3] Although it was a standard source of revenue for both colonial and state governments, “low taxes, noncompliance, and arrears were a chronic fact of fiscal life.” (Rabushka, 868) In fact, Rabushka asserted that in Massachusetts at the time of Paul Revere’s ride on April 18, 1775, “the residents of Massachusetts had created for themselves a fiscal paradise.” (779)

So why did Thoreau and his friends, Bronson Alcott and Charles Lane, object to paying the poll-tax even though it was such a minimal amount? “It was for no particular item in the tax-bill” that Thoreau and friends “refuse[d] to pay it. (206) Much like voluntaryists today, they “simply wished to refuse allegiance to the State, to withdraw and stand aloof from it … .” (206) The Massachusetts Revised Statutes of 1836 stated that the poll-tax was to be assessed upon “each taxable person in the town, where he shall be an inhabitant the first day of May in each year.” (Broderick, 614) As Rabushka put it, “To reside was to pay.” (166) It had nothing to do with citizenship. (Lane had been born in England and resided there until 1842.) It had everything to do with simply being a person living in a particular place. Did they, by their very existence, owe taxes to the town government where they lived? According to the town of Concord and the State of Massachusetts, there was no legal way to avoid the tax, short of leaving the state permanently. Yet, they did not want to leave their homes or lose their property, but neither did they want to support the institution of government.

Thus the “inhabitants” of Massachusetts’ towns had to meet the poll tax head-on, much as people today are faced with confronting local, state, and federal income taxes. [4] Governments, then and now, take one’s very existence as evidence that one owes a tax. In “Resistance to Civil Government,” Thoreau wrote, “If there were one who lived wholly without the use of money, the State itself would hesitate to demand it of him.” (200) However, this is not true today, even if it were in Thoreau‘s time (which is doubtful). If there were such a person in today’s United States, the IRS or a state revenue department would still want to know 1) why that person hadn’t filed a tax return; 2) if that person had any taxable income; and 3) how that person lived without incurring a tax liability. It is just as nearly impossible to hide from the IRS as it would have been to hide from the town-constable in Thoreau’s day. (It might even be more difficult today with the advent of government identifiers, computers, and government issued birth certificates.)

The only highwayman I ever met was the state itself – When I have refused to pay the tax which is demanded for that protection which I did not want, itself has robbed me – When I have asserted the freedom it declared, it has imprisoned me. – Henry David Thoreau, JOURNAL: Vol. 2, 1842- 1848. Edited by Robert Sattelmeyer. (Princeton University Press, 1984), p. 262.

Thoreau’s refusal to pay the poll tax would be much like refusing to file or pay federal and state income taxes today. It pits the individual against the State. The IRS assumes that your very existence means that you owe taxes, or at least an explanation as to why you don’t. The IRS places the burden of proof on the individual taxpayer to show why no return is due and/or to prove why no tax is owed. In principle, the government assumes that everyone owes, and that it may take as much or as little as the President, members of Congress and the IRS agree on. In effect, what you think you ‘own’ is actually government property that the government lets you ‘rent.’ See what happens to you and your property if you don’t pay your ‘rent’ (i.e., taxes). Much like monarchs of old, the government grants people the privilege of keeping only as much as the government allows. Taxation is not theft, from the government’s perspective, because it is only taking what already belongs to it. The whole premise behind government taxation is essentially the idea that you and your property belong to the State; that the government ‘owns’ everything in the geographic area over which it exerts control.

People are enslaved if their bodies are owned by others; but they are also slaves if others control their property or the results of their labor. If the State may take one dollar out of what a man owns, then it may take up to his last dollar. Once admit the right of the State to tax, then the State becomes the owner of all property. As in most situations in life, it is best to resist at the beginning, and thus it behooves us to stand tall and firm against the State and resist head-on by refusing to file or pay taxes.

Endnotes

[1] See page 203 of Thoreau. Numbers within parentheses in the text are page numbers of a particular article or book referred to below.

[2] $1.50 would be 7.5% of a $ 20 gold piece, which contains slightly less than an ounce of pure gold. We can extrapolate that into today’s prices by taking 7.5% of gold at $ 1300 an ounce and arrive at approximately $97, which would have been collected once a year.

[3] Walter Harding (37) was the first to note that the town-tax collectors of Massachusetts were empowered to levy upon the goods and property of the person, and if these were insufficient to satisfy the tax, then the collector was authorized to “take the body of such person and commit him to prison, there to remain until he shall pay the tax and the charges of commitment and imprisonment, or shall be discharged by order of law.”

[4] The problem of avoiding sales tax, which is nearly ubiquitous today, is not discussed in this article.

References

John C. Broderick, “Thoreau, Alcott, and the Poll Tax,” 53 STUDIES IN PHILOLOGY (1956), pp. 612- 626.

Walter Harding, “Thoreau in Jail: Was It Legal?” 26 AMERICAN HERITAGE (August 1975), pp. 36-37.

Alvin Rabushka, TAXATION IN COLONIAL AMERICA, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2008.

Henry Thoreau, “Resistance to Civil Government,” in Elizabeth P. Peabody (ed.) AESTHETIC PAPERS, New York: G. P. Putnam, 1849, Article X, pp. 189-211.

Laying the Axe to the Root of the Tree: Voluntaryist Strategies to End Human Slavery


by Carl Watner

In the Fall of 2013, I received a direct-mail campaign piece from The Foundation for Economic Education which was accompanied by a DVD titled AMAZING GRACE. The DVD told the story of the efforts of William Wilberforce and the British abolitionists to outlaw the slave trade. Their primary focus was on getting enough votes in the House of Commons and the House of Lords to make it a criminal act for any British subject or British-owned ship to transport slaves within the empire. When this goal was finally achieved in 1807, the abolitionists realized that they needed to undertake another campaign, this time to outlaw the ownership of slaves within the British dominions. Finally, in 1833, both houses of Parliament passed an emancipation bill which made the slaves apprentices until 1838, when they would become officially free. In addition, the British government awarded the owners of these slaves 20 million pounds in government bonds to compensate them for the loss of their “property.” [1]

Watching AMAZING GRACE got me thinking. Although most civilizations have had some form of slavery, historically, what were some of the non-political ways that the slaves had been freed? How might slavery have been abolished in a voluntaryist society where there was no central government to decree what was legal and illegal? Although it is clear that slavery and voluntaryism are incompatible, it is still likely that some form of slavery would occur in a voluntaryist society, but it would not be a socially acceptable institution. Slavery is the total violation of a person’s self-ownership rights. Indeed, some abolitionists referred to slavery as “man stealing.” Under a system of chattel slavery, slave owners not only buy and sell their slaves like beasts of burden, but the children of slaves are the slave owner’s property, too. As David Brion Davis wrote in THE PROBLEM OF SLAVERY IN WESTERN CULTURE, “the slave has three defining characteristics: his person is the property of another man, his will is subject to his owner’s authority, and his labor or services are obtained through coercion.” [2] In most cases, this requires the existence of a government and laws to define the rights of the slave owner, laws against manumission, laws that create compulsory slave patrols and, above all else, the use of the government police power to force the return of runaway slaves. [3]

Even though advances in technology and the Industrial Revolution and human understanding were making slavery less justifiable and less economically sustainable before the American Civil War, the big question still remained: Was it right or wrong for one person to own another? Many early American abolitionists believed that it was necessary “to convince their fellow-citizens … that slave-holding was a heinous crime,” but they shared different opinions about the proper way to bring about its cessation. [4] William Lloyd Garrison and his followers, for example, were opposed to involvement in politics. Whether it be office holding or participating in political parties, they did not want to support a government which permitted slavery. To Garrison’s way of thinking the end could not justify the means. They sought “a change in the moral vision of the people.” [5] “In seeking to reform the public sentiment that lay behind laws and constitutions and that inspirited them, the Garrisonians struck at the source of the problem.” [6] Moral suasion (as they called it) laid the axe at the root of the tree. Their task was “to awaken public opinion to the horror of slavery and to stimulate it to take action against the evil. … Without public opinion on their side, the abolitionists could accomplish” very little. Using moral persuasion, they had to concentrate on “awakening consciences and disseminating the truth” that slavery was evil. [7] Lydia Maria Child, a cohort of Garrison, pointed out that even if slavery were outlawed by Congress “great political changes … without corresponding changes in the moral sentiment of a nation, would be worse than useless.” The evils of slavery would reappear “in a more exaggerated form.” [8]

It is clearly wrong to think that the only way slavery could have been eliminated in the United States is by having fought the Civil War. As Jim Powell wrote in the conclusion to his book, GREATEST EMANCIPATIONS: HOW THE WEST ABOLISHED SLAVERY, “a peaceful, persistent, multi-strategy process of eroding slavery would have made it much less difficult to arrive at a point where blacks could be both emancipated and safe, flourishing with equal rights in a free society.” [9] Voluntaryists reject violent means, such as those used by John Brown and the armies of the North. Violence only begets violence and certainly does not change minds. Voluntaryists also reject governmental solutions to the problem of slavery. They would not become involved in party politics or government emancipation programs. What Voluntaryists would have done is to constantly emphasize that slavery was an unmitigated evil and dispel the assumption that “blacks were incapable of living in freedom.” [10] Voluntaryists would have supported the establishment of trade and vocational schools and colleges that would help blacks demonstrate that they were as capable, hard-working, frugal, and enterprising as their white counterparts. People like Frederick Douglas, Doctor James McCune Smith, William Wells Brown, and Booker T. Washington were shining examples of what could be achieved.

In a letter written about March 1, 1837, the sisters, Sarah and Angelina Grimke pretty much summarized what they described as “The definite, practical means by which the North can put an end to Slavery in the South.” They purported to set forth the sins of the North, and then “showed what Northerners could do to overthrow the great Prison House of the South.” Although they endorsed petitioning Congress and refusing to vote for pro-slavery Congressmen, they emphasized the voluntaryist, non-political means of undermining slavery:

Let the northern churches refuse to receive slaveholders at their communion tables, or to permit slaveholding ministers to enter their pulpits. … Let northern men who go to the South to make their fortunes, see to it that those fortunes are not made out of the unrequited toil of the slave. … Let northern manufacturers refuse to purchase cotton, for the cultivation of which the laborer has received no wages. Let the grocer refuse to buy the rice and sugar of the South, … . Let the merchant refuse to receive the articles manufactured of slave grown cotton, and let the consumer refuse to purchase either the rice, sugar or cotton articles … which has cost the slave his unpaid labor, his tears and his blood. Every northerner may, in this way, bear a faithful testimony against slavery at the South, by withdrawing his pecuniary support. …

If Northerners were to do all we have marked out, can anyone doubt the powerful influence which it would produce on southern conscience and Southern interest? Could slavery live a single year under such an organized, disinterested, noble opposition to it? No, it would wither and die, never to be revived again. If Northerners were to purify their hearts and cleanse their hands from the sin of slavery, then would their tongues be loosed, and they would unceasingly pour into the ears of Southerners, the calm remonstrance, the brotherly rebuke, the earnest entreaty “to loose the bands of wickedness, to undo the heavy burdens, and to let the oppressed go free, and to break every yoke.” … Oh no! He still has the heart of a man, and that heart would soon break under the hammer of truth. [11]

However, some major ideas were missing from the Grimkes’ letter, such as mounting a major tax refusal campaign against any government which supported slavery; and encouraging the slaves, themselves, to stop work and confront their oppressors with their refusal to cooperate. [12] Whether one believes that northern declamations against slavery and the religious, social, and economic boycott of slave-owning Southerners would be effective, history shows that these and other nonviolent means of weakening and undercutting slavery did exist, and in many cases, were at least partially successful, in accomplishing their goal.

In the case of England, the British abolitionists undertook a massive public relations campaign to arouse the public against the slave trade. As Alexis de Tocqueville observed, it was “something absolutely without precedent in history.” [13] To begin the massive job of changing public opinion, the British abolitionists used every means at their disposal. They used popular forums, like the debating societies (where women often took part), to argue the demerits of slavery. They collected many thousands of signatures on petitions. They printed and distributed letters reporting on the status of their campaign and solicited contributions to support their cause. They publicized and utilized a logo and medallion created by Josiah Wedgewood and his workers, which read “Am I not a man and a brother?” They encouraged people to boycott the use of slavegrown sugar. They issued the first widely distributed political poster showing the inhumane conditions existing in ships engaged in the slave trade. They organized local committees under the umbrella of a national organization, and they put an ex-slave, Olaudah Equiano, on tour to publicize his autobiography, which rapidly became a best-seller. [14]

The sugar boycott in Britain reached its climax during the year 1792, when it was estimated that 300,000 men, women, and children abstained from using slave-grown sugar. A tract written and published in the same year argued that since neither the slave dealer nor planter had any moral right to control the slave or the products of his labor, they could not convey good title. Anyone who bought from them only had a criminal possession; by receiving the produce of the slave’s labor a person became an accessory to robbery, after the fact. The advocates of the boycott argued, that “If we purchase the commodity, we participate in the crime.” [15] A 20th Century researcher on “slave sugar boycotts and female activism” noted:

of purifying oneself from pollution by the sin of slavery, …; and it was a way of rooting antislavery in domestic culture; and it was a means of promoting economic systems based on waged rather than unwaged labor. But it had another important significance. It was promoted as a way of bringing about the downfall of the slave system as rapidly as possible, without awaiting the results of parliamentary deliberations. … Abstention encouraged universal participation. .. Abstention campaigners recognized that their effectiveness depended on gaining the widest possible public participation, and thus actively solicited the support of children, of the poor, and most, notably, of women. … Private abstention became an expression of public anti-slavery opinion. … Abstention was direct action by the masses.

In 1824, Quaker pamphleteer, Elizabeth Heyrick, asserted that slavery was a question in which we are all implicated. The West Indian planter, and the people of this country, stand in the same moral relation to each other, as the thief and the receiver of stolen goods.] There was no neutral ground: “the whole nation must now divide itself into the active supporters, and the active opposers of slavery.” … Abstention was thus linked to an unwillingness to rely on governmental action. … If government would not take action the people must bring about the end of the slave trade themselves by putting economic pressure on the planters and slave traders. … Government could be by-passed and, through abstention, ‘We, the people, the common people of England – we ourselves will emancipate’ [the slave]. Abstention campaigns were thus about the people taking things into their own hands rather than relying on the authorities. [16]

Although the sugar boycott only reduced the price of sugar by one penny per pound, this alarmed the West Indian slave owners “more than all the alarm that had been produced by moral and legislative action.” [17] Midgley concludes that the boycott’s “direct impact on sugar production in the West Indies was very limited. … Abstention’s significance lay rather in its vital role in creating a national anti-slavery culture in Great Britain.” [18]

American abolitionists, with the active participation of many Quakers, created their own Free Produce movement. In 1839, Thomas Branagan published his tract, BUYING STOLEN GOODS SYNONYMOUS WITH STEALING. He argued that “Slavery depends on the consumption of the produce of its labour for support. Refuse this produce, and slavery MUST cease. Say not that individual influence is small. Every aggregate must be composed of a collection of individuals. It is only by such collected individual influence, that any important end is attained; any great design is accomplished by man. The power of numbers supplies the want of sufficient force in the individual; … .” [19] Elihu Burritt (1810-1879), the Learned Blacksmith, noted in Reason Seven of his preCivil War tract TWENTY REASONS FOR TOTAL ABSTINENCE FROM SLAVE-LABOUR PRODUCE, “It is a measure that does not trench upon any principle of free trade. It asks the interference of no legislation against the introduction or use of slave-labour produce. It requires no petitions to parliaments, diets, national assemblies, courts, or congresses. It involves nothing but the free, voluntary legislation of the individual conscience upon the articles of household or personal consumption.” [20] The Quaker-led American Free Produce Association called the boycott “one of the most efficient means of peacefully abolishing the system of slavery.” [21]

The Quakers did not limit their abolitionist activities to the free produce movement. In fact, their opposition to slavery began much earlier. The Quakers became the only major religious denomination that would not allow its members to own slaves. [22] They eventually voluntarily abolished slavery and slaveholding among the members of their religion. Those who refused were disowned from the Society. In 1758, the Philadelphia Yearly Meeting resolved to exclude members who bought or sold slaves. “Those who persisted in violating the rules by purchasing Negroes were … subjected to discipline. … They could not have the unity of Friends” if they continued to own slaves. [23] The Quakers asserted that slaves were “prize” goods, that is, captives of war, violence, cruelty, and oppression, of theft and robbery of the highest nature. The use of prize goods or any goods obtained through illegitimate means was inconsistent with their testimony towards peace and nonviolence. Therefore it was only consistent that they forego the purchase and services of human beings who had been captured in Africa, even though they themselves had not been involved in the original violence.

Not only did most Quakers manumit their slaves, but they actually paid reparations to their former slaves, as compensation for their past unpaid services. In this sense, they may have been the only “ruling class” ever to voluntarily relinquish their power over others. [24] One of the earliest Quakers to attack slavery was Elias Hicks (1748-1830), who manumitted his own slaves in 1778. In 1811, he published his OBSERVATIONS ON THE SLAVERY OF THE AFRICANS AND THEIR DESCENDANTS, AND ON THE USE OF THE PRODUCE OF THEIR LABOR. “Hicks insisted that all men were free under the laws of God; that no one had a moral right to enslave his fellows for any reason whatever. Users of the products of slave labor shared in the guilt of the slaveholders, he believed; they were equally culpable in the sight of God. No man-made law sanctioning slavery could remove this guilt, nor could slaveholders rightfully refuse to emancipate their slaves. On the contrary, they owed their slaves wages for the work which had unjustly been required of them.” [25]

Many Quakers were active in the Underground Railroad, and stood ready to help runaway slaves. But as Harriet Tubman and other contemporaries noted, the slaves had to want to be free. She is reputed to have said, “I freed a thousand slaves, but I could have freed a thousand more if they had only known they were slaves.” No external authority could make them free. This was exactly the point that the nonviolent Garrisonians clung to before John Brown’s raid and the outbreak of the Civil War. Violence was not a permanent solution to the problem of slavery. Violence would not make the slaves want freedom; violence would not convince the slaveholders that their ownership of slaves was a moral wrong; and violence would not change public sentiment. Slavery and governments and violence were so intertwined that the Garrisonians believed that it was foolish to believe that violence exercised by governments could be used to end slavery.

Furthermore, as the nonviolent critics of John Brown pointed out a war against slavery would be almost as bad as slavery itself. [26] Parker Pillsbury expressed a basic pacifist insight when “he said, ‘We cannot cast out the devil of slavery by the devil’ of war.” [27] Adin Ballou asked, “If the slaves were freed by rebellion what is to be done with them for the next one hundred years? It would take at least a century to educate them out of the ferocity engendered by such conflict. How are they to be employed, trained for liberty, and organized into well ordered communities? And above all how is this work to be accomplished with the great mass of whites in the country full of horror, loathing, and revenge toward them? … Can’t we wait the operation of a more peaceful process? Can’t we content ourselves with holy efforts to bring about a change in public sentiment, so that this thing may be accomplished, without resorting to such horrible measures? It may seem hard to wait, but if we do not wait, we shall do worse.” [28] Ballou claimed that there were “vast differences between a people trained for liberty and self-government through a century and a half, and the millions of long crushed slaves, schooled to servility and studiously kept in ignorance. Such a people need all the help and benefit of a peaceful emancipation.” [29] William H. Furness, Philadelphia Underground Railroader and Unitarian pastor summarized the damage that Brown’s raid did to abolitionism. “In resorting to force” he injured the cause of abolitionism. “He did not take into account the undeviating law that violence produces violence. …Revolutions effected by force always end, sooner or later, in reestablishing the tyranny they undertake to overthrow.” [30]

After the war, there were a few nonviolent abolitionists who realized that the Northern victory was hollow. They disagreed with Garrison’s belief that government-forced emancipation was a success. “H.C. Wright [had] repeatedly said that only ideas, not bullets, could permanently settle the question of slavery. … Ezra Heywood pointed out that a government that could abolish slavery as a military necessity had no antislavery principles and could therefore re-establish slavery if circumstances required it.” Indeed, the federal government initiated military conscription during the war (1862), even before Lincoln issued the Emancipation Proclamation in 1863. “Abby Kelley Foster … predicted flatly, if the slave is freed only out of consideration for the safety of the Union, then ‘the hate of the colored race will still continue, and the poison of that wickedness will destroy us as a nation’.” At least a few of the nonviolent abolitionists “had not forgotten their fundamental belief that to achieve humanitarian reform, particularly if it was to be thorough and permanent reform, the methods used to achieve it must be consistent with the nature of the reform.” [31] “What most pro-war abolitionists often chose to brush aside was that after the fighting most blacks would still be living in the South among … Confederates” who were opposed to their emancipation. [32] What the critics of war saw was that “War as a means to end the oppression of Negroes was to be little more than tragic futility.” [33]

In predicting the success of forced emancipation as a result of war, Thomas Wentworth Higginson noted that in reality “freedom of the slave ultimately had to be the work of the slave. He stated frankly in a private letter: ‘The great obstacle to anti-slavery action has always been the apparent feebleness and timidity of the slaves themselves.’ … Nonresistants held similar sentiments. One of them repeated Lord Byron’s often quoted line, ‘Who would be free, themselves must strike the first blow.’ The antislavery movement could help in removing ‘the outward forms of bondage,’ but it was up to the Negroes to raise themselves in the scale of civilization.” As Adin Ballou put it, “To put an end to slavery by emancipation will not materially elevate the character of the race,” nor make them free. The slaves have to want to free themselves; otherwise efforts by others to free them would ultimately fail. [34]

Douglas Lorimer in his article “Black Slaves and English Liberty” concluded that it was this attitude of desiring freedom and taking responsibility for one’s own self which actually brought freedom to the slaves in England. “Aided by free blacks and sympathetic whites … they established their own liberty.” The slaves simply voted with their feet and chose to become free servants. [35] Since English law of the mid to late 1700s did not take cognizance of a person’s skin color (“the law took no notice of a negro”), common law processes applied to those slaves that were brought to England by their masters. [36] In 1772, in what became known as the Somerset decision, Lord Mansfield removed the greatest threat to blacks in England: they could not be forcefully deported to a foreign country (where their slave status would be legally recognized). [37] Slaves in England were subject to the writ of habeas corpus. A Negro could not be held as a slave against his will, since there was no positive law sanctioning slavery within England. However, as Lorimer emphasized, the end of slavery in England came about, not from the decisions of the courts, but from the actions of the slaves.

One of the ways that some American slaves struck their first blows for freedom was by arranging to buy themselves. This was done by the slave purchasing himself from his master. [38] It is impossible to calculate the number of slaves who were freed by purchase, though historical records show it was in the hundreds, if not thousands. Often times, the self-purchase movement went forward in spite of the legal restrictions imposed by all of the slave states. It was most prevalent in the industrialized cities, where slaves usually had more opportunities to earn money. In cities, such as Charleston, SC, self-purchase arrangements were sometimes made through churches. In other places, already freed slaves were used as intermediaries and/or trustees to hold title to slaves who bought themselves. The self-purchase movement helped to undermine the system of slavery by refuting the argument that slavery was justifiable and necessary because Negroes were inferior beings. It demonstrated that Negroes could attain their freedom in the face of overwhelming obstacles. Furthermore, it aroused envy and discontent among those who were still slaves by showing what could be accomplished by free Negroes. [39]

So what would laying the axe to the root of the tree mean in terms of voluntaryist strategy? Ultimately, it would mean influencing public opinion to such an extent that slavery would no longer be tolerated. Society and culture would gradually dry up the support for slavery. [40] This is what happened in at least one northern state. “By the time of the first United States Census, in 1790, no slaves were officially listed in Massachusetts.” [41] Indeed in examining how slavery was ‘dried up’ in Massachusetts, in 1795, “Jeremy Belknap … claimed that public opinion was chiefly responsible for the wane of slavery. Summarizing the instances in which slaves had sued for and obtained their freedom before the Revolution, he noted that the process became easier after the ratification of the state Constitution of 1780, when many Negroes asked for their freedom and got it, while others simply absconded and depended upon the weight of public opinion to sustain them in their behavior.” [42] Thus, “When public opinion would no longer tolerate slavery it disappeared ….” [43] No war, no violence, no government legislation nor emancipation proclamations were necessary. When public opinion turns against slavery, support for slavery collapses, and the slaves simply become free.

The nonviolent campaign to abolish slavery holds many lessons for the voluntaryist who wants to abandon taxation and the state. As I noted in my anthology, RENDER NOT: THE CASE AGAINST TAXATION, the arguments against taxation are very analogous to the arguments against slavery. As I explain there, taxation is not only theft – it is slavery. If voluntaryists are to learn anything from the movement to abolish the slave trade and slavery it should be that they must lay the axe at the root of the tree and convincingly demonstrate that the premise behind taxation is that the State owns the citizen. When public opinion no longer tolerates the coercive monopolization of public services exercised by the State, the State will disappear. No war, no violence, no government legislation, nor government tax holidays will be necessary. When public opinion turns against taxation, support for the State will collapse, and the citizenry will simply become free.

Footnotes

[1] Hochschild, Adam, BURY THE CHAINS, Boston: Houghton Mifflin Company, 2005, pp. 347-348.

[2] Davis, David Brion, THE PROBLEM OF SLAVERY IN WESTERN CULTURE: Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1966, p. 31.

[3] Hummel, Jeffrey Rogers, EMANCIPATING SLAVES, ENSLAVING FREE MEN, Chicago: Open Court, 1996, p. 353.

[4] Kraditor, Aileen, MEANS AND ENDS IN AMERICAN ABOLITIONISM, New York: Pantheon Books, p. 5.

[5] Wiecek, William M., THE SOURCES OF ANTISLAVERY CONSTITUTIONALISM IN AMERICA, 1760-1848, Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1977, p. 235.

[6] ibid., p. 246.

[7] Kraditor, op. cit, pp. viii, 165, 216.

[8] ibid., p. 23.

[9] Powell, Jim, GREAT EMANCIPATIONS: HOW THE WEST ABOLISHED SLAVERY, New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2008, p. 245.

[10] Stauffer, John , “How the Bonds Were Finally Broken,” THE WALL STREET JOURNAL (February 1-2, 2014), pp. C5, C7 at p. C5.

[11] Barnes, Gilbert H. and Dumond, Dwight L, editors, LETERS OF THEODORE DWIGHT WELD, ANGELINA GRIMKE WELD, AND SARAH GRIMKE 1822-1844 (Volume I), Gloucester: Peter Smith, 1965, pp. 371-372. Emphasis in original.

[12] Perry, Lewis, RADICAL ABOLITIONISM, Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1973, p. 235.

[13] Hochschild, Adam, “Against All Odds,” MOTHER JONES (January/February 2004), pp. 66-73, at p. 67.

[14] ibid., pp. 70-71.

[15] Fox, William, AN ADDRESS TO THE PEOPLE OF GREAT BRITAIN, ON THE PROPRIETY OF ABSTAINING FROM WEST INDIA SUGAR AND RUM, London: 10th edition: Daniel Lawrence, 1792, p. 4. Found online.

[16] Midgley, Clare, “Slave Sugar Boycotts, Female Activism and the Domestic Base of British Anti-Slavery Culture,” 17 SLAVERY AND ABOLITION (December 1996), pp. 137-162, at 152-154. Emphasis in original.

[17] Mabee, Carleton, BLACK FREEDOM: THE NONVIOLENT ABOLITIONISTS FROM 1830 THROUGH THE CIVIL WAR, New York: The Macmillan Company, 1970, pp. 185-186.

[18] Midgley, op. cit., p. 155.

[19] Branagan, Thomas, THE GUARDIAN GENIUS OF THE FEDERAL UNION, New York: Published for the Author, 1839, p. 33. See pp. 30-34 for “Buying Stolen Goods Synonymous With Stealing.” Digitized and online by Google.

[20] Burritt, Elihu, TWENTY REASONS FOR TOTAL ABSTINENCE FROM SLAVE-LABOUR PRODUCE, post-1852. Found online at the Antislavery Literature Project site.

[21] Mabee, op. cit., p. 186. Also see Nuermberger, Ruth Ketring, THE FREE PRODUCE MOVEMENT: A QUAKER PROTEST AGAINST SLAVERY, Durham: Duke University Press, 1942.

[22] Mabee, op. cit., p. 3.

[23] Zilversmit, Arthur, THE FIRST EMANCIPATION: THE ABOLITION OF SLAVERY IN THE NORTH, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1967, p. 76.

[24] Watner, Carl, “The Radical Libertarian Tradition in Antislavery Thought,” 3 JOURNAL OF LIBERTARIAN STUDIES (Fall 1979), pp. 299-329 at p. 310.

[25] Drake, Thomas E., QUAKERS AND SLAVERY IN AMERICA, Gloucester: Peter Smith, 1965, p. 116.

[26] Mabee, op. cit., p. 339.

[27] ibid., p. 362.

[28] ibid., pp. 323-324.

[29] ibid., p. 324.

[30] ibid., p. 327.

[31] ibid., p. 336.

[32] ibid., p. 339.

[33] ibid., p. 330.

[34] Perry, op. cit., pp. 236-237.

[35] Lorimer, Douglas A., “Black Slaves and English Liberty: A Reexamination of Racial Slavery in England,” 3 IMMIGRANT & MINORITIES (July 1984), pp. 121-150 at pp. 124-125.

[36] Drescher, Seymour, “Manumission in a Society without Slave Law: Eighteenth Century England,” 3 SLAVERY & ABOLITION (December 1989), pp. 85-101 at p. 87.

[37] Hochschild (2005), op. cit., pp. 46-50.

[38] Matison, Sumner Eliot , “Manumission By Purchase,” 33 THE JOURNAL OF NEGRO HISTORY (April 1948), pp. 146-167 at pp. 166- 167.

[39] ibid., pp. 153 and 167.

[40] Freeman, Harrop A., “A Remonstrance for Conscience,” 106 UNIVERSITY OF PENNSYLVANIA LAW REVIEW (April 1958), pp. 806-830 at p. 825.

[41] Cushing, John D., “The Cushing Court and the Abolition of Slavery in Massachusetts,” 5 THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF LEGAL HISTORY (April 1961), pp. 118-144 at p. 138.

[42] ibid., pp. 136-137.

[43] ibid., p. 144.

H.L. Mencken


 

By H.L. Mencken

[Editor’s Note: This article is excerpted from Volume 117, No. 3048 of THE NATION (Dec. 5, 1923, pp. 647-648). In it, Mencken examines his penchant for liberty and its relationship to his work as a literary critic.]

I often marvel that the gentlemen who concern themselves with my own books, often very indignantly, do not penetrate more competently to my essence. Even for a critic I am excessively garrulous and confidential; nevertheless, it is rare for me to encounter a criticism that hits me where I live and have my being. A great deal of ink is wasted trying to discover and denounce my motive in being a critic at all. I am, by one theory, a German spy told off to flay, terrorize, and stampede the Anglo-Saxon. By another I am a secret radical, while professing to admire Coolidge, Judge Gary, and Genghis Khan. By a third, I am a, fanatical American chauvinist, bent upon defaming and ruining the motherland. All these notions are nonsense; only the first has even the slightest plausibility. The plain truth is — and how could it be plainer? — that I practice criticism for precisely the same reason that every other critic practices it: because I am a vain fellow, and have a great many ideas on all sorts of subjects, and like to put them into words and harass the, human race with them. If I could confine this flow of ideas to one subject I’d be a professor and get some respect. If I could reduce it, say, to one idea a year, I’d be a novelist, a dramatist, or a newspaper editorial writer. But being unable to staunch the flux, and having, as I say, a vast and exigent vanity, I am a critic of books, and through books of Homo sapiens, and through Homo sapiens of God.

So much for the motive. What, now, of the substance? What is the fundamental faith beneath all the spurting and coruscating of ideas that I have just mentioned? What do I primarily and immovably believe in, as a Puritan believes in hell? I believe in liberty. And when I say liberty, I mean the thing in its widest imaginable sense — liberty up to the extreme limits of the feasible and tolerable. I am against forbidding anybody to do anything, or say anything, or think anything so long as it is at all possible to imagine a habitable world in which he would be free to do, say, and think it. The burden of proof, as I see it, is always upon the policeman, which is to say, upon the lawmaker, the theologian, the right-thinker. He must prove his case doubly, triply, quadruply, and then he must start all over and prove it again. The eye through which I view him is watery and jaundiced. I do not pretend to be “just” to him — any more than a Christian pretends to be just to the devil. He is the enemy of everything I admire and respect in this world — of everything that makes it various and amusing and charming. He impedes every honest search for the truth. He stands against every sort of good-will and common decency. His ideal is that of an animal trainer, an archbishop, a major general in the army. I am against him until the last galoot’s ashore.

This simple and childlike faith in the freedom and dignity of man — here, perhaps, stated with undue rhetoric — should be obvious, I should think, to every critic above the mental backwardness of a Federal judge. Nevertheless, very few of them, anatomizing my books, have ever showed any sign of detecting it. But all the same even the dullest of them has, in his fashion, sensed it; it colors unconsciously all the diatribes about myself that I have ever read. It is responsible for the fact that in England and Germany (and, to the extent that I have ever been heard of at all, in France and Italy) I am regarded as a highly typical American — in truth, as almost the archetype of the American. And it is responsible equally for the fact that here at home I am often denounced as the worst American unhung. The paradox is only apparent. The explanation of it lies in this: that to most Europeans the United States is still regarded naively as the land of liberty par excellence, whereas to most Americans the thing itself has long ceased to have any significance, and to large numbers of them, indeed, it has of late taken on an extreme obnoxiousness. I know of no civilized country, indeed, in which liberty is less esteemed than it is in the United States today; certainly there is none in which more persistent efforts are made to limit it and put it down. I am thus, to Americans, a bad American, but to Europeans, still unaware of the practical effects of the Wilson idealism and the Roosevelt saloon-bouncer ethic, I seem to be an eloquent spokesman of the true American tradition. It is a joke, but the joke is not on me.

Liberty, of course, is not for slaves: I do not advocate inflicting it on men against their conscience. On the contrary, I am strongly in favor of letting them crawl and grovel all they please-before the Supreme Court of the United States, Gompers, J. P. Morgan, Henry Cabot Lodge, the Anti-Saloon League, or whatever other fraud or combination of frauds they choose to venerate. I am thus unable to make the grade as a Liberal, for Liberalism always involves freeing human beings against their will-often, indeed, to their obvious damage, as in the cases of the majority of Negroes and women. But all human beings are not congenital slaves, even in America. Here and there one finds a man or a woman with a great natural passion for liberty-and a hard job getting it. It is, to me at least, a vast pleasure to go to the rescue of such a victim of the herd, to give him some aid and comfort in his struggle against the forces that seek to regiment and throttle him. It is a double pleasure to succor him when the sort of liberty he strives for is apparently unintelligible and valueless- for example, liberty to address conventions of the I.W.W., to read the books of such bad authors as D. H. Lawrence and Petronius Arbiter, to work twelve hours a day, to rush the can, to carry red flags in parades, to patronize osteopaths and Christian Science healers, to belong to the best clubs. Such nonsensical varieties of liberty are especially sweet to me. I have wrecked my health and dissipated a fortune defending them — never, so far as I know, successfully. Why, then, go on? Ask yourself why a grasshopper goes on jumping.

But what has liberty to do with the art of literary criticism, my principal business in this vale? Nothing — or everything. It seems to me that it is perfectly possible to write profound and valuable literary criticism without entering upon the question of freedom at all, either directly or indirectly. Aesthetic judgments may be isolated from all other kinds of judgments, and yet remain interesting and important. But this isolation must be performed by other hands: to me it is as sheer a psychological impossibility as believing that God condemned forty-two little children to death for poking fun at Elisha’s bald head. When I encounter a new idea, whether aesthetic, political, theological, or epistemological, I ask myself, instantly and automatically, what would happen to its proponent if he should state its exact antithesis. If nothing would happen to him, then I am willing and eager to listen to him. But if he would lose anything valuable by a volte face — if stating his idea is profitable to him, if the act secures his roof, butters his parsnips, gets him a tip — then I hear him with one ear only. He is not a free man. Ergo, he is not a man. For liberty, when one ascends to the levels where ideas swish by and men pursue Truth to grab her by the tail, is the first thing and the last thing. So long as it prevails the show is thrilling and stupendous ; the moment it fails the show is a dull and dirty farce.

My “Road to Freedom”


By Peter Bos

[Editor’s Note: Peter Bos, the author of this short piece was the first person (to our knowledge) to assert (in the words of Richard Boren) that “the property protection function of government could be assumed by insurance companies,” and to point out “that those insurance companies would have a proprietary interest in the protection of the insured’s property.” Furthermore, Bos noted that “this would not require the creation of a new industry, or a new technology, because the basic mechanism already existed.” His book, THE ROAD TO FREEDOM AND THE DEMISE OF NATION STATES (2015), elaborates these concepts. For a more detailed discussion in THE VOLUNTARYIST, see Issue 167: Richard Boren, “Insurance Companies as Competing Governments: Whose Idea Was It?”]

My life’s story and the stages by which I discovered the road to freedom could be the subject of another book, but in the meantime, I offer this brief explanation. As a survivor of the Nazi occupation of my native country, the Netherlands, I became acutely aware of what it means not to be free and personally saw the violence and destruction of which nation-states are capable. As a result, I early on became interested in individual freedom and sovereignty. Fortunately, I was able to come to the United States after receiving a scholarship at the Massachusetts Institute of Technology, where I graduated with a degree in aeronautical engineering.

After graduation, I was drafted into the U.S. Army and received a commission from Officer Candidate School. Because of my technical background, I became a NIKE maintenance officer and, shortly thereafter, was assigned as head of the U.S. Army Air Defense School at Fort Bliss, Texas. After discharge from the Army, I became part of a small space program team at Chance Vought, Inc. that launched a successful SCOUT missile that placed a small payload into orbit in response to the Russian Sputnik.

Sometime thereafter, I became associated with the Space Technology Laboratories of Ramo Wooldridge and the Aerospace Corporation in California, where I learned about Andrew J. Galambos, an astrophysicist and owner of the Free Enterprise Institute (FEI), from Alvin Lowi. [1] They were friends and colleagues. At that time (the early 1960s), we were all part of the U. S. government’s space program.

Alvin asked me to handle the CCI (Capitalism, Constitutionalism, and Individualism) bookshelf at the FEI course he was presenting. I accepted, and thus had a chance to personally monitor the original Galambos course materials. At that time, Galambos, like Ayn Rand, was a strict Constitutionalist and both were strong supporters of Barry Goldwater. Both were advancing a constitutionally limited political democratic State Government. Actually, Galambos’ concept was to further expand the State to include two more branches – a constitutional branch and a resistor branch, the latter to provide checks and balances. They, like Mises and Hayek, and most classical liberals, succumbed to the fallacy of ceding the protection, jurisprudence, and money issuance functions to the State. The exceptions were Spooner, Riegel, Heath, and LeFevre. However, they did not have or provide a workable solution for providing protection.

It was during this exposure to Galambos’ materials in 1962, that I first introduced “the proprietary government using insurance” concept to Alvin Lowi. After my close friend, Chuck Estes, suggested this to Galambos, I subsequently presented this idea at the following year’s FEI Alumni conference. Fortunately, unbeknown to me and to his credit, Galambos realized the value of this concept and totally changed his subsequent lectures to incorporate it, albeit without giving credit. (I personally never attended any of the presentations given by Galambos nor got to know him except by reference).

Around the same time, I had become quite acquainted with Ayn Rand’s books and presentations. When Nathaniel Branden came to Los Angeles to present the lecture series on Objectivism, I chose to attend these rather than continuing with Lowi and Galambos. The main reason was that I found that Rand and Branden provided a more fundamentally integrated approach to philosophy, ethics and the psychology of individualism.

Unfortunately, I never had the opportunity to properly introduce the insurance concept to either Rand or Branden and, even then, I may not have been able to change their minds. I had not formally written about this concept – other than preparing an outline of my presentation. Fortunately, some years later, Murray Rothbard did incorporate the insurance concept in his writings.

During these years, I also became very interested in education and, as a parent, in the Montessori Method. I served as chairman of the board of directors of Escuela de Montessori, a school in the Los Angeles area. I was also instrumental in founding several affiliated Montessori schools there. Personally, to gain additional business experience, I enrolled in the Anderson School of Business at UCLA, where I received an MBA degree.

After establishing a successful solar energy program at the Aerospace Corporation, I became director of the new energy technology program at the Electric Power Institute in Palo Alto, California. In 1981, I founded my own company, Polydyne, Inc., which did some of the earliest electric vehicle design and fuel cell development for small-distributed energy systems for residential and commercial applications.

[1] For more on Galambos see the following entries on www.voluntaryist.com under the heading “How I Became a Voluntaryist”: Richard Boren, “Andrew J. Galambos and How I Became a Voluntaryist;”, Charles Estes, “We Never Called Him ‘Andy,’: My Recollections of the Person and Philosophy of the Earlier Joseph A. Galambos Alias Andrew Joseph Galambos – The Liberal;” and Alvin Lowi, “Voluntary Government as a Marketable Service: Reminiscences on the History of an Idea.”

The Practical Perspective


By Carl Watner
(Excerpted from Issue 141)

Objection 1: What would happen to the poor in a voluntaryist society?

Americans have often been referred to as the most generous people on earth. Although there has never been a true voluntaryist society, America, from its colonial roots to the early 20th Century, more closely approximated voluntaryist parameters than many other nations. What did we find happening in such circumstances?

In early America, private and community care for the poor often preceded government’s assumption of those responsibilities. If Americans wanted a school, a library, an orphanage, or a hospital they simply built it for themselves. The vitality and success of American communities rested on their voluntary nature. History and theory demonstrate that a free people produce many more goods and services than their counterparts in a centrally organized economy. Thus, there is more to go around in a free society, and the poor generally have a higher standard of living than the poor in a collectivist society. This economic largess is largely the result of the investment in tools and individual savings which are promoted by the free market economy.

Not only were there probably fewer “poor” in America, but those of the lower classes were able to better care for themselves and their poorer kin. Until the advent of State welfare in the early 20th Century, mutual aid societies, church, and fraternal organizations flourished. By 1920, about 18 million Americans belonged to some type of mutual aid society or fraternal order, which often provided some form of health, disability, and death benefits to their members. With the advent of the Great Depression (which voluntaryists assert was caused by government financial policies), government welfare programs began crowding out private efforts.

The private sector in America has not only proved itself capable of producing and creating large amounts of wealth, but it has also demonstrated its willingness to contribute to community causes and helping the poor. The record of American philanthropy is so impressive that it would require several books to list its achievements. So when one asks, “What would happen to the poor in a free society?” one only has to look at American history for an answer. As James Bryce writing in 1888 observed, “In works of active beneficence, no country has surpassed, perhaps none has equaled the United States.” [13]

Objection 2: The voluntaryist insight points out that the State depends on the cooperation of its citizens. Aren’t these citizens showing by their actions that they are consenting to the government they have?

Answer: Yes, citizens may obey their governments, but they are no more consenting to their “voluntary” enslavement than a victim of a robbery consents to his victimization. The victim of a robbery (your money or your life) “voluntarily” hands over his wallet to prevent a worse occurrence (his own death). When governments eliminate criminal penalties for failure to file and pay taxes, we can begin looking at how much real support governments might obtain voluntarily.

Objection 3: If there were no government, what would prevent criminals from taking over control of society?

Answer: First of all, voluntaryists would point out that criminals have taken over control of our society. It is only the fact that our criminal governors have so legitimated themselves in the eyes of most people that they are no longer considered criminal.

The existence of a peaceful society depends upon the fact that the large majority of people residing therein respect other people and their property. In the absence of coercive government to “protect” these peaceful people, there would be private defense and mutual protection agencies, voluntarily funded, to protect people from would-be aggressors. Each patron would contract for the level of protection he or she desired and could afford. In such a society, sureties and insurance companies would probably provide a great deal of protection, since they would have the most to lose from destruction and theft of property and life. Sureties or bonding companies would ultimately be responsible for the good behavior of those they covered.

Objection 4: Who would pay for the roads?

Answer: Those who use them and require their existence. Although roads have been a government monopoly throughout much of history, there is much historical evidence that roads could built and operated on a for-profit basis. Government monopolization and control of the roads has led to many inefficiencies, deaths, and environmental destruction. [14]

Objection 5: Is it right that voluntaryists benefit from government services and yet do not wish to pay for them?

Answer: Voluntaryists recognize that there is no such thing as a free lunch. They are not asking for government services in the first place. Governments by their coercive provision of certain services eliminates the voluntaryist’s range of choice among providers. The voluntaryist may need to know “what time it is,” but that doesn’t mean that the government has a right to eliminate all competitors and force the consumer to purchase from only a government agency. If a thief steals your watch, outlaws all other forms of telling time, tells you the time, and then demands that you pay him for providing you with this service, would you consider yourself obligated to pay him? Of course not. Similarly, the voluntaryist holds that the government should not be providing any services in the first place (any more than the thief should have stolen your watch or outlawed would-be competitors). When government uses coercion to enforce its will, many problematic situations arise. Voluntaryists try to resolve them by abandoning government, and using private services when available and affordable.

Voluntaryist Talking Points*


 

By Peter Spotswood Dillard
Number 120

As a voluntaryist, I want to secede from The United States of America, the State of Pennsylvania where I now live, the County of Chester, and the Township of Pennsbury without relocating. To borrow a phrase from the sixties, I want to “opt out” and live my life without having to participate in the coercive schemes of these authorities. Others can set up a state if they want to–but leave me alone.

I can already hear the objections from some of my statist neighbors. I’d like to anticipate them with a few perfectly logical replies that might prove useful to other voluntaryists under fire.

Objection: Doesn’t government provide you with a lot of benefits: police protection, defense, road maintenance, etc.? Doesn’t your enjoyment of these benefits mean you have a duty to obey the state?

Reply: No one asked me if I wanted any of this stuff. I never signed any contract. I just found myself in circumstances where forcing people to pay for things they never requested was a fait accompli. Sure, I enjoy these benefits. Yet, it doesn’t follow that I have a duty to pay for them. Suppose someone started mowing my lawn without asking my permission. Clearly that doesn’t give him the right to show up one day and force me to pay for his “service.” Furthermore, police protection, defense, road maintenance, and other services currently provided by government can be provided more efficiently by private contractors on the open market because they must voluntarily obtain the business. For example, when it snows a guy plows my driveway for me. If he charges what I think is “too” much, or does a poor job, then I look for someone else to provide the service. Since government generally “outlaws” the competition, there is no incentive to provide a better job at a lower price.

Objection: You preach one thing and practice something else. You’ve spent your whole life obeying the state’s authority by paying your taxes. Doesn’t that show you’ve given your tacit consent to government?

Reply: The notion of tacit consent goes at least as far back as John Locke, but it didn’t make sense in the seventeenth century, and it still doesn’t make sense today. What would tacit dissent be like? Moreover, when I hand my wallet over to a crook who threatens to blow me away with a .38 if I refuse, I’m not giving my tacit consent that robbery is morally acceptable. So when I pay my taxes to a government that threatens to imprison me if I don’t comply, it’s hard to see how I’m giving my tacit consent–whatever that is–that state coercion is morally acceptable. Just because many of us have spent our lives following the dictates of the state, it doesn’t follow that we believe in the legitimacy of government. Maybe there are lots of closet voluntaryists!

Objection: Love it or leave it. You’re free to move someplace where there isn’t any government. Why not build a house on the moon?

Reply: First, why should I incur the sizeable cost of relocating to a stateless place? If the fellow mowing my lawn without permission promised to stop if I moved to a desert island at my own expense I’d say he was extremely illogical, if not daft. More importantly, the objector is willing to let me opt out, so long as I opt out far away from here. But what difference does it make whether I opt out here or a thousand miles from here? In either case, I won’t interfere with anybody else and I won’t be paying any taxes. I conclude that if I can be allowed to opt out on the moon, I should also be allowed to opt out right smack in the middle of the good old U.S. of A.

Objection: You make it sound like you don’t have any say in the matter. But you do. In the next election you can always vote against authorities and ballot initiatives you feel are too coercive. All it takes is a majority of voters to change things.

Reply: The very idea of majority rule is irrational. If given the option, no liberty-loving individualist would ever subjugate himself to a group in which a majority of members called the shots. The majority might decide it was okay to sacrifice virgins. They might decide, with George Wallace, that segregation of blacks and whites should be state policy. The majority might decide, with socialistic communitarians like Hillary Clinton, that everyone should be strong-armed into mediocre, state-run health care. The majority might decide, with fascistic communitarians like Robert Bork, that gay people should be treated like dogs. The voluntaryist doesn’t want anything to do with majority rule since the majority, no more than the minority, have no right to violate my self-ownership or property rights.

Objection: What about the mechanisms we have to protect individual liberties against the tyranny of the majority? You know, the Supreme Court, the Bill of Rights.

Reply: The Supreme Court is a government institution. The justices are government employees that receive tax money for life. Once they get in, a simple majority renders decisions in a manner that is absolutely unaccountable to the people those decisions affect. Worse than the tyranny of a majority over a minority, the Court gives us the tyranny of a minority over a majority. Even the Bill of Rights doesn’t go far enough, because it still permits the use of force to collect taxes. Even if the Bill of Rights ever offered any protection against government, it has clearly failed to protect us today.

Objection: What if everybody seceded? Wouldn’t that lead to total chaos?

Reply: If everybody–my fellow inhabitants of Pennsbury Township, the Eskimos, the Red Chinese, etc.–seceded from government and minded his or her own business, the world would be a better place. However, we need to remember it still wouldn’t be perfect. Trouble arises when one group chooses voluntaryism, another doesn’t, and the statists set out to conquer the voluntaryists. But, as Thomas Paine observed long ago, by cultivating mutually beneficial free trade with partners around the globe–China, Cuba, Iraq, North Korea, whomever–the voluntaryists would create a strong incentive for their trading partners not to initiate force against them. After all, you don’t bite the hand that feeds you.

In the case of a determined aggressor, the voluntaryists could use all the money they save by abolishing taxes to devise effective defense systems that minimize casualities. For example, instead of funneling billions of tax dollars to the military-industrial complex before it produces products that work, the voluntaryists could take competive bids from independent contractors to design a truly effective missile shield–not like the one President Bush is proposing, which at best is sixty percent effective when the wind isn’t blowing. Continued funding would be contingent on results, not talk. Smart, non-violent alternatives, such as hacking into an aggressor’s computer network and disabling programs that coordinate attacks, could finally be developed and utilized, making the world a safer place.

Objection: Some people don’t have the same opportunities you have. They need better food, adequate housing, better education, better jobs, and affordable health care. Government is a way to increase opportunity by satisfying these needs.

Reply: I agree it would be good for more people to have more opportunities. The question is, does a third party have a right to provide those opportunities by forcing other people to fund them? Suppose Terry needs $20,000 to buy a new car that would increase his opportunities by enabling him to start his own delivery business. Does that give you the right to point a gun at my head or threaten me with imprisonment unless I give Terry $20,000? Certainly not. From the fact that I have X and Terry wants or needs X, it doesn’t follow that you have the right to make me give Terry X. Substitute “better food,” “adequate housing,” etc. for X and say good-by to the welfare state. Of course, people should be allowed to contribute to the welfare of others–but please, no arm-twisting.

Objection: What’s so bad about coercion? Remember the classic case of the mad doctor who has the only supply of a medicine that can cure a plague that will kill thousands but refuses to share any? Would any one be justified in taking the medicine away from the doctor?

Reply: Coercion corrupts, political power corrupts, and the use of coercion sets a precedent that soon boomerangs out of control. If you permit someone to use violence for a “good” cause, how do you object when someone else grabs power to use violence on behalf of a “bad” cause? Then, all you can argue about is whether the cause is “good” or “bad,” not whether violence should be used. Violence inevitably violates someone’s rights, so it best be left alone except in self-defense.

Let’s get clear about what the classic case does and does not establish. It may establish that it’s all right for SOMEBODY to deal with the mad doctor. It does not establish the legitimacy of a STATE with broad coercive authority, including the authority to take the medicine away from the mad doctor. So, how would voluntaryists deal with him if he won’t listen to reason? First of all, the voluntaryist remembers that the doctor is not the cause of the plague. He is thankful the doctor knows the remedy. If the doctor won’t sell, that’s his right, but without a government-backed patent, someone else might be able to produce a generic version of the medicine. The voluntaryists might ostracize the doctor, refusing to sell him food, water, and other necessities, leaving him helpless until he agrees to share the medicine. In the worst case scenario–the plague will kill thousands by tomorrow unless the voluntaryists administer the medicine today, the mad doctor is the only person in the world who knows the secret ingredients, no one else can figure them out before tomorrow–someone might steal the medicine. But no one would euphemistically call such “stealing,” charity or taxation or dub it by some other name. No state with a monopoly on the use of force is needed to do the job. However, this worst case scenario is highly unlikely, and the voluntaryists would still recognize that the doctor’s rights had been violated. They, themselves, would probably be more content with recognizing that “if you take care of the means, the end will take care of itself.” That is all that they, as voluntaryists, could do.

Viva voluntaryism!

*Thanks to Carl Watner for helpful comments on an earlier draft of this article.

A Voluntaryist Bibliography, The Short List


Prepared by Carl Watner, July 2009
(With suggestions by subscribers)

 

I. Books that helped me evolve into a voluntaryist

  • Ayn Rand, ATLAS SHRUGGED
  • Ayn Rand, FOR THE NEW INTELLECTUAL
  • Leonard Read, GOVERNMENT – AN IDEAL CONCEPT
  • Murray Rothbard, MAN, ECONOMY, AND STATE
  • Lysander Spooner, NO TREASON, NO. 6
  • William Graham Sumner, THE FORGOTTEN MAN, THE CHALLENGE OF FACTS, WAR, EARTH-HUNGER AND OTHER ESSAYS (4 vols.)
  • Morris and Linda Tannehill, THE MARKET FOR LIBERTY
  • Ludwig von Mises, HUMAN ACTION
  • William Wooldridge, UNCLE SAM, THE MONOPOLY MAN

II. Other books that I would recommend to those interested in voluntaryism

  • Bruce Benson, THE ENTERPRISE OF LAW: Justice Without the State
  • Etienne de La Boetie, THE POLITICS OF OBEDIENCE
  • Robert LeFevre, THE FUNDAMENTALS OF LIBERTY
  • Albert Jay Nock, OUR ENEMY, THE STATE
  • Jim Payne, PRINCESS NAVINA VISITS VOLUNTARIA
  • Robert Ringer, RESTORING THE AMERICAN DREAM
  • Murray Rothbard, FOR A NEW LIBERTY
  • Mary Ruwart, HEALING OUR WORLD IN AN AGE OF AGGRESSION
  • Lysander Spooner, THE LYSANDER SPOONER READER
  • Henry David Thoreau, “Civil Disobedience”
  • Benjamin Tucker, INSTEAD OF A BOOK
  • Carl Watner, I MUST SPEAK OUT

III. Economics for those interested in voluntaryism

  • Walter Block, DEFENDING THE UNDEFENDABLE
  • Elgin Groseclose, MONEY AND MAN
  • Henry Hazlitt, ECONOMICS IN ONE LESSON
  • Murray Rothbard, POWER AND MARKET
  • Murray Rothbard, THE CASE FOR A 100 PER CENT GOLD DOLLAR
  • Murray Rothbard, WHAT HAS GOVERNMENT DONE TO OUR MONEY?

IV. Reading Lists

  • www.mises.org/story/1830: David Gordon, “The Meaning and History of Liberty: An In-Print Bibliography”
  • www.tolfa.us/read.htm: Jim Davies, The On Line Freedom Academy
  • “The Literature of Liberty,” by Tom G. Palmer in David Boaz (ed.), THE LIBERTARIAN READER (1997), pp. 415-453.

V. Suggestions added by subscribers since June 2012

  • Mark Kurlansky, NONVIOLENCE
  • Michael Huemer, THE PROBLEM OF POLITICAL AUTHORITY
  • Ayn Rand, THE VIRTUE OF SELFISHNESS
  • Larken Rose, THE MOST DANGEROUS SUPERSTITION
  • Butler Shaffer, BOUNDARIES OF ORDER
  • Gene Sharp, THE POLITICS OF NONVIOLENT ACTION
  • Marc Stevens, ADVENTURES IN LEGAL LAND
  • Carl Watner, RENDER NOT: THE CASE AGAINST TAXATION

 

A Voluntaryist Bibliography, Annotated (1982)


by Carl Watner

General Introduction And Purpose Of This Bibliography

 

 

The Voluntaryists are a newly formed group of libertarians who have organized to promote non-political strategies to achieve a free society. We have chosen to label ourselves Voluntaryists because the term “libertarian” has become too closely associated with the Libertarian Party. We believe that all efforts to elect libertarians to political office conflict with libertarian principles and that such efforts are strategically unsound. Engaging in political action, running candidates for office, and encouraging people to vote must inevitably sabotage the Voluntaryist goal of delegitimizing the State. The only long-range and lasting way to curtail State power is to dissolve the illusion of legitimacy which all States must have in order to sustain themselves. Libertarians must come to act consistently with the Voluntaryist insight: that all State power ultimately depends on the sanction and cooperation of its victims.

The Voluntaryist Insight

The Voluntaryist insight, that all State power is grounded on general popular acceptance, was first formulated by Etienne de la Boetie (1530-1563). In his Discourse on Voluntary Servitude, which was probably written during the 1550’s, la Boetie discussed one of the most critical problems of political philosophy; namely, the question of civil obedience. “Why in the world do people consent to their own enslavement?” he asked. “Why do the bulk of the people acquiesce in their own subjection?” La Boetie answered these questions by explaining the governmental mystique created by the rulers and their intellectual apologists. By relying on custom, by providing both bread and circuses to the citizenry, and by creating a vast network of governmental supporters dependent on political plunder, governments were able to engineer and sustain their own popular acceptance among the populace.

La Boetie was also the first political philosopher to move from an emphasis on the importance of consent to the strategic question of toppling tyranny by leading the public to withdraw their consent. He saw that violence was not necessary:

“Obviously there is no need of fighting to overcome the tyrant, for he is automatically defeated if the country refuses to consent to its own enslavement: it is not necessary to deprive him of anything, but simply to give him nothing; … is therefore the inhabitants themselves who permit, or, rather, bring about, their own subjection, since by ceasing to submit, they would put an end to their servitude”(p. 50). Realizing the great value of natural liberty, la Boetie called for a thorough process of educating the public to the truth, a process which would give back to the people a knowledge of the the myths and illusions fostered by the State. The primary task of the opponents of State power is therefore an educational one: to alert the public to their despotic condition and then to demystify and desanctify the entire State apparatus.

There are two English language editions of la Boetie’s essay readily available. The best, and the one quoted from above, was prepared by Free Life Editions of New York in 1975 with the title of The Politics of Obedience: The Discourse of Voluntary Servitude. (See rear of this pamphlet for ordering instructions.) Despite his advocacy of libertarian political activity, Murray Rothbard’s introduction for this edition, “The Political Thought of Etienne de la Boetie”, gives a great deal of support to the ‘Voluntaryist critique of political action. Political activity not only unnecessarily reinforces the image of State legitimacy, which, as la Boetie points out, we must destroy, but it is also unlikely to end State power. La Boetie’s analysis implies that educational activities and non-violent resistance to the State (such as occurred in India during the Gandhian campaigns against the British) are sufficient to topple States. The other edition of The Discourse was prepared by William Flygare and is accompanied by a preface from James Martin. It is titled The Will to Bondage (Colorado Springs: Ralph Myles Publisher, 1974). Included is the original French version of the essay, along side the first English translation, which was prepared in 1735. The Free Life edition carries a 1942 translation, so it is worthwhile to compare the two.

There is not, a great deal of secondary material concerning la Boetie and his Discourse in English. The two best general discussions have been prepared by Nannerl O. Keohane and James Brown Scott. Scott includes a chapter entitled “Le Contr ‘Un de la Boetie – Tyrannicide through the Ages” in his The Catholic Conception of International Law (Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press, 1934). La Boetie’s essay is treated as part of the historical tradition of tyrannicide. Scott refers to it as “a literary exercise in behalf of liberty in which he [la Boetie] condemns tyranny in any and all of its forms as ruinous alike to the tyrant, the state, and the people” (p.299). He aptly summarizes la Boetie’s position: “He does not require of the people that they shall violently overthrow the tyrant, but merely that they shall cease to support him, whereupon he will fall of his own dead weight” (p.302). Keohane’s discussion of la Boetie originally appeared as “The Radical Humanism of Etienne de la Boetie” (38 Journal of the History of Ideas, Jan. – March, 1977, pp. 119-130) and then was condensed for his book, Philosophy and the State in France: The Renaissance to the Enlightenment (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1980) as “On Voluntary Servitude: La Boetie” (pp. 92-98). Keohane places la Boetie in the historical perspective of 16th Century France by pointing out that la Boetie was both a lawyer and member of parliament. Despite his place in the State apparatus, Keohane regards la Boetie’s premises as basically anarchistic, because they lead to the conclusion that no man or group of men should have authority over other individuals.

In his newly published The Ethics of Liberty (Atlantic Highlands: Humanities Press, 1982), Murray Rothbard devotes some space to the Voluntaryist insight in his chapter on “The Nature of the State”. The latter half of this chapter deals explicitly with la Boetie and generally discusses the significance of State legitimacy. Rothbard shows how the State has historically aligned itself with the Church, and that when this became no longer possible,how the State assumed control over public education. The State is thus able to “mould the minds of its subjects” from kindergarten to graduate school in order to foster this voluntary servitude. In a footnote Rothbard cites two other disparate thinkers who have understood the importance of majority consent to governmental tyranny. He quotes from David Hume’s essay “On the First Principles of Government” (see any edition of David Hume, Essays, Literary, Moral and Political). Hume, who was no libertarian wrote: “Nothing appears more surprising … than the easiness with which the many are governed by the few, and the implicit submission with which men resign their own sentiments … to those of their rulers. … [W]e shall find that, as ‘force’ is always on the side of the governed, the governors have nothing to support them but opinion. It is, therefore, on opinion only that government is founded; Rothbard also cites Ludwig von Mises, Human Action (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1949, p. 188ff).

Voluntaryism From A Historical Perspective

The Voluntaryist insight and the general non-political approach to social change which it suggests has a long standing place in the libertarian tradition. For a general discussion see Voluntaryism in the Libertarian Tradition (Baltimore: The Voluntaryist, 1982) by Carl Watner. (See reverse of this pamphlet for ordering instructions.) Any late 19th Century encyclopedia should have an entry under “Voluntaryism”, since the term originated back in the early 1820’s when it was used in the religious disputes between established churchmen in England and the dissenters. Typical of such articles is the one found in Chambers’ Encyclopedia at volume 10, page 23 (Philadelphia: J. P. Lippincott and Co., 1882). During the 1830’s and until the 1850’s, the term Voluntaryism was applied to the advocates of private schools in England. These voluntary educationists saw a religious threat in State controlled education and many believed that the law of supply, and demand, or the voluntary principle, as they termed it, would provide for the education of the whole English people. Edward Miall, a well known publisher and dissenter wrote a book, entitled Views of the Voluntary Principle (London: Aylott and Jones, 1845) which characterized the meaning of Voluntaryism for mid-19th Century England.

Auberon Herbert attempted to repopularize the term Voluntaryism during the 1880’s and 1890’s in his voluntaryist journal Free Life. Herbert was a supporter of voluntary taxation and one of the last projects of his life was the preparation and publication of “A Plea for Voluntaryism” which appeared in The Voluntaryist Creed (Oxford, 1908). Both the “Plea” and “The Principles of Voluntaryism and Free Life” by an American supporter of Herbert have been reprinted in Eric Mack’s collection The Right and Wrong of State Compulsion and Other Essaysby Auberon Herbert (Indianapolis: Liberty Classics, 1978).

Another classical example of Voluntaryism at work in England is to be found in William Godwin’s Enquiry Concerning Political Justice which first appeared in 1793. The best introduction to Godwin is found in the 1946 reprint edition by F.E.L. Priestley (Toronto: University of Toronto Press.) Godwin believed that physical force was too uncertain in its results and that peaceful resistance to tyrannical government was more desirable and effective. Godwin argued for reasonable discussion and disciplined non-cooperation as the means of fighting authority. In Book II, Chapter III, and Book IV, Chapter I, he urged that “All government is founded on opinion. Men at present live under any particular form, because they conceive it their interest to so do. …Destroy this opinion, and the fabric which is built upon it falls to the ground.” “Make men wise, and by that very operation you make them free. Civil liberty follows as a consequence of this; no usurped power can stand against the artillery of opinion.”

Godwin, in one important particular, was at variance with the main tradition of dissent in the 18th Century. A large body of dissenters thought in terms of politics; they tended to see problems as political and to seek political solutions. They favored associations and the normal methods of bringing political pressure to bear; they looked to legislative action for a solution of problems. Godwin, on the other hand, looked only to the reformation of the individual, objected to political parties, and had no faith in political solutions of what were for him simply moral problems. The voluntaryistic dissenters believed that moral agitation was always more effective and more proper than political activity.

The 19th Century abolitionists both in England and the United States, struggling to abolish slavery and the slave trade, were faced with similar problems. Was slave-holding to be abolished by moral suasion or political means? Should abolitionists participate in party politics or should they hold aloof from such controversies? Should they create their own organizations to propagate the abolition of slavery? Should they use political action to achieve their goals? The problems faced by the 19th Century abolitionists were very similar to the ones faced by 20th Century libertarians in their struggle to achieve a free society.

William Lloyd Garrison, Wendell Phillips, and Henry Clarke Wright were the leaders of the radical abolitionist movement in America. These men and their followers in the New England Non-Resistance Society held that all office holding and voting was morally wrong and reprehensible. Ultimately, the Garrisonians came to see the Constitution as a document which supported slavery and one to which they could not swear personal allegiance. These abolitionists suggested many of the arguments used by anti-political libertarians today. For example, they raised the issue of personal integrity. How could any abolitionist (read, libertarian) accept a government salary or swear a public oath of allegiance to the Constitution, or uphold laws which violate personal liberty? Garrison argued that political parties alter one’s fundamental outlook towards the State. The Liberty Party, which had been purposely formed as an anti-slavery party in 1840, appalled Garrison, both as a matter of theory and of tactics. He claimed that an anti-slavery party would split the movement and dilute anti-slavery principles by dragging them into the political gutter.

The Garrisonian ideas were propagated in many forums. Garrison engaged in a debate with James Birney, soon to be head of the Liberty Party in the 1830’s. In their A Letter on the Political Obligations of Abolitionists(Boston: Dow and Jackson, 1839) Garrison argued that moral suasion, not political action, was needed to reform public sentiment. Both of Garrison’s chief helpers, Phillips and Wright, independently expressed their anti-political views. Wright authored a small book entitled Ballot Box and Battlefield (Boston: Dow and Jackson, 1842) in which he claimed that the ballot box was only a make shift substitute for the violence of bullets on the battlefield. Wright held that no man could honestly undertake to become a voter and then vote against the existence of government. “May a man consent to be invested with power to do an evil?”, he asked. Wright claimed that a man may never rightfully consent to do what he thinks wrong. He who would do so proves himself dishonest. “He consents to be vested with power to do what he acknowledges to be wrong, and swears to do it. Such a man is unworthy of any trust.” Thus Wright concluded the fact that any man, knowing the nature and duties of a Congressman or President, “will consent to hold these offices, is of itself sufficient evidence that he is not a true and good man.” Wright summarized his argument by stating that he would not vote, even if by his one vote he could free all the slaves. Wendell Phillips considered the question: Can an Abolitionist Vote or Take Office Under the United States Constitution? (New York: American Anti-Slavery Society, 1845) and concluded quite straight forwardly that they could not.

The secondary literature dealing with the abolitionist position on voting is quite extensive and certainly much easier to locate than some of the primary materials. Two standard discussions of the voting controversy can be found in Aileen Kraditor, Means and Ends in American Abolitionism (New York: Pantheon Books, 1969) and in Lewis Perry, Radical Abolitionism: Anarchy and the Government of God in Antislavery Thought (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1973). Another excellent discussion of the “Garrisonian Critique” of politics can be found in William Wiecek, The Sources of Antislavery Constitutionalism in America, 1760-1848 (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1977). Some of Henry Clarke Wright’s writings (see the index for the entries under Wright), as well as excerpts from the Garrison-Birney exchange (see pp. 153-160), can be found in Truman Nelson’s Documents of Upheaval, Selections From Willaim Lloyd Garrison’s The Liberator 1831-1865 (New York: Hill and Wang, 1966).

Another very interesting aspect of the abolitionist movement is to be found in the writings of Henry David Thoreau and his close friend Charles Lane. Lane was an Englishman attracted to this country through his friendship with Bronson Alcott (another close friend of Thoreau). Both Alcott and Lane were arrested for refusal to pay their town taxes and their examples served to spur Thoreau onto his well known example of tax resistance. All three were opposed to voting and made their views, widely known. Lane wrote an extensive series of letters which appeared in Garrison’s The Liberator in 1843. They were entitled A Voluntary Political Government and have been recently reprinted (Carl Watner, editor, St. Paul: Michael Coughlin, Publisher, 1982). In the letters, Lane advocated a totally voluntary, anarchistic society. Lane’s aversion to politics is apparent in many of the letters and he realized that governmental control rests on the acquiescence of the citizenry. “This mixture of education with politics [by which he meant public schooling] is only a contrivance to gild the iron chains by which men are so despotically bound.” In his third letter, Lane urged us to go as far as possible from human governments. Participation in politics is evil. “Like all our enemies, State oppression will die of itself if we meddle not with it,” and do not support it. Disown the government and do not support it with your taxes. Enlighten the oppressed as to their own self-imposed servitude, but stay away from the State for it will only contaminate you. The similarity between Lane’s answer and Thoreau’s solution in Thoreau’s own “Resistance to Civil Government” (better known as his essay on “Civil Disobedience”) (Aesthetic Papers, Boston: Elizabeth Peabody, 1849) is quite striking:

“When the subject has refused allegiance, and the officer has resigned his office, then the revolution is accomplished.”

Lysander Spooner, the famous individualist-anarchist and constitutional lawyer, also played a prominent role in the abolitionist movement. Before he evolved into an outright anarchist, Spooner wrote some trenchant and logical attacks against the Garrisonian claim that the Constitution supported slavery. These are reprinted in The Collected Works of Lysander Spooner (Charles Shively, editor, Weston: M & S Press, 1971) and appear as The Unconstituionality of Slavery (Boston: Bela Marsh, Part I – 1845 and Part II – 1847). Spooner’s famous An Essay on Trial By Jury (Boston: John Jewett and Co., 1852) and his attacks on the Fugitive Slave law were all written to show why the common law, when uncorrupted by State legislation, upheld individual rights and destroyed slavery. There are some brilliant passages in all these works upholding natural rights, and especially the rights of all citizens to resist unjust acts of oppression perpetrated by the government (see his A Defence For Fugitive Slaves, Boston: Bela Marsh, 1850, Chapter II, “The Right of Resistance, and the Right to have the Legality of that Resistance judged of by a Jury”).

After the Civil War, and as a result of having lived through a domestic rebellion in which all the ideals of the American Revolution were totally ignored, Spooner became an anarchist. In his No Treason (1867 and 1870) series Spooner showed that the U.S. government could not claim either voting or tax-paying as proof that individuals consented to the government. Neither were evidence of any single person’s consent to the Constitution as a legal document. Spooner claimed that both paying taxes and voting were done under indirect threats, and therefore, were to be construed as acts of self-defense. However, Spooner never maintained that people should vote or that voting was proper or that he personally would ever take any part in the political process. Rather, he argued that when and if people vote, their actions were not to be interpreted as evidence that they actually supported the Constitution. Spooner eventually concluded that no one should have the right to vote or make laws. “No human being, nor any number of human beings, have any right to make laws, and compel other human beings to obey them. To say that they have is to say that they are masters and owners of those whom they require such obedience.” Spooner’s final conclusions on voting were expressed in his piece “Against Woman Suffrage”, which was reprinted in Benjamin Tucker’s Liberty (June 10, 1882, No. 22, p. 4) and in Rampart Individualist (Vol. 1, No. 1 and 2, Winter and Spring 1981, pp. 53-55).

Many other 19th Century individualist-anarchists supported Spooner’s position against political involvement. Josiah Warren, for example, one of the earliest American anarchists, rejected politics and engaged in a life long quest for the development of anarchist communities. Benjamin Tucker, the student of both Warren and Spooner, and editor of the famous journal Liberty (1881-1908), compiled his views on anarchist methods in a section of his book, Instead of a Book (originally published 1893, and reprinted by Haskell House Publishers, New York, 1969). The best of Tucker’s anti-political views are presented in a short editorial called “The Method of Anarchy” (Liberty, June 18, 1887; Haskell House edition, p. 415). Tucker advocated passive resistance as the superior alternative to either ballots or violent revolution.

Referring to the Voluntaryist insight, Tucker claimed that passive resistance (which hereafter shall be referred to as non-violent resistance) was … the most potent weapon ever wielded by man against oppression”. “Power feeds on its spoils, and dies when its victims refuse to be despoiled. They can’t persuade it to death; they can’t vote it to death; they can’t shoot it to death; but they can always starve it to death. When a determined body of people, sufficiently strong in numbers and force of character to command respect and make it unsafe to imprison them, shall agree to quietly close their doors in the face of the tax collector… government … will go by the board.” Tucker cited the near success of the Irish Land League and No Rent Movement in Ireland as examples of non-violent resistance campaigns.

Francis Tandy (a follower of Tucker) in his chapter on “Methods” in Voluntary Socialism (Denver: by the author, 1896) reiterated the strength of Tucker’s argument for non-violent resistance. “To gain anything by political methods, it is first necessary to gain a majority of the votes cast, and even then you have to trust to the integrity of the men elected to office. But with non-violent resistance this is unnecessary. … A strong, determined and intelligent minority, employing methods of non-violent resistance, would be able to carry all before it.” Tandy astutely pointed out the important relationships between means and ends in libertarian thought. Non-violent “resistance can never pass a law. It can only nullify laws. Consequently, it can never be used as a means of coercion and is particularly adapted to the attainment of Anarchy. All other schools of reform propose to compel people to do something. For this they must resort to force, usually by passing laws. These laws depend upon political action for their inauguration and physical violence for their enforcement. Anarchists are the only reformers who do not advocate physical violence. Tyranny must ever depend upon the weapon of tyranny, but Freedom can be inaugurated only by means of Freedom.” Tandy realized that when non-violent resistance is practiced, attention is drawn to its underlying principles. “Thus education and non-violent resistance go hand in hand and help each other, step by step, towards the goal of human Freedom.” A good discussion of late 19th Century individualist-anarchist strategy will appear in the forthcoming Liberty centennial volume in the chapter by Morgan Edwards, “Neither Bombs Nor Ballots: Benjamin Tucker and the Strategy of Anarchism” (Los Angeles: by the author, 1981).

During the first half of the 20th Century, the few well known libertarians actually followed the anti-political pattern set by Spooner, Tucker, and Tandy. Albert Jay Nock’s overall attitude certainly precluded political action. In his essay “What The American Votes For”, (reprinted in Snoring as a Fine Art and Twelve Other Essays, Freeport: Books for Libraries Press, 1971) which originally appeared in The American Mercury of February 1933, Nock claims that the only time he ever voted he cast a write-in ballot for Jefferson Davis on the basis that “if we can’t have a live statesman, let us by all means have a first-class corpse” (p. 90). In his essay “Anarchist’s Progress” (reprinted in On Doing The Right Thing and Other Essays, Freeport: Books for Libraries Press, 1971, first published 1928) Nock points out why it is impossible for the best intentioned office holder not to sell out to the system: Suppose that you put a Sunday school superintendent in charge of a whorehouse. “He might trim off some of the coarser fringes of the job, …and put things in … a state of ‘outward order and decency'”, but he must run a whorehouse, or he would promptly hear from the owners. The voters elect politicians to administer the State, not to destroy it. In the final analysis, Nock thought that “great and salutary social transformations, such as in the end do not cost more than they come to, are not effected by political shifts, by movements, by programs and platforms, least of all by violent revolutions, but by sound and disinterested thinking.”

H. L. Mencken, despite his outward appearances as a newspaperman, had some rather acerbic thoughts on the political system. His book Prejudices: Fourth Series (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1924) carries two implicitly anti-political essays, “The Politician” and “On Government.” Mencken begins his analysis of the politician by pointing out the assumption of the great majority of American voters: that politicians are divided into two classes, and that one of those classes is made up of good ones. Hence the American public thinks that every time they turn one set of politicians out of office, they will get better ones in their place. But how wrong they are, as history has proved: the “primary error lies in making the false assumption that some politicians are better than others” (p. 133). Obviously they are not. “Politics, as hopeful men practice it in the world, consists mainly of the delusion that a change in form is a change in substance” (p. 227).

Frank Chodorov really got to the heart of the matter when he declared that “the state itself, regardless of its composition, is an exploitative institution” (Fugitive Essays, Selected Writings of Frank Chodorov, selected by Charles Hamilton, Indianapolis: Liberty Press, 1980, p. 91). No matter who operates a whorehouse (to use Nock’s metaphor’) still operates a whorehouse; and any class of politician, even if they call themselves libertarians, are still politicians. It makes little difference whether libertarians, socialists, Democrats, or Republicans are in office; the State is still nothing more than a criminal gang. In his essays “On Underwriting an Evil” (in Out Of Step, New York: Devin-Adair, 1962) and “If We Quit Voting” (pp.200-205 of Fugitive Essays), Chodorov advocated staying away from the polls. “Why should a self respecting citizen endorse an institution grounded in thievery?” A voter’s boycott, unlike other revolutions, but much like non-violent resistance campaigns, “calls for no organization, no violence, no war fund, and no leader to sell it out.”

Other more recent libertarians have similarly called for mass non-participation in the electoral process. Robert LeFevre engaged in lengthy correspondence with a number of Congressional representatives and senators during 1972 in an effort to determine the legitimacy of their participation in government. Drawing much on Spooner’s analysis of elected representatives, LeFevre demonstrates in his The Power of Congress (As Congress Sees It) (Los Angeles: R. S. Radford, 1976) that the theory of electoral representation has no firm basis. His correspondents could not agree “whether representatives should really be agents of their electors and varied widely in the interpretation of their own function and authority.” LeFevre contends that because of the secret ballot and the structure of our political institutions elected office holders are in fact representatives of no one. They had best all pack up and go home!

Sy Leon in his None of the Above – The Lesser of Two Evils . . . is Evil (Santa Barbara: Fabian Publishing, 1976) attacks majority rule as a violation of individual rights and opposes the political vote. Voting is wrong because it does not give individuals the right to express their true opinions about the politicians. The politicians do not dare insert “None of the Above” on the ballot for fear that no politician would be elected to office. Robert Ringer in his bestseller, Restoring the American Dream (New York: QED, 1979) cites Leon favorably and makes some telling comments about the Libertarian Party and voting in general:”When you vote for a candidate, you are voting to put someone in a position to rule the lives of your fellowman – men who either do not want that candidate to rule them or do not want anyone’ to rule them” (p. 285). “The most disconcerting thing about the Libertarian Party is that it ‘is’ a political party” (p. 288). Every political party and every politician is subject to the historical law of corruption: Power corrupts and absolute power corrupts absolutely.

Among the younger generation of contemporary libertarians, Samuel Edward Konkin III and George H. Smith have led the attack against political action. Konkin’s magazine New Libertarian and his “Movement of the Libertarian Left” have long criticized the Libertarian Party. “He who serves the Party serves the State” because it is impossible to destroy the system by joining it. Konklin’s emphasis on counter-economics and agorism, as alternatives to political strategies, is set forth in his New Libertarian Manifesto (Box 1748, Long Beach, California 90801, published 1980). Smith, too, has tried to convey the message that Politics and libertarianism are inconsistent. One of his earliest attacks on the Libertarian Party was a satirical “Victory Speech of the Libertarian Party President-Elect, 1984” which appeared in Supplement 4 of New Libertarian Weekly (no. 46, October 31, 1976). Smith tried to show why a Libertarian President would be involved in all sorts of philosophical predicaments (how would he deal with tax evaders, drug smugglers, victims of victimless crime laws, etc.?). This criticism was followed up by a seriously theoretical piece entitled Party Dialogue (New Libertarian, Vol. 4, No. 8, Dec. 1980 – Feb. 1981; and reprinted Baltimore: The Voluntaryists, 1982; see reverse of this pamphlet for ordering instructions) and by an exchange of letters to the editor between Less Antman, a well-known member of the California LP and Smith, in New Libertarian (Vol. 5, no. 9, April-June, 1981). His most recent foray against the LP occurred at the California LP Convention on board the Queen Elizabeth II in February 1982. Here he continued his debate with Antman under the title “Political Action vs. Non Political Action” in which they exchanged their views on the validity of political action for libertarians. (See Tapes 651 A and B by Liberty Audio Forum, 824 West Broad Street, Richmond, Va. 23220.) Smith’s efforts against the LP have been instrumental in the formation of The Voluntaryists, whose purpose is to spread the message that libertarianism must be propagated by non-political means.

This brings to a conclusion our survey of literature which deals with the Voluntaryist insight and the question of anti-political and non-political activity. As can be seen from the suggestions of Tucker and Tandy, non-violent resistance is a very useful tool for Voluntaryists to embrace. It is hoped that the efforts put forth in this bibliographic essay will spark libertarians to at least investigate the merits and demerits of non-violent resistance, which itself has an extensive body of literature built up around it. The findings of such a study should be of great interest to all Voluntaryists and we hope it is not long forthcoming.

In Favorem Libertatis: The Life and Work of Granville Sharp


by Carl Watner
1980

   
Libertarians, if they care to examine the subject, will discover that they have a rich historical tradition in the English and American antislavery movements. The libertarian tradition in antislavery thought may be concisely summed up: In Favorem Libertatis–In Favor of Liberty. No one familiar with this tradition could fail to identify Granville Sharp (1735-1813) as one of its first and greatest expositors and coadjutors. From the time in 1765 when he first encountered the slave Johnathan Strong, till his death, Sharp’s name was inextricably bound up with the freedom of slaves in England. Sharp was born of a religious family, being the grandson of the Archbishop of York and son of an archdeacon. His early religious training and background permeated much of his adult thinking. Since his father could not afford to attend to his education, Sharp was largely self-educated. He was apprenticed to a linen draper in London from 1750 to 1757 and then secured an appointment as a clerk in the Government Ordnance Department, where he remained employed until 1775. His early activities exemplify his wide-ranging intellectual interests, his freedom from unreasoned prejudice, and his aptitude for patient and scholarly research.

While learning his trade as a linen-draper he encountered a fellow-apprentice who happened to be a Socinian with the irritating habit of referring in religious controversies to the original Greek of the New Testament, with the admonition that Granville Sharp’s mistaken opinions arose from his lack of acquaintance with Greek. . . . Accordingly Granville Sharp learned Greek in his spare time, until he was able to argue on a more than equal footing with the Socinian. It was the same with Hebrew. A Jew, another fellow-apprentice with whom he indulged in religious controversy, whenever hard pressed by Granville Sharp’s cogent reasonings, constantly declared that he was misrepresenting the prophecies from ignorance of the Hebrew tongue in which they were written.[1]

“To be ignorant of the truth, was, to his ardent mind, a source of inexpressible pain; to neglect the means of acquiring a knowledge of it, insupportable disgrace.”[2]

Sharp’s first encounter with English law and the blacks involved the person of Johnathan Strong and commenced sometime in 1765. Strong was a young African slave, brought from Barbados by his master David Lisle. Having been seriously beaten and then abandoned by his owner, Strong sought medical help from Granville Sharp’s brother, William, a surgeon who devoted part of his time to treating the poor. Befriended and healed by the brothers, Johnathan obtained paid employment through their assistance. In September 1767, Lisle happened upon his former slave, and inasmuch as he had regained his health, Lisle was determined to have him back. Accordingly, Johnathan Strong was ensnared and kidnapped under orders from Lisle and lodged in a London jail where he awaited transport back to Jamaica by Captain Laird, who was acting on behalf of Strong’s new owner, John Kerr. As a last resort, Strong sent for Granville Sharp. The message was received on September 12, 1767 and implored “protection from being sold as a Slave.” Sharp, who did not recollect the name of Strong, went the following day to the jail and demanded to see the prisoner. The jailer denied that they had anyone named Johnathan Strong committed to their charge. This blatant lie aroused Sharp’s suspicion. “He demanded to see the keeper of the prison and insisted on seeing Johnathan Strong. He was then called.” On seeing Johnathan Strong, “Sharp immediately recollected ‘him, and enquired what he had done to be thus imprisoned. The lad said he had not been guilty of any offense whatever, but that his former master David Lisle’ had put him in prison before shipment back to the plantations. Appalled by what he heard, Granville Sharp took Johnathan’s case to court on information ‘that a Johnathan Strong had been confined in prison without any warrant.”‘ The action was heard on September 18, 1767 in the presence of the Lord Mayor, who discharged Johnathan Strong because “the lad had not stolen any thing, and was not guilty of any offense, and was therefore at liberty to go away.”[3]

A few days after the hearing Granville was served “with copies of Writs issued by James Kerr, claiming . . . damages in a plea of trespass against the Sharp brothers for depriving him of his property.” Thus as Granville wrote in his manuscript entitled “An Account of the Occasion which Compelled Granville Sharp to Study Law, and the Defense of Negro Slaves in England,” “a lawsuit commenced against him . . . for having lawfully and openly obtained the liberty of a poor injured Negro before the Chief Magistrate of the City.”[4] When sued by Kerr, Sharp consulted with his own lawyers, all of whom fell back on the joint opinion of Attorney-General Philip Yorke and Solicitor-General Charles Talbot, which was unofficially issued in 1729. Their opinion claimed that a slave, by merely coming from the West Indies to Great Britain, did not become free, and that the slave’s master might legally compel him to return to the plantations even though it was against the slave’s will. Sharp was told that his case was defenseless, particularly since Lord Mansfield, on the King’s Bench, had confirmed the Yorke and Talbot opinion several times. The lawyers implied that Sharp should save his money and leave Johnathan to his fate. “Granville noted that ‘he could not believe that the Laws of England were really so injurious to natural Rights as so many great lawyers, for political reasons had been pleased to assert.’ Since the Yorke and Talbot opinion ‘so intimidated’ the lawyers, he calmly told his lawyers that he proposed to undertake his own . . . defense.”[5] The incident at the Lord Mayor’s Court, when Captain Laird claimed Johnathan Strong as the property of Kerr by virtue of a bill of sale produced as evidence, obviously made “a deep and frightening impression on Granville Sharp.” As the remainder of his life illustrates, it is reasonably clear that it left him with a “burning desire to combat the injustice and inhumanity of slavery.”

Left without legal help and impelled by circumstances, Granville Sharp once again began the laborious study of yet another subject. He determined “to give up two or three years to the study of English law, that he might better advocate the cause” of the Negro on English soil. “The result of these studies was the publication of a book in 1769, which he called A Representation of the Injustice and Dangerous Tendency of Tolerating Slavery in England.” In it he refuted the opinion of Yorke and Talbot. He produced against it the opinion of Lord Chief Justice Holt, who had determined many years before that every slave coming into England thereby became free.

He vigorously rejected the idea of private property in a black as if in a horse or dog. This he regarded as preposterous, ‘very insufficient and defective’ claim, because the comparing of a man to a beast ‘is unnatural and unjust.’ The claim of private property was maintainable only if ‘the pretended proprietors’ could prove that a slave ‘is neither man, woman nor child’: and if they are not able to do this, how can they presume to consider such a person as a mere ‘chose in action’? or ‘thing to be demanded in action’?

Sharp contended that men are rendered obnoxious to the law by their offenses and not by their particular denomination, rank, parentage, color or country. “True justice make no respect of persons, and can never deny to any one that blessing to which all mankind have an undoubted right, their natural liberty.”[7] He also showed it to be “an axiom in the British constitution, ‘That every man in England was free to sue for and defend his rights, and that force could not be used without legal process.”‘[8] Sharp quoted Sir Edward Coke’s statement made in 1628 that, “The law favors liberty and the freedom of a man from imprisonment; and therefore kind interpretations shall be made on its behalf.” This reinforced his argument that in English law the terms “subject” and “person” referred to both black and white people and were not limited to white people only, as the Courts were prone to interpret the law.[9]

While Sharp was engaged in his studies, another case involving a Negro slave was called to his attention. This occurred in the year 1768. John Hylas and his wife Mary were black slaves born in Barbados. They were married in England in 1758, having been brought there previously by their masters. John was granted his freedom after his marriage and he lived with his wife until 1766. At this time, Mary was kidnapped by her former owners, the Newtons, and sent back to the West Indies to be sold as a slave. “And so, in 1768, over two years after his wife had been kidnapped by Newton, Hylas complained to Granville Sharp, who interested himself in the success of the cause. Armed with a memorandum prepared by Granville Sharp, Hylas commenced an action against Newton,” which was heard on December 3, 1768.[10] The result of the trial was that Newton, the owner of Hylas’ wife, was bound to bring back the woman, either by the first ship or within six months, and was judged to pay damages in the nominal amount of one shilling. The import of the decision was not that blacks gained their freedom in England, but only that as Hylas had been manumitted, he was entitled to both his own liberty and that of his wife.[11] In his manuscript account of the case, “Remarks on the Case of John Hylas and his Wife, Mary,” Sharp noted that Hylas should have been entitled to both his wife and substantial damages. “If he had a right to his wife, which cannot be denied, he most certainly had a right to damages also, in consideration of the violent and unpardonable outrage committed against himself in the person of his wife, for which no pecuniary allowance whatsoever can really make amends.”[12] Sharp charged the court with doing a manifest injustice to Hylas, “who is as much entitled to 500 pounds damages, at the least, besides treble the costs, by this Act, as the first lawyer of the kingdom would be, if he should lose his wife in the same manner.” Despite his plea for justice, Granville Sharp was alone. The courts and the lawyers were convinced that the Habeas Corpus Act (upon which Sharp based his legal action) did not have blacks in mind.[13] To Sharp the matter was clear: on the plainest and most literal interpretation of the laws of England, blacks were entitled to liberty and freedom in England.[14]

Shortly after the publication of his work in 1769, Sharp was solicited to assist in procuring another writ of habeas corpus for a kidnapped Negro, Thomas Lewis. Lewis was seized by watermen in the dark of the night on July 2, 1770 and put on board a ship bound for Jamaica, where it was intended that he be sold as a slave. His former master, Robert Stapylton, had engineered the kidnapping. Sharp eventually obtained a habeas corpus, and just in time, as the ship on which Lewis was confined was making ready to sail from port. Following the rescue, Sharp began criminal proceedings for assault on behalf of Lewis against Stapylton and the two watermen who had assisted him.[15] Stapylton defended himself with the plea “that Lewis belonged to him as a slave.” In the course of the criminal trial, John Dunning, counsel for Lewis, paid Sharp a handsome compliment, for he held in his hand Sharp’s hook on the injustice and dangerous tendency of tolerating slavery in England while he was pleading that he was prepared to maintain in any of the courts in Great Britain, that “no man can be legally detained as a slave in this country.”[16] Lord Mansfield directed the jury to find Stapylton guilty if they found that Lewis was not his slave. In February 1771 the jury decided against Stapylton and showed that they thought Lewis was not his property. In spite of the guilty verdict, Stapylton suffered no punishment for his crime since Lord Mansfield repeatedly refused to render a sentence against him.[17]

This contempt of justice disturbed Sharp, even though he had secured the legal freedom of other Negroes. Not one of these cases had been pleaded on the broad ground of the question of “whether an African slave coming into England became free?” This great question had been avoided by the judiciary, especially Lord Mansfield, and legally it was still in doubt.[18] Sharp was desirous of having a case argued and decided on the basis of general principles and it was the case of Somerset v. Stewart that answered his wish. The facts in Somerset v. Stewart are clear-cut. Lord Mansfield in his summary of the case put them as follows:

That James Somerset, is a Negro of Africa, and long before the return of the King’s writ was brought to be sold, and was sold to Mr. Charles Stewart, Esq. then in Jamaica, and has not been manumitted since; that Mr. Stewart, having occasion to transact business, came over hither, with an intention to return; and brought Somerset, to attend and abide with him, and to carry him back as soon as the business should be transacted. That such intention has been, and still continues; and that the Negro did remain till the time of his departure, in the service of his master Mr. Stewart, and quitted it without his consent; and thereupon, before the return of the King’s writ, the said Charles Stewart did commit the slave on board the “Ann and Mary,” to save custody, to be kept till he should set sail, and then to be taken with him to Jamaica, and there sold as a slave. And this is the cause why he, Captain Knowles, who was then and now is, commander of the above vessel, then and now lying in the river of Thames, did the said Negro, committed to his custody, detain; and on which he now renders him to the orders of the Court.[19]

The chronology of the events was that both Stewart and his slave, Somerset, arrived in England in November 1769. Prior to their scheduled return in early October 1771, Somerset left his master, Stewart. The master then seized his slave and placed him on board ship for safekeeping on November 26, 1771. The godparents of Somerset obtained a writ of habeas corpus on November 28, 1771, and it was they who initially interceded on Somerset’s behalf.

Sharp was soon involved in the case. He recorded on January 13, 1772 that “James Somerset, a Negro from Virginia, called on me this morning to complain of Mr. Charles Stewart. I gave him the best advice I could.” Sharp also contributed towards the expense of retaining counsel for Somerset. “Money,” he said, “has no value but when well spent; and I am thoroughly convinced that no part of my little pittance of ready money can ever be better bestowed than in an honest endeavor to crush a growing oppression, which is not only shocking to humanity, but in time must prove even dangerous to the community.”[29] Sharp quickly printed an “Appendix” to his Injustice of Tolerating Slavery. The “Appendix” hinted at Mansfield’s previous contemptuous behavior in the Lewis case and forthrightly declared that there was no reason for judicial hesitation nor delay in granting “relief and discharge of a poor innocent man from an unlawful imprisonment and unjust oppression”:

When a Notorious Outrage and Breach of the Peace is committed under the pretence of any such groundless claim of service, the Magistrate who neglects to relieve the person oppressed, and to punish the Offenders, is certainly a partaker of their Guilt; and no upright and conscientious Judge (who does not set his own will above the laws of the Land) can possibly entertain any doubt in his mind about the punishment of such Offenders; for when the Laws of the Land, and especially the Habeas Corpus Act, are expressly and clearly on one Side of the Question (without the least exception whatever concerning any difference or distinction of Persons), and when the only plea on the other side of the Question is absolutely without foundation either in Natural Equity or the established Law and Customs of this country, what room can there be for doubt? and how would a Judge be able to justify an Arrest of Judgment in such a case? . . . A Doubt is certainly a very insufficient excuse for an arrest of Judgment, in any case whatever, unless “strong and probable Grounds” are allowed to justify it; hut a groundless doubt upon the present question would he more particularly criminal; because it would, probably, tend to the introduction of the diabolical Tyranny and Injustice of our West Indian Colonies, whereby human Nature is villifyed and delegated to the rank and level of brute Beasts . . . into this kingdom: which, added to the manifold corruptions and depravities into which this Kingdom has already fallen, will certainly cause our measure of Iniquity to overflow, and, in all probability, draw down upon us some dreadful and speedy national calamity, besides that severe judgment, which is already too apparent amongst us, I mean the deplorable Hardness of Heart, and abandoned Spirit of Injustice, which has rendered publication of this remonstrance necessary.[21]

“All the Court had to decide was whether Stewart had the right, which he claimed as the owner of Somerset, to remove him by force and against his will out of England and consign him to slavery in the plantations.”[22]

To represent Somerset, Sharp obtained some of the most eminent legal counsel of his day: Serjeants William Davy and John Glynn, and barristers James Mansfield, Francis Hargrave, and Mr. Alleyne. On the other side, representing Stewart and the West Indies Interest were William Wallace and John Dunning, who had represented the slave Lewis the previous year. Hargrave, young and unknown, contributed his own time to the case and after the conclusion of the hearings published his book, An Argument in the Case of James Somerset, a Negro, Lately Determined by the Court of the King’s Bench: Wherein It Is Attempted to Demonstrate the Present unlawfulness of Domestic Slavery in England. To Which Is Prefixed, A State of the Case (1772).[21]

Hargrave adopted several lines of reasoning suggested by Sharp. He opened his argument by declaring, “The question . . . is not whether slavery is lawful in the colonies, but whether [it is lawful] in England? Not whether it ever has existed in England; but whether it be not now abolished?”[24] Hargrave argued that the only form of slavery ever countenanced by English law was that of villenage (a feudal status) and that by 1770 that institution had been defunct for well over a century. He further argued that slavery was antithetical to other parts of English law, pointing out that the English law of contracts would not permit an individual to enslave himself and his posterity for their lifetimes. If the law of England would not permit a man to bind himself by contract to service for life, even when the parties were willing, then how could it ever sanctify the condition of a slave, who is coerced against his will? Hargrave questioned, “In England, where freedom is the grand object of the laws, and dispensed to the meanest individual, shall the laws of an infant colony, Virginia, or a barbarous nation, Africa, prevail?” He maintained that the Negro, while in England, was duty bound to submit to English law, and that therefore he has a right to claim the protection of English law. Hargrave concluded his brief by stating his belief that Mr. Stewart’s claim was opposed to “natural justice” and inconsistent “with the laws of England.”

Another argument for Somerset was that the laws of Virginia could not be used to sanction slavery in England. Serjeant Davy contended that the toleration of slavery in the colonies was merely local in character and wholly dependent on colonial law. An English court “was bound to apply its own law–the law of England–which is the lex situs and the proper law.” According to Davy, and echoing Hargrave and Sharp, “All the people who come into this country immediately become subject to the laws of this country, are governed by the laws, regulated entirely in their whole conduct by the laws, and are entitled to the protection of the laws of this country, and become the King’s subjects.” Davy points out that this man, Somerset, “remains, ‘upon his arrival in England, in the condition he was abroad, in Virginia or not. If he does so remain, the master’s power remains as before. If the laws, having attached upon him abroad, are at all to affect him here, it brings them all: either all the laws of Virginia are to attach upon him here, or none,–for where will they draw the line?”[26]

The arguments for Somerset were concluded by Mr. Alleyne. He laid it down as “an unimpeachable proposition that all municipal relations which were repugnant to natural law, ceased to operate the moment the persons affected by them were out of the state in which they were made.” In Alleyne’s consideration, the state of slavery was such a municipal relation which violated natural law, so that although the laws of Virginia might establish slavery there, they could never establish slavery in England. “The laws of Virginia extend to Virginia alone.”[27] He focused attention on the subject of the case, James Somerset, who was there in the English court. Said Alleyne, “This man is here: he owes submission to the laws of England, and he claims the protection of those laws; and as he ceases to be a citizen of Virginia, and stands in no such relation now to Mr. Stewart, so he is certainly not bound to him; and therefore he stands, like any other man in the kingdom, entitled to his freedom.”[28]

Mr. Wallace, the junior counsel for Stewart, opened his submission for the slaveholder by pointing out that slavery was found in more than three-quarters of the world and that this proved how widespread a practice it was. He argued that it would be unjust and absurd to divest Stewart of his property in Somerset only because he sailed in pursuit of his lawful business from one country to another. By implication, he held that the laws of Virginia, by which Somerset was a slave, must be recognized in England. Since there was no law in the West Indies or in the Northern Colonies or in England by which slavery was directly prohibited, he could not understand how or why slavery should be unlawful in those places. There was no “positive law. . . against it.”[29] He raised the question of the inconvenience and, especially, the loss of value in the slaves which English masters would suffer, should Somerset be set free. His final argument rested on the comparison of a slave to the status of an English servant. He reasoned that private force which an English master of that era might use against his servant to correct error was the equivalent of the force by which a master held his slave.

Mr. John Dunning was the senior counsel for the defendant and was in a very delicate situation. Only a year before, he had pleaded for the freedom of Thomas Lewis by declaring that no property could exist in a slave in England. Trying to extricate himself from this about-face, he said, “I am bound by duty to maintain those arguments which are useful to Captain Knowles (and Mr. Stewart) as far as are consistent with truth, and if his conduct has been agreeable to the laws throughout, I am under a further indispensable duty to support it.”[30] Dunning had little to add to Wallace’s arguments, but he did note that earlier English decisions, which the plaintiffs attorneys used to support their case, did not destroy the Negro’s obligation to serve his master. According to Dunning, Somerset was in a condition of servitude when he left Africa and the British legislature had merely confirmed him in that condition.

Lord Mansfield also found himself in trying circumstances. As Chief Justice, he had to interpret the law regardless of his personal views and regardless of the possible consequences of his decision. Prior to announcing his decision in the case, he summed up his views of the issues:

The question is, if the owner had a right to detain the slave, for the sending of him over to be sold in Jamaica. In five or six cases of this nature, I have known it to be accommodated by agreement between the parties: on its first coming before me, I strongly recommended it here. But if the parties will have it decided, we must give our opinion. Compassion will not, on the one hand, nor inconvenience on the other, be to decide; but the law . . . . Contract for sale of a slave is good here; the sale is a matter to which the law properly and readily attaches, and will maintain the price according to the agreement. But here the person of the slave himself is immediately the object of inquiry; which makes a very material difference. The question now is, whether any dominion, authority or coercion can be exercised in this country, on a slave according to the American laws? . . . Mr. Stewart advances no claim on contract; he rests his whole demand on a right to the negro as slave, and mentions the purpose of detainure to be the sending of him over to be sold in Jamaica. If the parties will have judgment, fiat justitia, ruat coelum, let justice be done whatever the consequence. . . . We cannot in any of these points direct the law; the law must rule us.[31]

On June 22, 1772, Lord Mansfield delivered his final opinion in Somerset v. Stewart:

The only question before us is, whether the cause on the return is sufficient? If it is, the negro must be remanded; if it is not, he must he discharged. Accordingly, the return states, that the slave departed and refused to serve; whereupon he was kept, to be sold abroad. So high an act of dominion must he recognized by the law of the country where it is used. The power of a master over his slave has been extremely different, in different countries. The state of slavery is of such a nature, that it is incapable of being introduced on any reasons, moral or political; but only positive law, which preserves its force long after the reasons, occasion, and time itself from whence it was created, is erased from memory: it’s so odious, that nothing can be suffered to support it, but positive law. Whatever inconveniences, therefore, may follow from a decision, I cannot say this case is allowed or approved by the law of England; and therefore the black must be discharged.[32]

Technically considered, the judgment “settled only two narrow points of English law.” A master could not seize his slave and remove him from the country against his will. And a slave could secure a writ of habeas corpus to prevent that removal.[33] Regardless of the claims of historians, the case did not legally declare slaves free when they landed in England, nor did it abolish slavery there. Even after the decision, blacks were still hunted and kidnapped in the streets of English cities. What Mansfield declared was that there was no positive law enforcing slavery in England and that when the actions of slave masters were contrary to the Habeas Corpus Act, the slaves might rely on the Act itself for legal relief.

Sharp took a quiet pride in the decision. He noted on the day that it was given that, “This day, James Somerset came to tell me that judgment was today given in his favor. Somerset was the last Negro whom G[ranville] S[harp] brought before Lord Mansfield by writ of habeas corpus; when his Lordship declared, as the opinion of all the Judges present, that the power claimed by the master ‘never was in use here, nor acknowledged by the law; and, therefore the man James Somerset must be discharged.’ Thus ended G. Sharp’s long contest with Lord Mansfield on the 22nd of June 1772.”[34]

Sharp had waged a long “uphill battle” in obtaining Lord Mansfield’s decision. In the course of his struggle, Sharp lost whatever faith he may have had in the legal profession. First, the practitioners had claimed his outlook on the law of slavery was futile and faulty. They had advised against offering any defense at all in the case of Johnathan Strong. Then he had employed Dunning to defend Lewis, after which Dunning pleaded the case of the slaveholder, Stewart. Of Dunning’s behavior on behalf of two mutually contradictory causes, Sharp wrote, “This is an abominable and insufferable practice in lawyers, to undertake causes diametrically opposite to their own declared opinions of law and common justice.”[35] William Blackstone, the author of The Commentaries on the Laws of England, written in 1765, also changed his opinion on the law of slavery in England during the course of Sharp’s struggle in the Courts. In the beginning of his research, Sharp had found and noted the following passage in Blackstone’s commentaries: “And this spirit of liberty is so deeply implanted in our constitution, and rooted even in our very soil, that a Slave, or Negro, the moment he lands in England, falls under the protection of the laws, and with regard to all national rights, becomes eo instanti a freeman.” In his second and third editions of 1766 and 1768, Blackstone altered this passage: “A Negro, the moment he lands in England, falls under the protection of the laws, and so far becomes a freeman; though the master’s right to his service may possibly still continue.”[36] In private correspondence with Sharp, Blackstone went so far as to request that Sharp not cite the passage “from my first edition as decisive in favor of your Doctrine.”[37]

In 1783, Sharp became involved in another court case concerned with the issue of slaves as property. The case of the slave-ship Zong, officially cataloged as Gregson v. Gilbert, involved the loss of 132 slaves, all of whom were thrown overboard by the crew of the Zong. Gregson and other members of his Liverpool mercantile firm owned the Zong and sued their underwriters for the value of the slaves, who had been insured as common merchandise or cargo. According to the policy, the underwriters would not be liable if the slaves perished of a natural death, such as sickness; they would be held liable if it were proven that the slaves had been jettisoned out of necessity. The pretense of throwing the slaves overboard was that there had been an acute shortage of water aboard ship, which jeopardized the other slaves and crew. Nevertheless, the evidence proved that the captain, Luke Collingwood, had taken no efforts to ration water supplies.

The underwriters defended their position by arguing that there had been no need for conduct so shocking to humanity, that the water situation might have been alleviated by a port call, and that, in fact, the Zong still carried at least a five-day supply of water when she finally docked. The chiefmate, John Kelsal, testified that at first he opposed the captain’s orders, but that on second thought he had decided that they were sufficient enough authority for throwing the slaves overboard–without considering whether such an action was criminal or not. Sharp was not aware of the case until near the end of the civil trial. He immediately took steps to insure that accurate records of the proceedings be kept, and he initiated legal action to see that the murderers be punished. He corresponded, without success however, with the Lords Commissioners of the Admiralty because the “right of inquiry concerning all murders committed on board British ships, belongs properly to the Admiralty department.” Sharp also contacted other high-placed officials and prominent clergymen in an effort to seek their assistance in prosecuting the crew members of the Zong. Although the Admiralty took no action, Sharp must be given much of the credit for publicizing the case in public and governmental circles. Sharp’s call for punishment was doomed because law and public opinion in 18th-century England still did not regard the African as a human being. In the eyes of most Englishmen, they were chattels or property, and the insurers were bound to pay for their loss.[38]

Sharp prepared an essay for distribution entitled “An Account of the Murder of One Hundred and Thirty-Two . . . Slaves on Board the Ship Zong.” Invoking both natural and divine law, Sharp attacked on two fronts. First he denied that there was any case for pleading “necessity” in the death of the slaves; and even if there were grounds for such a plea, he thought the plea of necessity was never a sufficient excuse for the murder of innocent slaves. Secondly, he disputed that slaves lost their claim to humanity just because they were slaves. Sharp pointed out that the supposed property in the persons of the slaves was a very limited kind of property, limited by the inevitable consideration of their human nature. Consequently, the property of the injured Africans in their own lives, despite their status as slaves, was infinitely superior to any claim of the slave dealers. The indispensable point under consideration was that the act of jettison was “the case of throwing over living men: and that, notwithstanding they are, in one sense, unhappily considered as goods or chattels (to the eternal disgrace of this nation!), yet they are still men; that their existence in human nature, and their natural rights as men, nay as brethren, still remains!”[39] Sharp’s commentary on the inexcusable plea of necessity probably remains unique in the history of English law: Thus one hundred and thirty-two innocent human persons were wilfully put to a violent death, not on account of any mutiny or insurrection, nor even through the fear of any such, . . . but merely on a pretended plea of necessity through want of water. . . So that, even if the plea of necessity for the wilful murder of the innocent persons was at all admissable (which it can never be) in a case of want or scarcity, yet no such necessity existed in the present case; because it is proved, even by their own evidence, that the stock of water was sufficient to have held out till the time that an ample supply was actually received.–But there can never be a necessity for the wilful murder of an innocent man, notwithstanding the high authority of those learned and dignified persons who seem to have conceived a contrary idea, because wilful murder is one of the worst evils that happen among men; so that the plea of a necessity to destroy a few men in order to save many, is not only the adoption of a declared damnable doctrine (“Let us do evil that good may come!”), which is extreme wickedness, but is also extreme ignorance; for it is obvious that the death of many by misfortune, which is properly in the hand of Divine Providence, is not near so great an evil as the murder of a few, or even of one innocent man–the former being the loss only of temporal lives, but the latter endangers the eternal souls, not only of the miserable aggressors themselves, but the souls of all their indiscriminate abettors and favourers. God’s vengeance is so clearly denounced against wilful murder, that it is certainly a malum in se of the most flagrant and odious nature, such as cannot, without extreme ignorance of the English common law, be admitted as a legal justification. . . . And therefore, whenever a man wilfully takes the life of an innocent man on pretense of necessity to save his own, in any case where se-defendendo will not hold (which requires proof of an actual attack by the deceased, who therefore is not an innocent man), . . . such a man, I say, is guilty of a felonious homicide.[40]

“The extraordinarily cruel nature of the Zong case furnished the anti-slavery crusade with a powerful, and almost unanswerable argument” in their favor.[41] Sharp was active in other antislavery activities as well. In June 1787, he was invited to cooperate with other English abolitionists to form the Committee for Effecting an Abolition of the Slave-Trade. Here he associated with Clarkson, Wilberforce, and others, whose immediate aim was to mitigate and abolish the slave trade and eventually to outlaw slavery itself. Of the ten people in the founding group, Sharp alone stood for including the abolition of slavery, per se, in the title of their society. For he feared that “the vast object of his benevolence–the abolition of slavery throughout the world,” might be “compromised by subordinate measures. . . . As slavery was as much a crime against the Divine Laws as the Slave-Trade, it became the Committee to exert themselves equally against the continuance of both; and he did not hesitate to pronounce all present guilty before God for shutting those, who were then slaves all the world over, out of the pale of their approaching labors.”[42] Finding himself unable to influence those present, “he felt satisfied that he had delivered his testimony against the proceedings which circumscribed them, and from that hour proved himself thoroughly desirous to aid, to his utmost ability, the part which he found could be undertaken with greater and more general consent.” It is worthy of note that during this same decade, Sharp was also devoting his energies to the establishment of a colony in Africa, which was to be settled by freed English Negroes. Although Sierra Leone was eventually to become a government project, Sharp was one of its earliest and most persistent advocates and organizers.

Sharp was, above all, his own man and was not about to betray his conscience for any reason whatsoever. He forcefully emphasized this point in an undated letter:

I look on myself to be perfectly independent, because I have never yet been afraid to do and avow whatever I thought just and right, without the consideration of consequences to myself: for, indeed, I think it unworthy of a man to be afraid of the world; and it is a point with me, never to conceal my sentiments on any subject whatever, not even from my superiors in office, when there is a probability of answering any good purpose by it.”[43]

Sharp was sympathetic to the position of the American colonists, and when armed hostilities broke out he was in a trying situation. He had been an employee of the Government Ordnance Department since 1758. In 1775, when demands were made for munitions from his department, he made his opposition to royal intervention in the colonies known and requested a leave of absence from his position. In September 1775, he wrote that he could not “return to my ordnance duty whilst a bloody war is carried on, unjustly as I conceive it, against my fellow-subjects; and yet, to resign my place would be to give up a calling, which, by my close attendance to it for near 18 years, and by my neglect of every other means of subsistence during so long a period, is now become my only profession and livelihood.”[44] When no end to the hostilities appeared in sight, Sharp formally resigned his clerkship. Meanwhile, he had determined to engage in his own private diplomacy in an effort to negotiate a peaceful settlement of the dispute between the colonists and the King and Parliament. From 1777 almost until the end of the war, he was engaged in lobbying for American representation in Parliament. He hoped that the North American colonists might put down their arms were they to obtain such representation.

Sharp’s “noble and incessant labors in the best causes, the preservation of the rights of mankind,” were noted as early as 1770, by another English radical, John Wilkes.[45] His political philosophy was bound by the maxim that “Honesty is the best policy”:

That excellent adage for all the ordinary circumstances of life, viz., “Honesty the best Policy,” will be found to hold equally good in politics or affairs of government, even throughout the most dangerous and alarming difficulties. . . . An administration which cannot subsist with law, justice, and common honesty is unjust to subsist at all because law is the only basis of good and lawful government.[46]

In spite of his liberal tendencies, Sharp was illiberal to Roman Catholics, who he believed already had sufficient privileges in England. Though a religious man, he bore the most implacable hatred towards their religion.[47]

Nevertheless, in many ways he was ahead of his time, as the lengthy list of his pamphlets and books illustrates. As a citizen of England in the days of pocket boroughs and rotten districts, he published a series of pamphlets urging a more equal system of representation, universal adult suffrage, and more frequent parliaments.[48] He wrote in favor of The People’s Natural Right to a Share in the Legislature: Against the Attempts to Tax America and to Make Laws for Her Against Her Consent (1774). Sharp opposed standing armies and wrote a series of severe tracts on “Free Militia,” among which were included The Ancient Common Law Right of Associating with the Vicinage to Maintain the Peace (1780). and A General Militia, Acting by Rotation, Is the Only Safe Means of Defending a Free People (1780). He wrote against the prevailing practice of dueling in his Remarks on the Opinions of Some of the Most Celebrated Writers on Crown Law, Respecting the Distinction Between Manslaughter and Murder (1773).

This last work reflects Sharp’s scholarly and legal abilities. He attempted to show that “the plea of sudden anger cannot remove the imputation of guilt of murder, when a mortal wound is wilfully given with a weapon,” as in the case of a duel. It was his opinion that “No Man can give or accept a challenge to fight with weapons, on any private difference whatever, without being guilty of wilful murder if he kills his antagonist.”[50] Sharp reasoned that:

When two persons fight with dangerous weapons an intention of killing is expressed by the weapons; and such intention renders the manslaughter voluntary, which is the same thing as wilful. . . . For if the killing be voluntary, the evil and malicious intention is necessarily included in the act, . . . for a voluntary striking, without an intention to kill, is indeed pardonable, though death ensues; but a voluntary killing (where murderous weapons imply the intention to kill) . . . must, necessarily, be esteemed Murder.[51]

Sharp attributed the propensity for dueling, especially among military men, to a false sense of honor and pride. He berated the military men as well as the professors of law for their misunderstanding of the law, but he asserted that

Gentlemen of the Army are not obliged, indeed, to acquire a critical knowledge of the Law, but they must not forget that they are Men, as well as Soldiers: and that if they do not maintain the Natural Privilege of Men, (viz. that of thinking for themselves, and acting agreeable to the Dictates of their own conscience, as Members of the Community), they are unfit for British Soldiers, of whom the Law requires an acknowledgment for her supremacy. For the Law will not excuse an unlawful Act by a Soldier, even though he commits it by the express Command of the highest military Authority in the Kingdom: and much less is the Soldier obliged to conform himself implicitly to the mere opinions and false Notions of Honor, which his Superiors may have unfortunately adopted. . . . The Law manifestly requires the Soldier to think for himself; and to consider, before he acts in any war, whether the same be just; for, if it be otherwise, the Common Law of this Kingdom will impute to him the Guilt of Murder.”[52]

In 1778, Sharp published An Address to the People of England: Being the Protest of a Private Person Against Every Suspension of Law that Is Liable to Injure or Endanger Personal Security. This book expresses as well as any of his other writings his views on government and politics. The compendium or sum total of his politics was:

I am thoroughly convinced that right ought to be adopted and maintained on all occasions, without regard to the consequences either probable or possible; for these (when we have done our own duty as honest men) must, after all, be left to the disposal of Divine Providence.[53]

In Sharp’s view, “It was better to endure all adversities than to assent to one evil measure; it was better that ten offenders should escape penal justice than one innocent man should suffer by denial or suspension of common right.”[54] No government could ever be justified in suspending the law, even in times of national emergencies. “There never can be any necessity for injustice,” wrote Sharp. “No necessity, therefore, whatever, can justify the adoption of an unrighteous or unjust measure, by any legislature upon earth.”[55]

Part of Sharp’s Address was directed against the practice of impressing seamen, which was conducted by the Royal Navy. Pressing was a form of involuntary conscription by which the Navy seized Englishmen and forced them on board ships where they were made to serve as sailors. Sharp had been employed to help obtain a writ of habeas corpus to secure the freedom of Millachip, a freeman of London, who had been kidnapped by a press gang in 1777. He described the practice of pressing as “a warrant to take a man by force, to drag him away, like a thief, to a floating prison (the most dangerous and detestable of them all); that, by imprisonment and duress he may be compelled to enter into an involuntary servitude.”[56] Sharp claimed that pressing the poorer and seafaring elements of the citizenry was intolerable and that no such thing as common rights (applicable to all men) could exist where this was the case.[57] Those engaged in the press gang and those enforcing the press warrants in court were criminal and acting contrary to the King’s Peace. Those who resisted the press officers, Sharp maintained, were acting legally, in defense of their own freedom and against unjust violence. And such resisters must not be “deemed guilty of murder even if they kill the assailants, provided the killing be inevitable in their defense; and that they cannot otherwise maintain their rights.–Nay men are not only justified in defending themselves with force and arms but may also legally defend and rescue any other persons whatever that is attacked or oppressed by unlawful violence.”[58]

Sharp’s role in the history of liberty in England seems easily assured. He was both a writer and an activist; he was willing to go to court to prove his theories, and in many cases he was successful. In the case of the African Negro he determined upon a plan of action and devoted a considerable portion of his time, energy and talents toward procuring their freedom. His life, in the words of his first biographer, was the example of the inestimable “value of a single step of virtue.”[59] If his charitable virtuousness had not brought him into contact with Johnathan Strong, his life may have been spent in other directions. That small step led to his early actions on behalf of the distressed Negro, which led to his study of law, and which eventually led to the abolition of the slave-trade and finally of slavery in England. Once Sharp had convinced himself that some cause needed his help, no consideration of the difficulties or magnitude of his task would deter him.[60] “All times were, in his estimation, the proper times for pursuing what was right to be done, and no time so particularly proper as the present instant.”[61] Such was the man and his life.

Sharp represents a tradition extending back to the Magna Carta of 1215, which provided that “no freemen should be killed, imprisoned, or disseised except by lawful judgment of his peers or by the law of the land.” During the reign of Edward III (in the mid-1300’s) Parliament bad revised the “law of the land” provisions by extending the Magna Carta’s applicability to all men, not just freemen: “no man of whatever estate or condition that he be, shall be put out of land or tenement, nor taken nor imprisoned, nor disinherited, nor put to death without being brought in answer by due process of law.” The Habeas Corpus Act of 1679 “explicitly extended the prosecution of the Great Writ to ‘Any person or persons.’”[62] Sharp argued that these provisions gave all persons in England a statutory right to contest their restraint through the courts. He believed that the Great Writ affirmed the natural right of all men and women to their own freedom and that the same principles of natural law and English Common Law applied to all people, regardless of their color or status. “Liberty was his darling object.”[63] He was an extreme votary of the habeas corpus writ.

The motivation of any great libertarian must be a passion for justice, which Sharp definitely embodied. He thus represents a strong link in the historic chain of English liberty, extending as it does from the Magna Carta, through medieval Parliaments, to the Bill of Rights and the Habeas Corpus Act. That chain of history has linked itself to the American Revolution of the 18th century, the antislavery movements of the 19th century, and the libertarian movement of the 20th century.

NOTES

1. F.O. Shyllon, Black Slaves in Britain (London: Oxford University Press, 1974). p. 29. This is the best full-length study of Sharp, drawing on his private papers.

2. Prince Hoare, Memoirs of Granville Sharp, 2nd ed., (London: Henry Colburn, 1828). 1:44. This is the first biography of Sharp.

3. Shyllon, Black Slaves, p. 21.

4. The last quotation appears in Sharp’s The Case of James and Granville Sharp, As Far As They Are Concerned with James Kerr, Esq. See Shyllon, Black Slaves, p. 22.

5. Ibid., pp. 22-23.

6. See Thomas Clarkson, The History of the Rise, Progress, and Accomplishment of the Abolition of the African Slave-Trade by the British Parliament (London: R. Taylor & Co., 1808; reprinted., London: Frank Cass & Co., 1968). p. 71. Clarkson’s is a broad, general account of the anti-slavery crusade in England. written by a young contemporary of Sharp.

7. Shyllon, Black Slaves, pp. 31-33.

8. Clarkson, African Slave-Trade, p. 72.

9. Shyllon, Black Slaves, pp. 33-34.

10. Ibid., p. 41.

11. Ibid.

12. Ibid., p. 42.

13. Ibid.

14. Ibid., p. 43.

15. Ibid., p. 45.

16. Clarkson, African Slave-Trade, p. 74; Hoare, Memoirs, 1:81-82.

17. Hoare, Memoirs, 1:92.

18. Clarkson, African Slave-Trade, p. 76.

19. Cappel Lofft, 98 English Reprints, 510.

20. Shyllon, Black Slaves, p. 125.

21. Ibid., p. 127.

22. Ibid., pp. 125-126.

23. Ibid., p. 85.

24. Lofft, English Reprints, pp. 499-500.

25. Ibid., p. 501.

26. Shyllon, Black Slaves, pp. 91-92.

27. Ibid., p. 99.

28. Ibid., p. 100.

29. Lofft, English Reprints, p. 503.

30. Ibid., p. 504.

31. Ibid., p. 508.

32. Ibid., p. 510.

33. See William M. Wiecek, “Somerset: Lord Mansfield and the Legitimacy of Slavery in the Anglo-American World,” University of Chicago Law Review 42 (Fall 1974): 87.

34. Hoare, Memoirs, 1:137.

35. Ibid., p. 132.

36. Ibid., 137-38. Reprinted from William Blackstone, The Commentaries on the Laws of England, 1st ed. (1765), bk. I, p. 123; 2nd ed. (1766), 3rd ed. (1768).

37. Shyllon, Black Slaves, pp. 66-67.

38. Ibid., pp. 192-97.

39. Ibid., p. 196.

40. Ibid., pp. 194-97.

41. See Robert Weisbord, “The Case of the Slave-Ship ‘Zong,’ 1783,” History Today 19 (August 1969): 567.

42. Hoare, Memoirs, 2:234-35.

43. Ibid., 1:100.

44. Ibid., 1:185-86.

45. Shyllon, Black Slaves, p. 137.

46. Granville Sharp, An Address to the People of England (London: 1778), p. 74. (Copy from Duke University Library.)

47. Shyllon, Black Slaves, p. 138.

48. Ibid.

49. Sharp, Remarks on Crown Law (London: B. White & R. Horsfield, 1773), title page. (Copy from Library of Congress.)

50. Ibid., p. vi.

51. Ibid., pp. xii-xiv.

52. Ibid., pp. 66-68.

53. Hoare, Memoirs, 1:l01.

54. Sharp, Address, pp. 33, 44.

55. Ibid., p. 46.

56. Ibid., p. 57.

57. Ibid., pp. 64-65.

58. Ibid., p. 71.

59. Hoare, Memoirs, 2:269.

60. See E. C. P. Lascelles, Granville Sharp and the Freedom of Slaves in England (London: Oxford University Press, 1928), p. 136.

61. Hoare, Memoirs, 2:323.

62. Wiecek, “Somerset,” p. 97

63. Hoare, Memoirs, 2:384

“All Mankind Is One”: The Libertarian Tradition In Sixteenth Century Spain


by Carl Watner
1987

[This article appeared in Volume 8, THE JOURNAL OF LIBERTARIAN STUDIES (Summer 1987), pp. 293-309.]

It would probably be looked upon as unusual to associate sixteenth century Spain with the libertarian tradition. However, during that time there arose a school of natural law thinkers and activists who espoused a universal ethic of freedom, which they saw as applicable to all mankind. Sixteenth century Spain was the golden age of Spanish culture and humanism. Unlike other European countries of that age, the Spaniards were vitally concerned with the moral problems of conquest, conversion, and the government of heathen peoples.[1] What constituted justice and how it could be achieved were everywhere concerns of the Spanish theologians, jurists, and statesmen. To these Spaniards, the basis for the just title by which they ruled the Indies was a palpable question through much of the sixteenth century.[2] Although the Spanish natural law thinkers never truly broke outside the feudal-statist mentality of their culture to become anarchists, they did elaborate a doctrine of natural rights based on both divine and human reasoning. In a very broad way, and using very typical libertarian logic, they elucidated a proprietary theory of justice by which they denounced the violent invasion and conquest of the New World and supported the rights of the native inhabitants. This was one of the greatest attempts the world has ever seen to make natural law precepts prevail in relations between peoples. Such was the Spanish concern for justice in its colonizing efforts, that its monarchs organized several major inquiries into the methods used to extend their empire. Spain is probably one of the few nations that, after having searched its “royal” conscience in light of natural law and Christian teachings, ever revised its colonial policy in order to correct and punish abuses.[3]

Within the context of the libertarian tradition, natural law is an ethic that is applicable to all mankind. When libertarians think of freedom, they think in terms of all men, women, and children being free from the coercive interference of other persons.[4] Libertarians extend freedom to everyone. “All mankind is one”–in the libertarian sense that all people have individual rights, regardless of their age, sex, religion, geographical location or other particulars.[5] Such rights are derived from the fact of their bodily existence, which implies the existence of a self-ownership and homesteading axiom. The vitality and brilliance of the sixteenth century Spanish jurists was that they were objective and logical enough to apply these principles to the Indians of the New World, even when it meant going against the vested interests of the Spanish Crown. They could have become apologists for government intervention, justifying enslavement, forced labor, and illegitimate property titles in the land violently wrested from the Indians. Well-known European advocates, such as Ginés de Sepúdveda and other Spanish imperialists, actually defended the Conquest. Yet others, such as Francisco de Vitoria, Domingo de Soto, and Bartolomé de las Casas, fought for and established the rights of the natives on the basis of their having a common human name with Europeans. These men displayed a keen insight into the essentials of justice and right, based on the scholastic writings of earlier centuries.[6] Without exception, all the Spanish theological-jurists “defended the doctrine that all men are equally free; on the basis of natural Liberty, they proclaimed their right to life, to culture, and to property.”[7]

The Spanish colonial enterprise was unique in world history because it rested on a theological-juridical foundation which gave a special character to the Laws of Burgos, the Laws of the Indies, the Conquest, and the Christianization of America. The principal architect of the Spanish theological science was St. Thomas Aquinas (1225?-1274), and the followers of St. Thomas were particularly well represented in Spain by members of the Dominican order.[8] The first Dominican missionaries arrived in the New World in 1510, intent upon carrying out the late Queen Isabella’s hopes of converting and civilizing the Indians. When they personally witnessed the violence and outrages being committed by the Spaniards and conquistadores upon the natives, their consciences compelled them to speak out against such abuses. After mature deliberation, the small Dominican community on the island of Hispaniola decided to voice its protest during a religious festival at which Diego Columbus and other high Spanish authorities would be present. The sermon was written out beforehand and was delivered by Father Antonio Montesinos.[9]

This sermon, delivered in December 1511, took as its text, “I am the voice of one crying in the wilderness.” After Montesinos completed his introduction and said something about the subject of the religious holiday, he began to emphasize the aridity of the Spanish consciences on the island of Hispaniola, and the ignorance in which the Spaniards on the island lived. After pointing out that he, Montesinos, was the voice of Christ in the “wilderness” of the island, he warned his audience that they “are all in mortal sin and live and die in it, because of the cruelty and tyranny they practice among these innocent peoples.”

Tell me, by what right of justice do you hold these Indians in such a cruel and horrible servitude? On what authority have you waged such detestable wars against these people, who dwelt quietly and peacefully on their own land? Wars in which you have destroyed such infinite numbers of them by homicides and slaughters never before heard of! Why do you keep them so oppressed and exhausted without giving them enough to eat or curing them of the sicknesses they incur from the excessive labor you give them, and they die, or rather, you kill them, in order to extract and acquire gold every day?[10]

The sermon, which fell like a bombshell on the Spaniards, brought forth protests from all the leading men of the island, including Admiral Diego Columbus and the royal representatives of the king. They all agreed to rebuke the Dominicans for preaching such a new and unheard of doctrine, which condemned them all. After haughtily meeting with Montesinos’ superior, Fray Pedro de Córdoba, they calmed down enough to present their complaints. The Admiral asked “why that father had dared preach things in such disservice to the king and so harmful to the whole land, by affirming that they could not possess Indians after the king, the lord of all the Indies, gave them to them–especially since the Spaniards had won those islands with great hardships and had subjugated the pagans who held them. And since that sermon had been so scandalous . . . they had decided that that father should retract everything he had said; if not, they would undertake to arrange a fitting remedy.”[11] After further beseeching and argument, the Dominicans finally agreed that Father Montesinos would return to preach the next Sunday and would go back over his subject “and say what seemed best to him about it, and, as much as possible, would try to satisfy them and explain everything he had said. This having been agreed upon, the officials departed, happy in this hope.”[12]

When the hour for the next sermon came, Father Montesinos mounted the pulpit and announced as his text for the basis of the retraction a saying from St. Job, “I will go back over my knowledge from the beginning and I will prove that my discourse is without falsehood.” That is, “I will go back to rehearse from the beginning my knowledge and the truths which I preached to you last Sunday and 1 will show that those words of mine which embittered you are true.” He began to elaborate with more arguments and facts what he had affirmed before:

“… that those oppressed and exhausted peoples were held unjustly and tyrannically. He repeated his understanding that the Spaniards could certainly not be saved in the state they were in, and therefore in time should heal themselves. He made them know that the friars would not confess a man of them, any more than they would confess highway robbers, and that the Spaniards might proclaim and write that to whomever they wished in Castile. In all this, the friars considered it certain that they were serving God and doing the king no small favor.”[13]

The news of these two sermons arrived in Spain, very much distorted and much to the discredit of the conscientious Dominicans. King Ferdinand, astounded by the reports of infidelity and treason among the Dominicans, summoned the provincial of the Order, who similarly shared the surprise of the king and wrote a long and famous letter to the missionaries of Hispaniola. However, the friars themselves were not passive in the face of falsehood and slander. Montesinos and Córdoba returned to Spain to present their case to the king. The king’s officials tried to prevent this and went so far as to send a Franciscan missionary to court to counteract the reports of the Dominicans. However, Montesinos was able to convince the Franciscan and bring him over to his point of view. It was then that the king, shocked by what he now heard of Spanish atrocities, said, “Is this possible?” Having been properly informed of Spanish outrages against the Indians, Ferdinand summoned the juntas of Burgos and Valladolid, in which, together with other jurists and theologians, five Dominicans took part. From these juntas came the Laws of Burgos of 1512 and those of Valladolid of 1513.[14] These codes were promulgated by Ferdinand in an attempt to limit the demands of the Spaniards upon a conquered people.”[15]

This controversy over the treatment of the Indians, and the eventual formulation of the much celebrated Laws of the Indies in 1542, could never have come about without the theological-juridical and Thomist tradition of the Dominican order. Those first missionaries did not protest solely from the natural and Christian impulse of humanity and compassion; they were learned men formed in Salamanca and other centers of Dominican instruction in Spain. Their protests stemmed from the theological and juridical theses reflected in the report of Father Montesinos: “Are the Indians not men? Do they not have rational souls? With what right do you keep them in servitude? With what authority have you waged these detestable wars against these peoples who lived peacefully in their own lands?” To the credit of all the Spanish monarchs, Ferdinand, Charles I, and Philip II, they all sought to make their work in America conform to the doctrines of the Dominican missionaries and theologians, such as Vitoria and de Soto. Although their efforts may have failed owing to improper enforcement and the greed of themselves and their officials, “no other theological-juridical problem of sixteenth century Spain revealed such an unanimity of opinion among Spanish thinkers, as that displayed in the problems arising from the Conquest and Christianization of America.” The Laws of the Indies serve as proof.[16]

Francisco de Vitoria (1483?-1546) was probably the most noted scholastic scholar in all of Spain during the first half of the sixteenth century. He was literally a teacher of teachers at the University of Salamanca from 1526 till his death, during which time the University produced most of the great theologians and missionaries for America. In 1532, he delivered lectures, subsequently published under the title Relección de los lndios, or Readings on the Indians and on the Law of War, which set forth certain fundamental principles of law in the course of analyzing and defending the rights of the Indians. Vitoria has been referred to as the father of modern international law. He examined and rejected the various alleged justifications for the subjugation of the Indians, maintaining their rights to the lands they occupied and their freedom from any compulsion in the acceptance of Christianity, and limiting the intervention of the Spaniards to the organization of a government on behalf of the welfare of the Indians.”

The Thomist tradition formed the central part of Vitoria’s system. From St. Thomas, Vitoria received these two fundamental principles:

1. The divine law, which proceeds from grace, does not annul human law, which proceeds from natural reason. 2. Those things that are natural to man neither are to be taken from nor are to be given to him on account of sin. In other words: That which is natural, be it called law or right, faculty or power, is so consubstantial with the being of man that it remains immutable in every class of men and he cannot lose it or acquire it through sin, whether he be Christian or pagan, black or white.

Using these postulates, Vitoria analyzed and offered his solution to the colonization problems of the Indies. His analysis of the justice of the situation resolved itself into three questions: “By what right have the barbarians or natives of the recently discovered New World been placed under Spanish rule? What temporal and civil power do the Spanish kings have over those natives? What are the limits of the power of the Spanish monarchs, or the church or the popes, over the Indians in what pertains to spiritual or religious matters?”[18]

Vitoria ultimately reduced his preliminary questions to one fundamental issue. Were these barbarians or natives of the New World true masters of their countries, and hence true owners of their properties and capable of having legitimate princes or rulers? Vitoria’s answer inevitably flowed from the two Thomistic principles stated above, “and dealt a crushing blow to the medieval errors that presented the Indians as barbarous, savage, indolent, and incapable of governing themselves. Following the classic custom of theologians, Vitoria first enumerated the arguments of his foes, which constituted a synthesis of the contemporary ideology and its classical citations from Aristotle,” defending two forms of human nature–the slave and the master.[19]

“Vitoria’s reply to these arguments was incisive: Mortal sin does not deprive a man of his civil rights, of his true dominion over himself and his property.[20] In other words, the dominion or right of a man, of all men without distinction of race or culture, to use inferior objects as his own is a natural right which is not annulled by mortal sin, paganism, or the vices of the barbarian, uncouth peoples.” Domingo de Soto, Vitoria’s comrade at Salamanca, corroborated this thesis: “Those who are in the grace of God are not a whit better off then the sinner or the pagan in what concerns natural rights.” Vitoria also cited the opinion of St. Thomas: “Paganism annuls neither natural rights nor human rights.” The Indians did not lose their rights because of their backwardness or sins against nature or their savage condition. From all this, Vitoria concluded in his Relección de los Indios that the Indians of the New World were without doubt true owners, publicly and privately, of their lands and estates, whether they were princes or private persons, just as Christians were in their own lands, and could not be stripped of these rights. Vitoria strongly defended the equal rights of all men. Anticipating and elaborating on both the self-ownership and homesteading axioms, he did not consider discovery as the sufficient basis for ownership of new lands. If the Indians of the New World are owners of their land by natural and human right, as Vitoria claimed, the arrival of foreign navigators and seamen meant nothing. From this point of view, the Spaniards had no more right to America than the Indians would have had if they had discovered Spain and the rest of Europe. The title was false because this had not been a discovery of deserted, ownerless land. The Indians were the owners of their lands by the same right that Spaniards owned their land in Spain.[22]

Thus did Dominicans assert “the Thomist principle that natural rights come before all other rights, divine, positive, ecclesiastical. Natural law is at the base of all other laws; its provisions take precedence over the provisions of the laws of nations, international law, and the various national civil laws. To be sure, a man might lose his rights, even his natural rights, but not through sinning qua sinning–only through the commission of crime, of injury, by offending society and the natural and human rights of other men.” The Spanish theologians preached these verities without consulting the interests of their monarchs or country. Their integrity and respect for the truth as they understood it shines out above all. “The Spanish monarchs were not offended, nor did they halt these controversies when they were told the truth. On the contrary, they made these doctrines their own and sought to make their laws conform to them.” The formulation of the Laws of the Indies in 1542 was largely based on the arguments of such men as Vitoria and Bartolomé de las Casas.[23]

The integrity and renunciation of worldly interests by the Spanish theologians is perhaps best represented by Bartolomé de las Casas (1474-1566). His “chief merit consists in having had the courage to renounce all material interests” and to have embraced “the justice and truth espoused by the first Dominican missionaries” and teachers “and to have defended these principles on behalf of the Indians for over half a century.”[24] It is important to understand that las Casas, known as the Apostle or Protector of the Indians, was only one of the many Dominicans who took an interest in the affairs of the Indians. He defended their proprietary rights and demanded restitution for the violation of their liberty and property. While he could not rise to the theoretical insights of a Vitoria or de Soto, he did write and publish many, many theses and books in defense of the Indians, such as his well-known History of the Indies. Bartolomé de las Casas is important to us because he represented a set of ideas systematized by men like Vitoria and de Soto and because he gave his body and soul to the defense of such ideas without fear of adversity, censure, intrigues, or calumnies.[25] From this point of view he is without an equal.[26]

Las Casas clearly reflects the thinking of the Spanish Renaissance scholars of natural law. In all his treatises, he affirmed the natural liberty and dominion of the Indians and their princes to their lands, by virtue of their being men with all the natural and human rights that entailed.[27] Las Casas received a good Latin education in Spain and was greatly influenced by the discovery of the New World. His father and two uncles sailed with Columbus on his second voyage, and when they returned in 1498, las Casas was presented with a young Taino Indian, who was to be his servant. In early 1502 las Casas, himself, embarked on his first trip to the New World. He was commissioned a doctrinero, which meant that his Latin ability afforded him an opportunity to instruct the Indians in Christian doctrine. In Hispaniola, las Casas lived like the other colonists, received an encomienda and helped to put down Indian uprisings against the Spaniards.[28] The encomienda system was based on the “giving” or “commendation” of the Indians to the Spaniards, who became encomenderos. This grant by the Spanish crown gave the Spaniards the right to exact labor or tribute from the Indians; in return, the encomenderos were obliged to provide religious instruction and protection.[29]

During the years 1506-1507, las Casas traveled back to Europe and visited Rome, where he was advanced to a deaconate. He was back in Hispaniola by 1511 and apparently was a firsthand witness to Father Montesinos’ sermon (the only contemporary historical record of this event is found in his History of the Indies). However, it was not until several years later, that the impact of the sermon reached las Casas’ consciousness. In 1513, he served as a chaplain during the Spanish conquest of Cuba. He was awarded another large encomienda and with the help of his partner, Pedro de Renteria, prospered in farming and trade. A year later, while preparing a sermon, las Casas came across the Biblical saying, “Tainted his gifts who offers in sacrifice ill-gotten goods” (Ecclesiasticus 34). Having witnessed the Spanish slaughter of the Indians in Cuba, as a literal blood-bath, las Casas was troubled about the justice of his holdings. Were his offerings derived from Indian lands and Indian labor actually ill-gotten goods? What he had heard from Father Montesinos and the other Dominicans on Hispaniola only served to reinforce his doubts. Moreover, another Dominican priest had refused to hear las Casas’ confession because he was holding Indians.[30]

After spending a few days with these thoughts and having each day become more sure “from what he read of natural and divine law, and from the events he witnessed–applying the first to the second–he decided for himself, convinced by truth, that everything done to the Indians in these Indies was unjust and tyrannical.”[31] Finally he decided to preach this message in his sermon, but not before giving up his holdings in land and Indians. In order freely to condemn the encomenderos and the enslavement of the Indians, he felt it necessary to cleanse his own hands of such injustices. He thus decided to consult his partner and surrender his lands and Indians back to the governor, who was to consider them unclaimed and do with them what he would.[32] Las Casas thereupon preached a number of sermons against his fellow Spaniards, which shocked them as much as they had been shocked by the sermon of Montesinos. Henceforth, las Casas devoted his life to the Indians, and in every book he read, “whether in Latin or Spanish, he found additional reasons and authorities to prove and corroborate the justice of those Indian people and to condemn the robbery, evil, and injustice committed against them.” Las Casas was to follow this path, chosen in his fortieth year, for the remaining fifty years of his life. It is not too much to say that the struggle for justice for the Indians would have been much less stoutly and persistently fought without him.[33]

After undergoing this change of mind and heart, las Casas re-crossed the ocean, arriving in Seville in October 1515. His intent was to present his case to King Ferdinand, but he was foiled by the monarch’s untimely death. Nevertheless, he was able to present his case against the Spanish conquest to Secretary Lope Conchillos, who tried to offer him favors in the New World if he would call off his campaign on behalf of the Indians. He also spoke to Bishop Juan Rodriguez de Fonseca, the overseer of Indian affairs in Spain, who listened impatiently to las Casas’ account of Indian sufferings and scornfully inquired, “What is this to me?” “What is it to your lordship and to the king that those souls die?” retorted the “choleric” las Casas. “Oh great and eternal God! Who is there to whom that is something?”[34] During the following years, until his departure for the New World again in 1521, las Casas continued his campaign for Indian justice undismayed. He hatched various schemes of colonization to serve as alternatives to the encomienda system, and one of his efforts to establish a utopian colony in Venezuela was dramatically unsuccessful.

In 1522, las Casas entered the Dominican novitiate at Santa Domingo and, one year later, became a professed Dominican. For the next eleven years, in his own words, he “to all appearances, slept,” while the tide of Spanish conquest swept over Mexico and Peru. During these years he devoted himself to contemplation and the study of theology and law. In 1527, he founded the Dominican monastery at Puerto de Plata on the north end of Hispaniola. Here, as prior, he refused to grant absolution to Spanish colonists unless they would make restitution for goods and services taken from the Indians.[35] He also began work on his famous History of the Indies. In 1537, in response to the papal bull “Sublimis Deus”, which affirmed the Church’s conviction in the rationality of the Indians and in their ability to receive the faith, las Casas wrote in Latin, The Only Method of Attracting People to the True Faith. In this work he refuted the arguments that armed conquest was a necessary preliminary to conversion of the Indians. Las Casas demonstrated the inexpediency and injustice of all wars against the Indians and pleaded for their peaceful conversion. “War also fills every place with highwaymen, thieves, ravishers, fires, and murders,” wrote las Casas. In true libertarian style, he asked, “Indeed what is war but general murder and robbery among many?”[36] To prove the merits of his arguments, in 1537, he undertook the peaceful conversion of fierce Indian tribes living in an area called the Land of War in northeast Guatemala.

Finding the need for more missionaries in Guatemala, las Casas journeyed to Spain in 1540. He recruited Dominicans for his mission and won the support of his superiors for his view that the Indians should not be baptized en masse. He received permission to remain in Spain until Charles V returned from war with France, hoping thereby to present anew his complaints against the methods of the conquistadores. He wrote the first version of his Very Brief Account of the Destruction of the Indies and read it at court to shock his hearers with lurid details of Spanish cruelty. He charged members of the Council of the Indies with corruption and argued in favor of abolishing the encomienda system and placing all Indians under the trusteeship of the Crown. The New Laws of the Indies, promulgated in 1542, were partly a response to las Casas’ campaign at court. Confirming the hostility of Charles V to the development of a neo-feudalism in the New World, the New Laws announced that no more Indians were to he enslaved, officials were to be deprived of their encomiendas, and all other encomiendas were to be transferred back to the Crown upon the death of their holders.”[37]

Hoping to see his efforts ripen in the New World, las Casas sailed for Peru in 1544. News of the New Laws had already reached Mexico and Peru, and had set off protests against its provisions. When las Casas announced to the Spaniards in Chiapa, Mexico, where he accepted a bishopric, that he would refuse absolution to any Spaniard who did not free his Indiana slaves or make restitution of wealth gained from the encomiendas, he was nearly forced out of the colony. Owing to the widespread revolt against the New Laws, in 1545 Charles revoked the key law of inheritance, which had provided for the phasing out of the encomiendas. In June 1546, while preparing to depart from Mexico City for Spain, las Casas composed his “confesionario” or rules for confessors to be applied in his own diocese. The contents of his “Confesionario” created a scandal and caused las Casas to be accused of treason. He insisted that every penitent free his Indian slaves and make full restitution before receiving absolution–no matter what heirs were waiting for his property–because the penitent’s wealth had been unjustly acquired.[38]

When las Casas reached Spain, he found himself on the defensive. He had to spell out his theory of Spain’s title to the Indies, which was that Pope Alexander VI had granted Spain only the right to evangelize the natives, not to conquer and make slaves of them. He also encountered, for the first time, the well-known champion of the conquistadores’ point of view, Ginés de Sepúlveda, who was the emperor’s chronicler and Renaissance humanist. In 1548, las Casas had helped prevent the Spanish publication of Sepúlveda’s Democrates Alter, which defended wars of conquest. In return, Sepúlveda played a part in the government’s confiscation of las Casas’ “Confesionario.” Las Casas tried to stem the reaction by redoubling his protests against Spain’s exploitation of the Indian. Finally Charles V became so troubled by las Casas’ criticisms that he ordered all conquest in the New World halted. This was in 1550, and soon thereafter a commission of theologians jurists was appointed to hear Sepúlveda and las Casas debate the justice of the conquest and to decide on the most lawful method of carrying out the Spanish occupation of America.[39]

The great debate took place in 1550, between July and September, in Valladolid, and was heard by many of the great university theologians and jurists of Spain. Sepúlveda argued that the Indians’ vices justified war against them and that they were also an inferior race needing Spanish tutelage. They were “slaves by nature” in the words of Aristotle’s Politics. Las Casas replied by defending the Indians’ rationality and liberty.[40] Without recounting their arguments, it is not too much to say that Sepúlveda’s ideas failed to win official approval. Spain, through the mouth of las Casas, made a substantial contribution toward the development of one of the most important hypotheses ever set forth–the idea that the Indians discovered by Spain in the New World were not beasts, not slaves by nature, not childlike creatures with a limited understanding, but rather men capable of becoming Christians, with the right to enjoy their property, political liberty, and human dignity, who should be incorporated into the Spanish and Christian civilization rather than being enslaved or destroyed. “When las Casas spoke at Valladolid for the American Indians, his argumentation . . . strengthened the hands of all those who in his time and the centuries to follow worked in the belief that all the peoples of the world are human beings with the potentialities and responsibilities of men.”[41]

Though the judges never rendered a formal decision, las Casas was inspired by the successes he had accomplished in Spain. There was still much work to be done on behalf of the Indians, and since he felt it could best be done in Spain, in 1551 he arranged for lifetime residence in the Dominican monastery at Valladolid. This gave him the leisure and time to devote to his studies and writings about the New World and the Indians. He now became permanently and universally recognized as “Protector of the Indians.” During 1552, he published seven treatises at Seville. They included his controversial “Confesionario,” two treatises on Spain’s title to the Indies, an attack on Indian slavery, an attack on the encomienda system, a summary of his debate with Sepúlveda, and his already written Very Brief Account of the Destruction of the Indies. Between 1554 and 1560, he fought his last major battle on behalf of the Indians. Peruvian conquistadores were making an effort to have their encomiendas made perpetual by offering the new Spanish monarch, Philip II, some 7-9 million ducats. Las Casas arranged to get powers of attorney from the Peruvian tribes and offered to better the bid of the conquistadores by 100,000 ducats. Eventually the proposal was dismissed, but not before las Casas had written of the Spaniards in the New World: “The best thing imaginable would be to cast them, the Spaniards, all out, except a few chosen ones”[42]

Instead of gracefully or even gradually retiring, las Casas kept on campaigning for recognition of Indian rights almost to the day of his death. During the last decade of his life, he followed the regal court about clamoring for justice for the Indians–and most often obtaining it.[43] “The old holy man” was both an Old Testament prophet and a canon lawyer.[44] In true libertarian style he became more radical as he grew older.”[45] If anything, his final positions hardened.[46] He became more rigid on his insistence of restitution to the Indians.[47] In the years after the failure of the New Laws, las Casas became more and more determined and energetic. His earlier view of considering the conquest and the encomiendo system as abuses by individual Spaniards could not be continued when the Crown itself supported them. “Then it was that las Casas began to abandon his ancient regalism to give himself over to the defense of his thesis, even when it was contrary to legal decisions of the king, finding support for his views in the Thomistic theory of natural law.” Earlier, “las Casas had recalled to Phillip II that the prince could not make just by his laws what natural law held to be unjust. The regalism of las Casas now seems to disappear entirely when he sees that the Crown has decided on a matter involving conscience in the light of its own material interests.”[48]

Las Casas carried on extensive correspondence with his disciples throughout Spain and the New World. He represented many of the Indian tribes at court under powers of attorney. In 1559 he completed his Apologetic History, and by 1564 had finished his History of the Indies. The latter work is a pioneer study in anthropology, containing detailed descriptions of the Indians’ lands, social and political organization, and customs. Las Casas also made a very important contribution to New World historiography by preserving the single greatest document on the discovery of America, the journal kept by Columbus as he proceeded westward on his first voyage. The journal, which has not survived, was transcribed by las Casas and used in writing his History.[49]

A few days before his death in Madrid in 1566, he had a colleague present a petition concerning Indian rights to the Council of the Indies. Less than three weeks before, he had prevented certain Indians of Guatemala from being given in an encomienda. In his will, dated March 17, 1564, he described his vocation and told how he had labored for fifty years for his people, the Indians:

In His goodness and mercy, God considered it right to choose me as his minister, though unworthy, to plead for all those peoples of the Indies, possessors of those kingdoms and lands, against wrongs and injuries never before heard of or seen, received from our Spaniards . . . and to restore them to the primitive liberty of which they were unjustly deprived. . . . And I have labored in the court of the kings of Castile going and coming many lies from the Indies to Castile and from Castile to the Indies, for about fifty years, since the year 1514, for God alone and from compassion at seeing perish such multitudes of rational men, domestic, humble, most mild and simple beings, well fitted to receive our Catholic faith . . . and to be endowed with all good customs.[50]

Las Casas was truly a heroic figure; today, throughout much of Latin America, he is considered a true saint. There is only one blotch on his escutcheon, yet even this stain serves to demonstrate his concern for justice and right. In his History of the Indies, las Casas tells that at the beginning of his crusade, and with the object of securing freedom for the Indian, he had advocated that the Spaniards be permitted to bring Negro slaves to the New World. He states that later he came to regret this, having realized the injustice of the ways in which the Portuguese took blacks and made them slaves. From that time onward, he spoke of Negro enslavement as being equally unjust and tyrannical as that of the Indians, because Negroes possess the same powers of reasoning as do Indians.[51]

Las Casas did not ultimately reject the institution of slavery, but he did demand that its legal requirements be fulfilled.[52] This was in line with the thinking of other Dominicans, such as Vitoria, who claimed that those Negroes enslaved in legitimate war, among themselves, could be sold as slaves to the Europeans. The case of the Indian was different, from las Casas’ view, because the Spaniards had entered into unjust wars against them. Therefore no legitimate slaves could be taken. In his memorial of 1543, las Casas offered to prove that not even a single Indian could lawfully be enslaved. In another treatise, las Casas wrote that all men are free “if the contrary is not proved” and that their natural freedom can be lost only by accident or special circumstances–not by nature as Sepúlveda maintained.[53] Several Spanish thinkers, besides las Casas, anticipated the English and American antislavery movement of the nineteenth century. An interesting episode is related by Friar Tomás de Mercado, a Spaniard, in 1569. He relates that the theologians of Seville and Castile asked the theologians of Lisbon whether they approved of the African slave trade, which was taking place under the Portuguese emperor. The latter replied by asking whether the Sevillians and Castilians thought that theology in Lisbon was different from theology in Seville, and saying that they, in Lisbon, condemned the slave trade just as much as the Spanish theologians did.[54]

As Protector of the Indians, las Casas came to advocate restitution, whereby the Spaniards would have to return to the Indians the land and property stolen from them. The requirements of full restitution were contrary to the interests of the Spanish colonists, as evidenced by their rejection of the New Laws of 1542. However from las Casas’ point of view, open or even covert refusal to make restitution to the Indian was equated with cases of simple theft, which in conformity with the norms of Christian doctrine barred the offending encomendero from absolution by a priest. The same was true of an encomendero who had not paid Indians for their work, or had sent them illegally to the mines, or taken their goods without payment. According to the rules of las Casas’ “Confesionario,” such offenses deferred absolution until the delinquents had made reparation. They had the recourse of complaining or litigating in the Council of the Indies, but they could not receive absolution or make their peace with the church because they had not repaired the mischief done and had retained property that belonged to others.[55] “The restitution of Indian property and other rights was represented as the collective obligation of all the participants in the Conquest.” Las Casas also “insisted on the perpetual right of the Indians to wage war against the Spaniards, until the just cause of such war disappeared. . . . He asserted that the Spaniards could not collect tribute without committing mortal sin” and he “reminded confessors that they had no right to collect as much as a penny for performance of their duties if they did not exhort and persuade those who had robbed the Indians to make restitution. Nor could the church collect tithes or accept alms that had originally been ‘stolen.’ Anyone who took gold from the native temples or graves committed robbery. No Spaniard could gain salvation if he did not return all the lands he had taken from the Indians.”[56]

Las Casas often referred to restitution, especially in his later years, and he had even written a treatise on the subject, which has not survived. In a “representation” of 1542, las Casas wrote: “All the goods that all the conquistadores in all the Indies possess were robbed and taken with enormous violence from their owners, the Indians. All the world knows this, and the conquistadores themselves recognize and admit this. . . .”[57] He proposed that the pope be requested to order “a general composition” of goods or riches whose owners or heirs were dead or unknown. Las Casas requested that in the case of properties

whose owners or heirs are alive, Your Majesty should order their restitution to their proper owners. . . . But in the case of those who are dead or have not left heirs, using the said license and authority of the Pope, Your Majesty is obliged to order the best and most favorable restitution possible, to the people of the said lands. . . . And this Your Majesty must not fail to do, with all your power, for restitution of stolen property or for injuries done to the innocent is commanded by both natural and divine law, which Your Majesty cannot set aside or weaken.”[58]

Las Casas maintained that the King, who had received a large share of the booty of the conquistadores, should waive his rights to all future tribute from the Indians. Las Casas specifically required restitution from three classes of persons: those who had taken or still took up arms as conquistadores; encomenderos who held Indians in encomienda; and merchants who supplied arms and material for wars against the Indians.[59] None of these people were innocent of wrong doing. In sum, las Casas thought that all the Spaniards had done in the Indies was null and legally invalid because it had been done without the authority of their king and without natural justice.[60] Las Casas’ restitution theory had a definite impact in Latin America, especially in Peru where the archbishop of Lima, Fray Geronimo de Loaysa, gave it serious attention. First, a junta of theologians was summoned, later, the second council of Lima, over which Loaysa presided, considered the significance of restitution to the Indians. The council decreed that “those who have gravely injured the Indians must cease their oppression and restore what has been unjustly taken from them, since the sin continues if restitution is not made.” The decree explained how restitution was to be made if the injured parties were not known or had left no heirs, and it admonished notary publics to propose to testators just means for making good the injuries they had caused. Las Casas’ doctrine on the strict application of the Christian norms of restitution of unjustly acquired property deeply penetrated the Church in Peru. “The trail of las Casas can he recognized with the most absolute certainty, especially in the rigorous condition that restitution must be specified in a public instrument that was made out before confession by conquistadores and encomenderos.”[61]

There is no question but that the natural law theories of a Vitoria and the demands for restitution by las Casas fall within the libertarian tradition. The central thrust of that tradition is to oppose any and all forms of invasion against property rights of individuals in their own persons and in the material objects they have voluntarily acquired. Adopting the criminal metaphor, we may say that governments are like organized gangs of banditti, negating property rights and surviving by imposing territorial jurisdiction and taxation on those they conquer.[62] This description aptly fits the history of the Spanish conquest in the New World. The scholastics of sixteenth century Spain saw that the Indians were deprived of their personal Liberty, their lands, and their moveable property. Without a doubt they were forerunners of later groups comprising the libertarian tradition: the Levellers and opponents of Charles II in seventeenth century England, the American rebels revolting against England in the eighteenth, and the English and American anti-slavery radicals of the nineteenth century. These Spaniards were unable to envision the existence of a truly libertarian society and free market, given the semi-feudal state they lived in, but they did realize that legitimate property titles were essential to defining justice in any given situation. Only by inquiring into the justice of property titles, which they rightfully grounded on homesteading and self-ownership, and demanding rectification of injustices wherever they were found, could these Spaniards rest easy with their consciences. The entire Third World concern with land reform today points back to the same concerns of these sixteenth century Spanish clerics and jurists.[63] At the base of their theological-juridical system was a fundamentally libertarian postulate. Humanity, in their eyes, was a single universal society–by natural law. Although we might not accept their theology, they maintained that God, lord of the universe, created man in order to people the world and exploit its natural resources. Natural law makes men–all men without distinction of frontier or race–members of this world community by birth. “Man is a citizen of the world by natural law.”[64] “All mankind is one” as we have stated, in the sense that all peoples of the world have individual rights. What more beautiful illustration of the libertarian tradition at work in sixteenth century Spain could one ask for?

Notes

1. Encyclopaedia Britannica, 15th ed., s.v. “Spain, History of.”
2. Lewis Hanke, Bartolomé de las Casas , An Interpretation of His Life and Writings (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1951), pp. 2, 4, 48.
3. Venancio D. Carro, “The Spanish Theological-Juridical Renaissance and the Ideology of Bartolomé de las Casas,” in Juan Friede and Benjamin Keen, eds., Bartolomé de Las Casas in History (De Kalb: Northern Illinois University Press, 1971), p. 245.
4. Murray Rothbard, For a New Liberty (New York: Macmillan, 1973), p. 43. For more on the libertarian tradition, see Carl Watner, “The Criminal Metaphor in the Libertarian Tradition,” Journal of Libertarian Studies, 5, No.3 (Summer 1981).
5. This expression was used by Lewis Hanke in his book by the same title, “All Mankind Is One”; A Study of the Disputation Between Bartolomé de las Casas and Juan Ginés de Sepúlveda in 1550 on the Intellectual and Religious Capacity of the American Indian (De Kalb: Northern Illinois University Press, 1974). See also p. xi of this book.
6. J. Martin Littlejohn, “The Political Theory of the Schoolmen and Grotius” (Ph.D. diss., Columbia University, 1896), pp. 7-8.
7. Hanke, “All Mankind Is One,” p. 142, quoting Pereña Vicente.
8. Carro, “Spanish Theological-Juridical Renaissance,” pp. 248-49. Carro’s essay has been invaluable in writing this paper and is highly recommended.
9. The next several paragraphs dealing with Montesinos are based on selections found in Goorge Sanderlin, tr. and ed., Bartolomé de las Casas, A Selection of His Writings (New York: Knopf, 1971), pp. 81-86.
10. Ibid., p. 81.
11. Ibid., p. 83.
12. Ibid., p. 84.
13. Ibid., p. 85.
14. This paragraph is based on Carro. “Spanish Theological-Juridica1 Renaissance,” p. 245.
15. Encyclopaedia Britannica, 15th ed., s.v. “Indies, Law of the.”
16. This paragraph is based on Carro, “Spanish Theological-Juridical Renaissance,” p. 245.
17. See ibid., generally, and also Encyclopaedia Britannica, 15th ed., s.v. “Vitoria, Francisco de.”
18. This paragraph is based on Carro, “Spanish Theological-Juridical Renaissance,” pp. 251-52.
19. Ibid., pp. 252-53.
20. Ibid., p. 253 (unless otherwise noted). i
21. Carro refers to his work, Domingo de Soto y su doctrina juridico (Madrid, 1944), pp. 207-50. Referring to de Soto’s work on Justice, Carro writes: “Domingo de Solo always answered in the negative mode and supported the first principles of right [referring to the question of whether the state might not sacrifice one of its citizens, even if innocent of any wrongdoing. in order to save the remainder]. The city or Republic is not the owner of life and may not sacrifice, even indirectly, any citizen even if it is the only means proper for the defense of the rest. Even if the existence of the nation depended on the life of one innocent man, it would not be legal for the State to sacrifice his life. . . Vitoria and de Soto exploded the argument that one should sacrifice one’s arm or leg to save the rest of one’s body from infection [as a justification for the Republic’s sacrifice of one innocent citizen]. Sacrificing a citizen to the public good was not the same as amputating your leg. The two examples had no parity. The innocent person has a personality of his own, even though he is a member of the public, whereas our arms or legs do not have their own distinct personalities and are incapable of having rights separate from the rest of the body” (my translation, pp. 211-12). I am sure one could find many more libertarian arguments based on natural rights in the works of these authors.
22. See Carro, “Spanish Theological-Juridical Renaissance,” pp. 254-58, especially p. 256.
23. This paragraph is based on ibid., pp. 253-54.
24. Ibid., pp. 247-48.
25. Ibid., p. 264.
26. Las Casas’ biography is reminiscent and serves as a forerunner of latter day anti-slavery radicals and crusaders, such as the Quakers, Ralph Sandiford, Benjamin Lay, and John Woolman. See Carl Watner, “The Radical Libertarian Tradition in Anti-Slavery Thought,” Journal of Libertarian Studies 3, No.3 (Fall 1979):311-12.
27. Carro, “Spanish Theological-Juridical Renaissance,” p. 269.
28. For these and the following biographica1 details, see Sanderlin, Bartolomé de las Casas, pp. 4-24.
29. Hanke, Bartolomé de las Casas, p. 15.
30. Sanderlin, Bartolomé de las Casas. pp. 7-8. Sanderlin’s “Introduction” has been invaluable in writing this paper.
31. Ibid., p. 88, based on autobiographical writings of las Casas found in his History of The Indies.
32. Ibid., p. 89.
33. Hanke, Bartolomé de las Casas, p. 21.
34. Sanderlin, Bartolomé de los Casas, p. 9.
35. Ibid., p. 13.
36. Ibid., p. 14.
37. Ibid., pp. 15-16.
38. Ibid., p. 18.
39. Ibid., p. 19.
40. Ibid.
41. Hanke, Bartolomé de las Casas, p. 87.
42. Sanderlin, Bartolomé de las Casas, p. 21.
43. Ibid.
44. Henry R. Wagner, The Life and Writings of Bartolomé de las Casas (Albuquerque; University of New Mexico, 1967), p. 136; also Sanderlin, Bartolomé de las Casas, p. 21.
45. Sanderlin, Bartolomé de las Casas, p. 20. This reminds one of Murray Rothbard’s description of Lysander Spooner, noted constitutional lawyer and individualist-anarchist: “He became steadily and inexorably more radical as he grew older.” Libertarian Forum 6, No. 9 (September 1974);1.
46. Wagner, Life and Writings, p. 247.
47. Sander1in, Bartolomé de las Casas, p. 20.
48. Hanke, “All Mankind Is One,” p. 155, quoting Silvio Zavala. Here we readily note the implicit anarchist doctrine found in the natural rights theory of the libertarian tradition.
49. Sanderlin, Bartolomé de las Casas. pp. 21-22; see also Hanke, Bartolomé de las Casas. p. 53.
50. Sanderlin, Bartolomé de las Casas, pp. 22-23.
51. Silvio Zavala, The Defense of Human Rights in Latin America, Sixteenth to Eighteenth Centuries (Paris: UNESCO, 1961), pp. 47-48.
52. Juan Friede, “Las Casas and Indigenism in the Sixteenth Century,” in Juan Friede and Benjamin Keen, eds., Bartolomé de las Casas in History (De Kalb: Northern Illinois University Press, 1971), p. 166.
53. Ibid.
54. Zavala, Defense of Human Rights, pp. 49-50.
55. Friede, “Las Casas and Indigenism,” p. 190; see also Wagner’s remarks on restitution in Life and Writings, pp. 234-36.
56. Friede, “Las Casas and Indigenism,” p. 203.
57. Manuel M. Maninez, “Las Casas on the Conquest of America,” in Friede and Keen, eds., Bartolomé de las Casas in History, p. 340.
58. Maninez, “Las Casas on the Conquest of America,” p. 340.
59. Ibid., p. 343.
60. Ibid.
61. Ibid., p. 344.
62. See Rothbard, For a New Liberty, and Watner, “The Criminal Metaphor in the Libertarian Tradition.”
63. Roy Childs, Jr., “Land Reform and the Entitlement Theory of Justice” (Paper delivered at the Libertarian Scholars Conference, Princeton University, Princeton, New Jersey, 1977). See Childs’ “Conclusion,” especially pp. 25-27.
64. Carro, “Spanish Theological-Juridical Renaissance,” p. 258.

Libertarians and Indians: Proprietary Justice and Aboriginal Land Rights


CARL WATNER

Two remarks will serve to introduce my subject. Several years ago, Rosalie Nichols was asked if the Indians had ever had a title deed to North America. She responded, “Who should have issued them one, I don’t know, unless it was the buffalo.”[1] Secondly, Jonathan Hughes, in his book The Governmental Habit, contrasts the allodial and socage forms of land tenure. “Socage tenure was part of the feudal order” and was inevitably carried over by the English to their landholdings in North America. It was designed to protect the interests of the feudal donor (“transformed in our time into the state”) by forcing “property owners to support the taxing power at all times” regardless of whether they desired or used state services. The property owner could never “withdraw his support” from the state by not paying real estate taxes. If he attempted to discontinue his payment, the state would confiscate his title and auction off his property to someone who would pay taxes. “This form of coercion is a product of history” and ultimately traces itself back to the principle of the Right of Discovery, upon which all European nations based their claims to land in North America.[2]

According to the international law of Europe during the fifteenth century, priority of discovery gave a nation supreme and unlimited right to the discovered territory.[3] Title to lands hitherto unknown to Europeans was based on the union of discovery and possession.[4] This meant that although numerous European nations claimed first discovery, actual sovereignty could only be established by effective colonization. (Since the English, in North America, generally proved themselves the most effective colonizers, succeeding comments will refer largely to the practice of the English.) The rights of the Crown were not merely those of head of state or feudal lord paramount. The King was the immediate owner and lord of the soil and exercised unlimited power in its disposition.[5] Theoretically, no settlement could be made without his consent, and if any settlement took place without his prior approval, then he could force it either to disband or to seek a royal charter to confirm its existence. Once the Crown established sovereignty over an area, it then enlarged its authority to include the right to extinguish any vestige of Indian title.[6]

Under international law, the Indians had only a right of uncivilized occupancy.[7] This meant that the natives had no right to dispose of their title except to the Crown or its proprietary agents. The Indians were consistently held incapable of alienating their lands to private parties.[8] By implication, the Crown took the position that if it cared to recognize any Indian title (to lands occupied by the Indians) at all, such title could be transferred only to the Crown. Any purchase of land made by settlers from the natives without the consent of the Crown was regarded and treated as absolutely void. It was a fundamental principle in the English colonial jurisprudence that all titles to land within the colonies passed to individuals only from the Crown or proprietary authorities.[9] No land title examined in the colonial or early state courts was ever admitted to depend upon any Indian deed of relinquishment.[10,11]

These views were confirmed by the Royal Proclamation of 1763, in which the territory still occupied by the Indians west of the Appalachian Mountains was disposed of without reference to the natives. The Crown’s assumption was that the aboriginal tribes had neither title to the soil nor sovereignty. The Royal Proclamation reserved to the British government the exclusive right to purchase and extinguish the rights of the Indian tribes as occupants of the soil. Furthermore, it forbade European settlement on Indian Territory, until permission was granted by the Crown and until after the Indian right had been extinguished by conveyance to the Crown.[12]

The first European in North America to challenge the principle of the Right of Discovery and to uphold the native rights to the soil was Roger Williams. In 1633 he became an ardent proponent of the idea that King James had no right or power to claim ownership of North American lands occupied and used by the Indians. The King was granting things beyond his power to grant when, for example, he issued royal patents to Plymouth, Massachusetts Bay, and other colonies. From Williams’s point of view these patents were invalid. The English could justly occupy lands in North America only by purchasing those lands from their rightful owners, the Indians. Undoubtedly these claims caused alarm among the royal patriots, for they struck at the very foundations of the colonial governments which King James had authorized. Williams was banished from Massachusetts and left to establish his colony in Rhode Island, where he began by purchasing the land from the Indians.[13]

Williams asserted that the rights of the Indian stood upon the original principles of the law of nature, which meant that the lands they had occupied and used could not be alienated from them without their free consent.[14] Roger Williams pointed out that a modified form of private ownership of land did exist among the Indian tribes and that they did not simply live in a state of nature. They had improved the land by burning the underbrush and had cleared the land where they lived, and their woodlands were no less useful than the King’s parks in England.[16] John Winthrop, one of Williams’s detractors, maintained that the unimproved lands of North America belonged to no one, and that whoever labored on unimproved and unclaimed land thereby made it his own. According to Winthrop, land became private property only through cultivation, manuring, and enclosure. Since by English standards the Indians had not noticeably improved their land or enclosed it, it was not rightfully theirs, but simply lay ownerless in the state of nature. Even though the Indians had not cultivated or enclosed their lands, Williams insisted that the colonists first purchase the right to the land from its original users and occupants, the Indians. Williams demanded that the Indians be dealt with on the principle of equality and maintained that so-called civilized states have no right, however nomadic or savage they (the Indians) might be, to divest the title to the soil from them.[17]

Misunderstanding arising from their differing concepts of property in land was one of the main causes of disputes between the Europeans and the Indians. The Indians did not recognize land appropriation by individual members of the tribe, and even Roger Williams recognized that landownership among the Indians was usually held by the tribe. Nevertheless, among the Indians articles of personal property were owned by the individual.[18] Each Indian tribe was perfectly well acquainted with the limits and bounds of its landholdings, even though these holdings were not enclosed in the normal European fashion.[19] Indian land tenure has been characterized 1) as a right of beneficial use and occupancy, rather than an exclusive ownership, and 2) as a group right rather than an individual one. It was probably difficult for the Indians to think of land as individual, private properly, which could be sold or permanently alienated.[20]

Besides Roger Williams, there were others concerned with respecting Indian rights. In 1626 the West India Company instructed its New Netherlands’s agents to formally acquire title to lands, by purchase from the Indians. As early as 1623, records indicate that the Hollanders had purchased land of the Indians.[21 Thus Manhattan Island was purchased by the Dutch in 1626, for goods valued at 60 guilders.[22] This was a sum probably representing the real value of the land in that day, and the Indians made a good trade. The Dutch probably initiated the practice of purchasing lands from the Indians in order to counter the claims of the other European powers. They had little chance of sustaining themselves under the principle of Right of Discovery. They decided to argue, against the claims of the English, that the Indian tribes or nations were the true owners of the land discovered by the English and that title could be obtained from the natives only by gift or purchase. Interestingly enough, when the Swedes arrived in 1638, they recognized the claims of the Dutch, to lands purchased of the Indians. Likewise, the Dutch formally admitted the validity of Swedish titles, when a deed or transfer from the Indians could be produced.[23] The only English colonists to emulate the Dutch and Swedish practice were the Quakers in Pennsylvania; practically all the other English settlers refused to recognize Swedish or Dutch claims since the Indian title had no standing in English law.

The Quakers were the only group of European settlers to have their hands free from the blood of innocent Indians.[24] They never deliberately schemed for the extermination of the Indians and were nearly always concerned to do full justice to Indian claims.[25] They were an unimaginative, pecuniary people, who thought that justice to the Indian consisted in doing him no harm, paying him for his land, and letting him go.[26]

The curious aspect of William Penn’s approach was that his chief object seems to have been to extinguish Indian claims and to give satisfaction to the natives for their possessory rights, rather than to fix definite and accurate boundaries of the land purchased. The wording of the deeds implies that the intent was to cover all possible claims of those making the grants to Penn. Hence it was of little importance that these deeds overlapped and included areas obtained from other claimants.[27] Thus, practically the whole of Pennsylvania was purchased of the Indians, and some of it several times over.[28] The price of these land purchases seems as nothing now, but it was a fair price in those days in the minds of both parties. It took centuries for the white people to learn the value of land in America. In every instance when Penn dealt with the Indians, so long as the bargain was fairly made, the Indians returned to their wigwams satisfied.[29]

What seems to have impressed the Indians was the fact that Penn insisted on purchase at the first and all subsequent agreements as being an act of justice, to which both parties were to give their assent voluntarily. They also felt that the price was ample to extinguish their claims, and that no advantages were taken by plying them with drink or cheating them with false maps. The treaties were open and honorable contracts, and not characterized by sharpness and chicanery. As the Indians reflected on them at their leisure, they saw nothing to repent of and everything to admire in the conduct of Penn, and they preserved inviolably the terms to which they had solemnly agreed.[30]

Even before Penn arrived in his colony, land was purchased of the Indians, under his instructions, as early as 1682. As a Quaker and quasi-pacifist and as a proprietary of the Crown, Penn had a dual role to fulfill as colonial leader. As in many of the other colonies, to resort to buying the lands of the natives may have been an act of expediency, for it must have been much cheaper and easier to purchase the lands of the Indians than to attempt to take them away by force.[31] Liberty and peace were the two main elements of Penn’s Holy Experiment and could be obtained only if no aggression were made on the rights, real or supposed, of the native inhabitants.[32] Penn’s Quaker conscience inspired him to buy not only the Indian lands, but those of all claimants in order to quiet all possible land disputes. It should be noted, however, that regardless of Penn’s concern for justice, Pennsylvania law prohibited purchase of Indian land by individual Quakers or other settlers. Quieting title was a government monopoly which Penn held for himself.[33]

It has been urged by Penn’s critics that neither he nor any other European colonist could with perfect integrity and honesty purchase the land of the aboriginal natives of America, for several reasons. First, savages can never, for any consideration, enter into contracts obligatory upon them. They stand by the law of nations, when trafficking with the civilized pan of mankind, in the situation of infants, incapable of entering into contracts, especially for the sale of their country. Second, should this be denied, it may then be asserted that no monarch or chief of a nation has the power to transfer by sale the soil of the nation over which he rules. Neither William Penn nor any other European since made a purchase of lands from any Indian nation other than through the agency of their sachems or head men, who certainly could have no more right to sell their country than any European monarch has to sell theirs. Third, should these objections be over-ruled, then it may be safely asked, what could William Penn or at least what did he give which should be considered from any point of view as a consideration or a compensation to those aborigines for their land?[34]

Before dealing with these critical points, let it be said that the Indian land issue ought to be viewed from the standpoint of man’s natural and inalienable rights to life, liberty, and property.[35] This means that, since the Indians were human beings, they had the same rights as Caucasians. This means they had the right to control their own minds and bodies free of coercive interference and to own the land on which they and their ancestors had lived since time immemorial. Thus, when “discovered” by the Europeans, parts of the North American continent were not ownerless. The American Indians, by virtue of being first users and occupiers of parts of the continent, were its rightful owners.[36] Since legitimate property owners have an unrestricted right to make arrangements for the disposition of their property, this effectively disposes of the first argument that savages cannot enter into obligatory contracts.

Since the Indians did not hold the land as individuals, but as collective tribal entities, it is difficult to determine whether or not land allocations (under the tribal regime) were more just than the English land grab which took place under the guise of discovery.[37] However, it is plain that private collective ownership is perfectly valid and moral, as long as it is voluntary and there is no violation of individual rights.[38] Private collective ownership must originate in the ability of the individual to own property, which he then cooperatively pools with the property of others. However in the case of the Indians, it has never been asserted that tribal title rested on the agglomeration of individual titles. The actual settler–the first transformer of the land–whether white or Indian–had to fight his way past a nest of arbitrary land claims by others.[39] Were the tribes, in effect, voluntary associations of individuals who consented to their collective ownership of the land? The fact that no form of tribute or taxes was ever collected among the Indian tribes inhabiting what is now the United States lends some credence to the view that the tribes were voluntary organizations.[40]

As voluntary associations, the tribes could, and in fact did, historically, sell their rights to the soil by allowing their chiefs to represent tribal interests. These chiefs were authorized to make and execute deeds on behalf of the tribe, to receive for the tribe the consideration for the deeds, and to divide such consideration among the individuals of the tribe. The authority of the chiefs, so acting for the whole tribe, is attested by the presence and assent of the individuals composing the tribe and by their receipt of their respective share of the price.[41] Thus could the Indian tribes deal with the Europeans for the sale of their lands, and granted that the chiefs had this authority, it must be admitted that they were capable of determining what in their opinion would be ample compensation for their lands.

With these preliminary concerns out of the way, it must now be determined whether or not the bulk of Indian claimed land was actually used and occupied, settled and transformed by the tribes claiming them. If it be admitted that the tribal organizations were voluntary and that Indian landownership was just, then it is plain that European intervention into the allocation of property was a usurpation and a crime against the rightful Indian owners. If the Europeans settling in North America had operated in a free-market or even semi-free-market framework, then the British government would have refrained from claiming sovereignty over the unused domains of America. It would have denounced the principle of the Right of Discovery, and recognized that true ownership could only be established under the principle of “first ownership by the first user” (whether white or Indian).[42]

What exactly does first occupation and use mean? What are the criteria by which the principle of first ownership by the first user is to be interpreted? The crux of the dispute over whether Indian claimed lands were truly owned by the Indians or actually ownerless stems from the failure to distinguish between cultivation and other forms of use. If cultivation and enclosure are deemed to be the hallmarks of establishing occupancy and use, then that large portion of the Indian claimed land which was never “homesteaded” must be viewed as actually ownerless (and thus open to settlement by the actual first user).

Claiming that the American Indians, by virtue of being the first users and occupiers of the continent, were its rightful owners, Rosalie Nichols maintains that “use” is decided upon according to the condition and natural resources of the land, the level and particular type of technology of the occupants, and the desires of the owner.[43] Undoubtedly, the Indians rightfully owned the land that they cultivated and upon which they erected their wigwams and shelters. The main question to settle is whether they rightfully owned the land upon which they regularly or sporadically hunted.

Lysander Spooner in the mid-nineteenth century asserted that those lands which the Indians merely roamed over in search of game, could not be said to have been rightfully owned by them.[44] Rightful ownership of unoccupied lands is established by either actually living upon the land, or improving it, or bestowing other useful labor upon it. “Nothing short of this actual possession can give any one a rightful ownership of wilderness lands, or justify him in withholding it from those who wish to occupy it.” He based his assertions on the principle that occupation and use meant more than standing upon a portion of the North American continent and claiming possession of it. To establish ownership a person must bestow some valuable labor upon the land. In these cases he holds the land in order to hold the labor which he had put into it.[45] Similarly, Rothbard has written that the bulk of Indian claimed land was not settled and transformed by the Indians, and that the new European settlers were justified in ignoring the Indians’ vague abstract claims because they knew they were the first to actually cultivate and enclose the lands upon which they settled.[46]

The fact that the Indians and Europeans did not share a common technology seems to be of no import in establishing legitimate properly titles. To live, all people (regardless of their technology) must occupy certain places on the land, and whoever first establishes a homestead becomes its rightful owner. Unless the Indians bestowed some form of valuable labor over the wilderness areas they hunted, their claims of ownership were unsubstantiated. At most, they could claim the wild animals they killed and the trails that they cleared. The fact that the tribes each had their own hunting areas does not disprove this and indicates that they only wished to live in peace with one another. If and where the Indians attempted to bound off their hunting lands, so that no one else could enter and game could not escape, and where they made efforts to help propagate game, then their ownership would be valid.

Thus game preserves or wilderness areas could exist in a free society. It is also important to understand that land once cultivated, even if allowed to go wild, does not become ownerless. Once a piece of land has passed into just ownership, the owner cannot be divested of title without his consent. Thus even though a piece of land is not currently being farmed, but is perhaps being used for cycle racing or as a rifle range, it is still owned, so long as sometime in the past a rightful possession took place. The present owner is the rightful owner so long as he can trace his title through a historical chain of voluntary transfers from the first occupier and user.[47] The fact that certain forest areas, desert lands, and open ranges, even at this late date (four hundred years after the European discovery of the continent) have never been homesteaded or cultivated means that they are still rightfully ownerless and will probably remain so because of their uneconomic value.[48]

Thus granting that some Indian claims were valid and others invalid, what were the Europeans to do when they discovered America? Even though there were probably few areas which the Indians did not claim, were the Europeans under the necessity of abandoning the country and relinquishing their own pompous claims established under the principle of Right of Discovery?[49] All unjust claims–by the Indians and the European powers–should have been ignored. “The English who colonized this country had no right to drive the Indians from their homes; but on the other hand, there being here an abundance of unoccupied land, the colonists had a right to come and settle on it, and the Indians had no right to prevent them from doing so.[50] I believe that the history of Quaker settlement proves that this policy was possible and furthermore believe that until the latter stages of settlement, the Indians were not as concerned to establish their title to hunting lands as we might think.

If Penn had not been a representative of the Crown, but only a private Quaker or the recognized leader of a corporate body of Friends, his conduct toward the Indians would serve as an example of how a libertarian colonization process could have worked. The fact remains that the Indian tribes he dealt with voluntarily relinquished their claims to him (and in this respect, his position as a Crown representative was unimportant). The Europeans did not need to abandon the continent upon discovering that parts of it were inhabited. Individual settlers or groups of settlers could have quieted Indian claims and extinguished Indian titles much as Penn did. Thus it is conceptually possible that the bulk of Indian landholdings could have passed legitimately into non-Indian control. This is not to say that all tribes would have alienated all their lands, but at least historically some Indians did willingly relinquish their land.[51] Thus the historical picture clearly demonstrates that libertarians and Indians could have lived peacefully together under a regime of proprietary justice.

NOTES

1. Rosalie Nichols, “Right-Wing Rationale of Non-Recognition of Indian Rights,” The Indian Historian 3 (Spring 1970): 27.
2. Jonathan Hughes, The Governmental Habit (New York. Basic Books, 1978), p. 233.
3. James E. Ernst, The Political Thought of Roger Williams (Seattle: University of Washington Press, 1929), p. 95.
4. Melville Egleston, The Land System of the New England Colonies, Johns Hopkins University Studies in Historical and Political Science, 4th ser., vols. 11-12 (Baltimore, 1886), p. 4.
5. Ibid.
6. Ernst, Political Thought of Roger Williams, p. 95.
7. Alpheus Snow, The Question of Aborigines in the Law and Practice of Nations (New York: G P. Putnam’s Sons, 1921), p. 25.
8. Alfred N. Chandler, Land Title Origins (New York: Robert Schalkenbach Foundation, 1945), p. 36.
9. Ibid.
10. Snow, The Question of Aborigines, p. 121.
11. Several interesting questions are raised by the case of Johnson and Granham’s Lessee vs. William McIntosh (8 Wheaton 543) which was decided by the U. S. Supreme Court in 1823. This was an action by Johnson and others to eject McIntosh from lands granted to them by the Piankeshaw Indians during the 1770’s. The land claimed by Johnson was part of the Indian territory claimed by the State of Virginia and then ceded to the federal government in 1783. Although the plaintiffs had petitioned the U. S. Congress numerous times to recognize their conveyance from the Piankeshaw, the federal government granted McIntosh title to the identical piece of land in 1818. In concluding that the Indian deed was of no value and that the grant from the United States government was paramount, Chief Justice Marshall pointed out that: “The person who purchases land from the Indians, within their territory, incorporates himself with them, so far as respects the property purchased; holds their title under their protection, and subject to their laws. If they annul the grant, we know of no tribunal which can revise and set aside the proceeding. We know of no principle which can distinguish this case from a grant made to a native Indian authorizing him to hold a particular tract in severalty [that is, to hold the land as a separate individual, apart from the tribe]. As such a grant could not separate an Indian from his nation, nor give a title which our courts could distinguish from the title of his tribe, we can perceive no legal principle which will authorize a court to say that different consequences are attached to this purchase because it was made by a stranger. By the treaties concluded between the United States and the Indian nations, whose title the plaintiffs claim, the country comprehending the lands in controversy had been ceded to the United States without any reservation of their title. These nations had been at war with the United States, and had an unquestionable right to annul any grant they had made to American citizens. Their cession of the country without any reservation of this land affords a fair presumption that they considered it as of no validity,” (8 Wheaton 593-94). Query I) Why would an Indian grant to a member of the tribe to hold the land in severalty be incapable of separating the Indian from his tribe? Query 2) By what “unquestionable right” did the Indian tribes have the right to annul grants made to outside parties (whether such parties be American citizens or not)? Would the fact that a grant was made to an enemy citizen prior to the commencement of war entitle the Indians to cancel their conveyance after the war had begun? Query 3) Would Marshall have decided the case differently had the Indians actually made a reservation in their treaty with the United States, whereby they recognized the existence of a prior grant of land to Johnson? The presumption that the Indians annulled their former conveyance would have been overcome. Then to rebut the presumption thus created in favor of Johnson’s title, Marshall would have had to revert to the principle of the Right of Discovery .
12. Snow, The Question of Aborigines, p. 19.
13. William C. Macleod, The American Indian Frontier (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1928), p. 199.
14. Ernst, Political Thought of Roger Williams, p. 96.
15. Macleod, American Indian Frontier, p. 19. There is some discrepancy between Ernst and Macleod over Roger Williams’s recognition of landownership by the Indians. For the conflicting discussion see ibid., pp. 18-19, and Ernst, Political Thought of Roger Williams, p. 104.
16. William B. Scott, In Pursuit of Happiness: American Conceptions of Property from the Seventeenth Century to the Twentieth Century (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1977), p. 16.
17. Ernst, Political Thought of Roger Williams, p. 105.
18. Ibid., p. 102.
19. Chandler, Land Title Origins, p. 30.
20. John Provinse, “Tenure Problems of the American Indians,” in Ken H. Parsons, ed., Land Tenure (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1956), p. 421.
21. Macleod. American Indian Frontier, p. 194.
22. Marshall Harris, Origin of the Land Tenure System in the United States (Ames: Iowa State College Press, 1953), p. 165. Also see Macleod, American Indian Frontier, p. 194.
23. Ibid., pp. 195-96. Macleod also footnotes the interesting and similar practice of the Dutch East India Company at the Cape in South Africa: “forced by virtue of desire to avoid an immediate issue of arms with the Hottentot Africans,” the Dutch East India Company during the 1660’s. were “holding formal treaties with the native tribes, giving them money or goods in exchange for land and privileges, and even paying a stated tax to the local tribe for each ship entering the harbour at the Cape” (ibid., p. 196). The Dutch claimed that outright conquest and subjugation of the natives would entitle the invaders to the land of the conquered, but apparently the Dutch never adopted this unlibertarian practice.
24. Ibid.. p. 376.
25. This was true while William Penn lived (until 1748). The story of his son’s fraudulent interpretation of Indian deeds is related in William J. Buck, History of the Indian Walk (Philadelphia: Edwin S. Stuart, 1886).
26. Macleod, American Indian Frontier, p. 376.
27. Cyrus Thomas, “Introduction,” in Charles C. Royce, comp., Indian Land Cessions in the United Stares, 18th Annual Report of the Bureau of American Ethnology to the Secretary of the Smithsonian Institute (Washington: Government Printing Office, 1899), p. 599.
28. Isaac Sharpless, A History of Quaker Government in Pennsylvania (Philadelphia: T. S. Leach & Company, 1900), 1:162.
29. Rayner W. Kelsey, Friends and the Indians (Philadelphia: The Associated Executive Committee of Friends on Indian Affairs, 1917), pp. 45-46.
30. Sharpless, A History of Quaker Government. pp. 157-58.
31. Buck, History of the Indian Walk, pp. 31-32.
32. Rufus M. Jones, The Quakers in the American Colonies (London: Macmillan and Co., 1911), p.470.
33. Royce, Indian Land Cessions, p. 597.
34. John L. Bozman, The History of Maryland (Baltimore: James Lucas & K. E. Deaver, 1837), pp. 569-70.
35. Nichols, “Right-Wing Rationale,” p. 26.
36. Rosalie Nichols, “An Open Letter to an American Author,” The Indian Historian 1 (Spring 1968): 17. Also see Nichols, “Right-Wing Rationale,” pp. 29-30. Ms. Nichols takes the position that the various Indian tribes owned every part of the continent, not just parts of it.
37. Murray N. Rothbard, Conceived in Liberty (New Rochelle, N. Y.: Arlington House, 1975), 1:187.
38. Nichols, “Right-Wing Rationale,” p. 32.
39. Rothbard, Conceived in Liberty, 1:187.
40. Nichols, “Right-Wing Rationale,” p. 33. Referring to the Comanches, Ms. Nichols remarks, “There was no Internal Revenue Service to come after him [the Indian hunter]” (ibid., p. 32).
41. Johnson vs. McIntosh, 8 Wheaton 550.
42. Rothbard, Conceived in Liberty, 1:49.
43. Nichols, “Right-Wing Rationale,” pp. 29, 31.
44. Lysander Spooner, Address of the Free Constitutionalists to the People of the U. S. (Boston: Thayer and Eldridge, 1860), p. 33.
45. Lysander Spooner, The Law of Intellectual Property (Boston: Bela Marsh, 1855), pp. 21-22.
46. Rothbard, Conceived in Liberty, 2:54.
47. Thus comments Murray N. Rothbard, Man, Economy, and State (Princeton: D. Van Nostrand, 1962), 1:147-48: “There is no requirement, however, that land continue to be used in order for it to continue to be a man’s property. Suppose that Jones uses some new land, then finds it unprofitable, and lets it fall into disuse. Or suppose that he clears new land and therefore obtains title to it, but then finds it is no longer useful in production and allows it to remain idle. In a free society, would he lose title? No, for once his labor is mixed with the natural resources, it remains his owned land. His labor has been irretrievably mixed with the land, and the land is therefore his or his assigns’ in perpetuity.” Also see Carl Watner, Towards a Proprietary Theory of Justice (Baltimore: by the author, 1976), p. 8.
48. Nichols, “Right-Wing Rationale,” p. 30. Neither does the federal government rightfully own such land as has never been homesteaded and which falls within the so-called public domain.
49. Royce, Indian Land Cessions, p. 538, and Johnson vs. McIntosh, 8 Wheaton 590.
50. Benjamin Tucker, Liberty, Whole No.360 (March 1899), p. 1.
51. Even Ms. Nichols, an advocate of Indian rights to all the land, implies that some holdings by Europeans of Indian land were justly acquired. Otherwise, how could she write: “Fraud also was used by European invaders to obtain land that they could not obtain by voluntary consent” (Nichols, “Right-Wing Rationale,” p. 26).

“Oh, Ye Are For Anarchy!”: Consent Theory in the Radical Libertarian Tradition


 

by Carl Watner
1986

The twentieth century libertarian movement has experienced an ongoing debate between the minarchists, the advocates of “limited” government, and the anarchists, who argue that the ultimate implications of libertarian principles are “no” government. Few of the parties to these arguments realize that they are participating in a discussion whose roots can be traced back well over three centuries. Nor do they realize how the argument has shifted over time. In the beginning, those who defended existing governments argued for state absolutism and the divine right of kings. Their opponents argued that no persons could be bound in a political sense except by their own consent. The argument that the “ruled” had individual rights meant that the monarch ought not to violate those rights. In response, the divine-rightists or patriarchialists, as they became known, urged that such a “limited” government or “mixed monarchy,” as they called it, was a contradiction in terms. These critics offered “no”-government-anarchy as the reductio ad absurdum of individual rights and government by consent. As Oliver Cromwell so aptly put it, at the time of the Putney Debates in 1647: “The consequences of this rule tends to anarchy, must end in anarchy.”[l] In the English-speaking part of the world, the “limited” government versus anarchy controversy has evolved in at least three stages. The first stage was the critique by such people as Sir Robert Filmer[a] (and later the opponents of the Levellers, as we have noted above) and others that government by consent led straight to anarchy. In this phase of the discussion, there were as yet no defenders of anarchy–only defenders of limited government and their opponents, the patriarchalists. The second stage of the controversy witnessed both the moral and practical triumph of the libertarian ideal (especially after the success of the Glorious Revolution of 1688 and the American Revolution in 1783) that each person is unique and possesses proprietorial rights over him- or herself. Only the most dyed-in-the wool statist could continue to argue after those victories that no one should have any say in the political matters affecting him- or herself. Whereas the absolutists had argued that the people had no rights, eventually it became commonplace to recognize that they did have rights, even if their “life, liberty, and property” could be entrenched upon in certain situations. Although as late as the 1780s the ideal of government by consent seems to have won the day, it would still be difficult to find any proponents of the social ideal of anarchy.

Finally, after nearly a century and a half of discourse, there arose a group of radical thinkers who were brave enough actually to brandish the reductio ad absurdum of anarchy. This constituted the third phase of the limited- versus no- government controversy. People like William Godwin were prepared to accept the logical implications of their beginning premises, namely, that no outside coercive authority had any jurisdiction over the nonconsenting individual and that each person should be left totally free of coercive molestation. Godwin and the individualist-anarchist movement he spawned realized that “to contend that consent is the moral justification for government is to lay the groundwork for anarchy.”[2] Subsequent thinkers explained the various moral and practical ramifications of anarchy, but the point had finally been reached where anarchism was set against any and all forms of government. Unknowingly or not, latter-day anarchists repeated many of the arguments originated by Sir Robert Filmer to explain why no government could ever be “limited.” Many political theorists were caught on the horns of this dilemma. On the one hand, they believed in government by consent and in individual rights, but on the other, they were not prepared to accept the anarchist implications raised by either Filmer or Godwin. In order to try to salvage their own position, thinkers like John Locke developed and relied upon the doctrine of “tacit” consent to prove that existing governments did in fact rest on some son of consent. “Tacit” consent meant that one accepted the government one lived under simply because one continued to live in the geographic area over which it maintained jurisdiction. Owning property according to governmental law and using government services of one sort or another indicated one’s support. “To trace the history of the tacit consent doctrine is to trace” the “tortuous route whereby political theorists . . . attempted to void the anarchistic implications” of their consent doctrines.[3]

The basic issues in the anarchy versus limited-government debate are the same now as they were over 300 years ago. The only difference is that radical libertarianism bas advanced to the point where the reductio argument is no longer that but is a position it willingly accepts and defends. If consent is to mean anything, it must mean the explicit voluntary consent of each and every person over whom government exercises control. Since no government can document that it rests on individual consent and since payment of taxes is not voluntary, no government can demonstrate that it has the consent of the governed (otherwise the imposition of physical force, and the threat of physical force, to collect taxes would not be necessary). Three hundred years ago this was a novel argument used by the defenders of kings to discredit their limited-government opponents, but it is now a perfectly valid argument used by the no-government defenders of anarchy. This, then, is one of the purposes of this paper: to show how the early critics of consent theory argued that such ideas inevitably led to anarchism. Other purposes of this paper are to (1) describe the historical development of consent theory in general, and (2) demonstrate how this theory has become part and parcel of the radical libertarian tradition.

Probably the earliest glimmerings of consent theory in English history are found in A Shorte Treatise of Politike Power, written by John Ponet in 1556. Ponet (1516?-1556) was a Cambridge scholar who eventually became an English bishop and then, with the accession of Queen Mary to the throne in 1553, went into exile. His treatise was concerned with “the true obedience which subjects owe to their kings and other civil governors” and propounded a series of political questions: “whether kings, princes, and other governors have an absolute power and authority over their subjects,” “whether kings, princes and other politic governors be subject to God’s laws, and the positive laws of their countries,” “in and what things, and how far subjects are bound to obey their princes and governors,” “whether all the subjects’ goods be the kaisers and kings own, and that they may lawfully take as their own,” and finally “whether it be lawful to depose an evil governor, and kill a tyrant.”[4]

Ponet’s answers, although couched in a radical Protestant religious posture, nonetheless form the basis for a nonsecular, natural rights approach. Quentin Skinner, a twentieth century historian of this era, refers to their “anarchic implications”: “With citations from both the civil and canon laws, Ponet argues that the crimes of a ruler who exceeds the bounds of his office are in fact no different–and ought to be treated no differently–from the same crimes when committed by ordinary citizens. ‘If a prince rob and spoil his subjects, it is theft, and as a theft ought to be punished.’ And ‘if he kill and murder them contrary or without the laws of his country, it is murder, and as a murderer he ought to be punished.’ ‘And those that be judges in commonwealths, ought (upon complaint) to summon and cite them to answer to their crimes, and so to proceed, as they do with others.’”[5]

Ponet’s biographer, Winthrop S. Hudson, notes that his “writer becomes somewhat emotional as be thinks of those ‘evil princes’ who ‘claim all their subjects goods for their own.’ . . . To them he cites the example of Naboth refusing to sell his vineyard to the king, affirming that he rightly ‘refused to sell it, as he might do, for by God’s law he had a property therein, from which without his will and consent, he could not be forced to depart.'”[6]

The idea of consent played a prominent part in Ponet’s thinking. His view of natural law led to a restriction on the power of kings and governors, who derived their authority from the people. “Neither pope, Emperor, nor king may do any thing to the ‘hurt’ of his people without their consent,” nor may any king or prince break or dispense with the positive laws “but with the consent of the people.’”[7] The institution of government and its magisterial offices are in the nature of a trust, which ultimately rests upon the consent of the governed.

 

Is any man so unreasonable to deny, that the whole may do as much as they
have permitted one member to do? Or those that have appointed an office
upon trust, have not authority upon just occasion (as the abuse of it)
to take away that they gave? All laws do agree that men may revoke their
proxies and letters of Attorney, when it pleaseth them: much more when
they see their proctors and anomies abuse it.[8]

 

It was not understood until the heyday of Lysander Spooner some 300 years later that this view of civil authority as “merely a delegation of power which might be revoked when it was abused” might be used to destroy the very concept of political representation.[9] It was certainly used by Ponet and other sixteenth century thinkers to justify tyrannicide.[10] “To affirm, as Ponet does, that a private man may kill a magistrate is, to be sure, nothing less than the rankest anarchy.”[11] Ponet made the people (and by the people, Ponet included the poor) custodians of natural and divine law with the power to enforce it, by means of establishing that form of government they thought most conducive to their interests. When their governors and kings violated their trust, then they forfeited their power, whether they relinquished their positions voluntarily or whether they had to be removed forcefully.

Although Ponet was not an oft-quoted theorist during the century following his death, his Shorte Treatise was republished twice during the Puritan era. “By virtue of these two editions of 1639 and 1642, it is evident that Ponet was still a living source of ideas in the seventeenth century.”[12] His authorship of the tract was not well known, and in fact it was not until after the American Revolution that Ponet actually received the recognition due him. “By that time a charge of rebellion made little difference, and so John Adam felt no hesitation in quoting from the 1556 edition and declaring that it “contains all the essentials of liberty which were afterwards dilated on by Sidney and Locke.”[13]

Although there is no evidence that Ponet used the word “anarchy” or any of its derivatives, there is proof that the term was used to identify the “absence of government” and “a state of lawlessness” or “political disorder” by other sixteenth and seventeenth century writers. The term itself may have been derived from the medieval Latin anarchia and the French anarchie, which were cited by Randle Cotgrave’s A Dictionary of the French and English Tongues, published in 1611. The earliest entry for the use of the word “anarchy” in The Oxford English Dictionary is from the 1552 edition of Richard Taverner’s Proverbs or Adages with New Additions, Gathered out of the Chiliades of Erasmus, originally published in 1539: “This unlawful liberty or licence of the multitude is called an Anarchy.”[14] By the 1640s in England it was common to find the word “anarchy” being used quite seriously. In a tract entitled The Resolving of Conscience (1642), attacking the social contract theory of government, Henry Ferne wrote that if the doctrine of the original power of the people “must be a Fundamentall” then “it is such a one as upon it this government cannot be built, but confusion and anarchy may be readily raised.”[15] Clement Walker in his Anarchia Anglicana, or The History of Independency, The Second Part (1649) referred to those “who under colour of merchandise vent antimonarchical and anarchical tenets.”[16]

The term “anarchy” was apparently not confined to the political sphere for there was an early realization of the connection between religious freedom and liberty of conscience and political freedom. “Preaching before the House of Commons on 26th May 1647, Thomas Case denounced liberty of conscience as opening the floodgates of anarchy.” In his sermon, “Spiritual Whoredom Discovered,” Case said that if you publish liberty of conscience as one of the people’s rights then

 

see . . . how long your civil peace will secure you when religion is
destroyed. . . . For no doubt if this once be granted them . . . they
may in good time come to know also–there be them that are instructing
them even in these principles, too–that it is their birthright to be
freed from the power of parliaments and . . . kings. . . . Liberty of
conscience (falsely so called) may in time improve itself into liberty
of estates and . . . houses and . . . wives, and in a word liberty of
perdition of souls and bodies.”[17]

 

This “anarchy of religious freedom” was noted by other contemporary writers. Henry Parker in 1644 in his Liberty of Conscience: Or the Sole Means to Obtain Peace and Truth noted that liberty for men to teach what they will, will result in many false doctrines and teachers. “Yet it were better that many false doctrines were published . . . then that one sound truth should be forcibly smothered or willfully concealed.” This “complying with weak consciences or the tolerating of several opinions”, as Parker termed it, was not any “sort of Libertinism,” for it was the only means of arriving at truth.[18]

This was one of the main themes of the English radicals of the mid-seventeenth Century: that liberty of conscience was one of the natural rights of man. There was nothing that the Levellers “held with more tenacity than liberty of conscience.”[19] Case was right in pointing out the anarchic implications of this doctrine, for the supporters of liberty of conscience realized that it was impossible to assert one’s right of private judgment without upholding the same right for everyone else. In the religious sphere this meant that guaranteeing the liberty of the regenerate necessitated guaranteeing the liberty of all. This was one of the main contributions of Puritanism to the doctrine of general liberty.[20] These radicals also observed a direct connection between their churches and the civil state. Their entire doctrine of Christian liberty insisted upon the importance of consent as opposed to conformity and called into question the end or reason of their social organizations. Richard Overton, for example, in An Arrow Against All Tyrants , written in 1646, noted:

 

For by natural birth all men are equal, . . . born to like propriety,
liberty and freedom, and as we were delivered of God by the hand of
nature into this world, every one with a natural innate freedom and
propriety, . . . even so we are to live, every one equally . . . to
enjoy his birthright and privilege, even all whereof God by nature
hath made him free. . . . Every man by nature being a king, priest,
prophet, in his own natural circuit and compass, whereof no second
may partake but by deputation, commission, and free consent from him
whose right and freedom it is.[21]

 

During the late sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, many radical religious sects employed the device of a church covenant. This was sometimes an implicit, but usually an explicit congregational agreement by which those voluntarily enrolling in a particular church pledged themselves to the faith. Familiarity with the idea of church covenant and with the principles it embodied “helped establish in the civil sphere the doctrine of the social contract and government by consent.”[22] The church in this view was a voluntary association of equals and undoubtedly furnished a model for the civil state. The church preserved the free form of community and enabled (or at least aided) it to influence by analogy the theory of the state. The Levellers brought to their conception of the state, their views about church organization. “If the Leveller emphasizes the contract on which the authority of just government depends and insists on the principle of consent, he has had in his church, experiences of a community organized on these very principles.”[23]

It was only a small step for the Levellers to conclude that if the voluntary church was the only true church, then the only true political organization was the voluntary state. They moved quite close to a voluntaryist conception of the church, and a Leveller petition of March 1647 went so far as to urge “that tithes and all other enforced maintainences may be for ever abolished, and nothing in place thereof imposed, but that ministers may be paid only by those who voluntarily choose them, and contract with them for their labours.”[24] By substituting “taxes” for “tithes” and “government officials” for “ministers,” we can see how close these early religious dissenters were to espousing a truly voluntary state. Latter-day thinkers were left to question: If men’s spiritual health could be left to the free reign of voluntary forces, why could not men’s physical well-being be left to the free market? Clearly these early advocates of church-state segregation were in the vanguard of the libertarian tradition because they took one of the first steps necessary to separate the state from the rest of society. They did this by declaring themselves four-square for liberty of conscience and religious freedom, and government by consent.[25]

The Levellers, by the principles of their religious thinking, were “thrown back wholly on the law of nature in the civil sphere.”[26] They admitted no sovereignty anywhere except in the individual and “seriously accepted the possibility of any man refusing obedience to commands imcompatible with his ideas of reason or justice. This may appear anarchic, but to them it was the ultimate guarantee of liberty.”[27] The Leveller leaders, such as John Lilburne and Richard Overton, saw the English nation as having been reduced to the original law of nature as a result of the tyranny of Charles I and the usurpations of Oliver Cromwell. They proposed that a new political settlement be made in which all Englishmen would give their consent to the Agreement of the People. The Agreement was a written document, the forerunner of written “constitutions,” which was to be superior to Parliament. The Levellers hoped that it would be unanimously accepted by members of the army and then be signed by the people at large at the first general election. It plainly illustrates the Levellers’ premise that society could be constituted on an entirely voluntary basis.[28]

The Putney Debates, which took place October 28–November 1,1647, placed the Levellers against Cromwell, Ireton (his son-in-law and chief spokesman), and the other army grandees. The debates illustrate the radical nature of Leveller thought and their reliance on both consent and state-of-nature theory. Ireton declared that the Levellers could ground their demand for manhood suffrage only on some plea of natural rights as opposed to the historic rights held forth by the supporters of the fundamental English state. They did not deny the fact. When Ireton claimed that the Levellers would destroy all property, they confidently appealed to the law of nature to demonstrate that the right to property is guaranteed by the law of nature, and not, as Ireton maintained, merely by positive government laws. Clarke, one of the Leveller debaters, argued that the law of nature is the basis of all constitutions,

 

yet really properties are the foundation of constitutions, and not
constitutions of property. For if so be there were no constitutions,
yet the Law of Nature does give a principle for every man to have a
property of what he has, or may have, which is not another man’s.
This natural right to property is the ground of ‘meum’ and ‘tuum.’[29]

 

Furthermore it is the law of nature that teaches the individual his rights and attendant duties: the right and duty of self-preservation, the natural limits of obedience, and the right and duty of resistance to tyrannical rulers. It teaches him what are the ends of government; and it inculcates the basic principles of social life–the principles of natural justice and equity that dictate the political equality of all men within the state and that are also based upon the biblical maxim “to do unto others as you would have them do unto you.”[30]

The reliance of the Leveller debaters on a theory of government by consent is quite explicit at some places. In a classic and oft-cited statement Rainborough affirmed his belief that “the poorest he that is in England hath a life to live, as the greatest he; and therefore truly, sir, I think it’s clear, that every man that is to live under a government ought first by his own consent to put himself under that government; and I do think that the poorest man in England is not at all bound in a strict sense to that government that he hath not had a voice to put himself under.”[31] John Wildman, another Leveller leader, plainly responded to Ireton:

 

I conceive that’s the undeniable maxim of government: that all government
is in the free consent of the people. If so, then upon that account there
is no person that is under a just government, or hath justly his own,
unless he has by his own free consent be put under that government.”[32]

 

There is a very striking example–found in a letter attributed to Wildman, which was issued at the time of the Putney Debates–of the invective used by the opponents of the Levellers. In “A Call to All the Soldiers of the Army by the Free People of England” (October 29, 1647), Wildman warned the soldiers not to “take heed of the crafty politicians and subtle Machiavellians.” If the soldiers did attend the meetings of the General Council of the army,

 

be ye not frighted by the word ‘anarchy’, unto a love of ‘monarchy’,
which is but the gilded name for ‘tyranny’; for anarchy had never been
so much as once mentioned amongst you had it not been for that wicked end.
‘Tis an old threadbare trick of the profane Court and doth amongst
discreet men show plainly who is for the Court and against the liberties
of the people, who, whensoever they positively insist for their just
freedoms, are immediately flapped in the mouths with these most malignant
reproaches:

Oh, ye are for anarchy. Ye are against all governments. Ye are sectaries,
seditious persons, troublers both of church and state, and so not worthy
to live in a commonwealth. There shall be a speedy course taken both
against you and such as you.”[33]

 

This is obvious proof that “anarchy” was a term of aspersion, even in the mid-seventeenth century. What is also interesting to note is that by that time the term had found itself in common usage in the political realm. The circumstances of the day (the Ship Money Controversy of 1634-1638 and the political turmoil and revolution of the early 1640s) dictated that at least one political theorist would realize that the theory of proprietary justice that the Levellers and other political Protestants were espousing would lead one to anarchism. Their fundamental position, insisting that property was a natural right of the individual and that each person was a self-owner, led directly to government by consent, civil and religious liberty, and ultimately to an incipient son of individualist anarchism. Sir Robert Filmer, in his tract Patriarcha, composed sometime between 1635 and 1642, was the first to note this anarchist tendency in this radical thought.

Despite the fact that Filmer (1588-1653) is perhaps best known as the royalist against whom Locke directed his Two Treatises, his treatment of consent theory has had a great deal to do with its development in English political thought.[34] He possessed an acute, critical mind and his chief biographer, Peter Laslett, has attributed “the destructive cast of his thought” to “his capacity for seeing straight through the arguments of other.”[35] His was the strongest case ever made in his own century against consent theory, and when his collected political works were published in 1680, “three of the ablest minds on the Whig side had set to work to refute patriarchalism.”[36] These were James Tyrell, Algernon Sidney, and John Locke, who were all as much concerned with his defense of royal absolutism as they were with his critique of government by consent. It was Filmer’s primary contention that “stable governments could not be based on consent” because they would always he in danger of having that consent withdrawn.[37] “Filmer’s critique included the recognition that free submission to government logically entailed the right of withdrawal through the same voluntary actions.”[38] Therefore, Filmer saw consent theory as an open invitation leading to constant anarchy.

Filmer left no integrated corpus of thought, and many of his ideas are originally set forth in his Patriarcha and then repeated in his later tracts. However, his most mature and explicit criticism of the anarchist implications of consent theory are found in his treatise, The Anarchy of a Limited or Mired Monarchy (1648), which was written as a rebuttal to Philip Hunton’s 1643 work, A Treatise of Monarchy.[39] Filmer’s main charge against Hunton was “that instead of a treatise of monarchy, he hath brought forth a treatise of anarchy.”[40]

In Patriarcha and in The Anarchy , Filmer argues that “by nature all mankind in the world makes but one people” who are all “born alike to an equal freedom from subjection.”[41] Since there are no natural political divisions in the world, Filmer concludes that “every man is at liberty to be of what kingdom he please.” Therefore,

 

every petty company hath a right to make a kingdom by itself; and not
only every city, but every village, and every family, nay, and ever
particular man, a liberty to choose himself to be his own King if he
please; and he were a madman that being by nature free, would choose
any man but himself to be his own governor. Thus to avoid the having
but of one King of the whole world, we shall run into a liberty of
having as many Kings as there be men in the world, which upon the matter,
is to have no King at all, but to leave all men to their natural liberty. . . .[42]

 

Of course Filmer’s point is that the right to secede from political society leads to anarchy and makes coercive political government an impossibility.[43] Filmer even went so far as to grant the seeming impossibility of all individuals having at one time agreed to their government. Even if this were so, Filmer demanded to know why this promise to abide by government could not be broken. Was a man prevented from withdrawing from a government once he had consented to it? “Who can say that such a man doth more than by right he may do?”[44] As Laslett observes, the right of any independent group of people “to set up their own political society without reference to the rest of mankind” inevitably implies a “universal, world-wide anarchy.”[45] If it ever be imagined, as the Levellers thought, that each person was a self-owner, free, independent, and equal with all other human beings, then it would prove an impossibility to introduce any kind of legitimate government into the world, at least without unanimous consent of all those affected.[46]

Nonetheless, Filmer saw the world divided into numerous commonwealths. The defenders of these countries argued that they were legitimated by majority rule and tacit consent. But Filmer questioned if it was ever possible for the members of the entire world to assemble at one time and consent to its political subdivision. Notwithstanding this being an impossibility, Filmer further argued that majority rule could bind no one and that a majority of the earth’s inhabitants (or even the majority of one country’s citizens) could not justify political rule. “No one man, nor a multitude, can give away the natural right of another. . . . The acts of multitudes not entire are not binding to all, but only to such as consent unto them.”[47]

Thus, in a very Spooneresque fashion, Filmer called into question the validity of majority rule and representative government. He said that “it cannot be showed or proved that all those that have been absent from popular elections did ever give their voices to some of their fellows.”[48] Therefore, those who do not participate in an election cannot legitimately be bound by its outcome. Nor could it be countered that the silence of those in opposition or the silence of those who did not vote could be construed as an acceptance of the election. The “tacit assent” of the whole commonwealth to every government is a plain political fact. Yet from that we cannot conclude “that every Prince that come to a crown, either by succession, conquest or usurpation, may be said to be” acceptable to the people.[49] The tacit consent doctrine argues too much. “To pretend that a major part, or the silent consent of any part, may be interpreted to bind the whole people, is both unreasonable and unnatural.”[50]

The supporters of consent theory argued that “the people” must consent to their government. This led such radicals as the Levellers to argue for universal manhood suffrage. Yet, as Filmer pointed out, what of women and children? Were they not “the people,” too?[51] Furthermore, Filmer was confounded by the question of how one generation of “the people” could bind future generations. “Mankind is like the sea, ever ebbing or flowing, every minute one is born another dies; those that are the people this minute, are not the people the next minute.”[52] If one person might be excluded, then the same reason that excludes that person might exclude many hundreds or thousands. Filmer, pushing consent theory to what he saw as a reductio posited that

 

if it be admitted, that the people are or ever were free by nature, and not
to be governed, but by their own consent, it is most unjust to exclude any
one man from his right in government; . . . for the whole people is a thing
so uncertain and changeable, that it alters every moment, so that it is
necessary to ask of every infant so soon as it is born its consent to government,
if you will ever have the consent of the whole people.[53]

 

One of the most original and insightful of Filmer’s commentaries occurs in his Observations Concerning the Originall of Government and is repeated in his “Preface” to The Anarchy. His point is that all government, by its very nature, is arbitrary, so it really makes no different what form government takes.

 

We flatter ourselves if we hope ever to be governed without an arbitrary
power. No: we mistake; the question is not whether there shall be an
arbitrary power, whether one man or many? There never was, nor ever can
be any people governed without a power of making laws, and every power of
making laws must be arbitrary.”
[54]

 

Thus Filmer totally rejects the idea of a lawful government; “he repudiates at one fell swoop the idea of a ‘government of laws, not of men’ and its historical but not logical concomitant, the belief that a popular government cannot be arbitrary” because it is based on the will of the people.[55] As Filmer logically points out, “if it be tyranny for one man to govern arbitrarily, why should it not be far greater tyranny for a multitude of men to govern . . . ? It would be further inquired how it is possible for any government at all to be in the world without an arbitrary power; it is not power except it be arbitrary. . . .”[56] Not only does Filmer emphasize that it is impossible to get away from the fact that government by its very nature is arbitrary, but he identifies the “law-making” features of government as the essence of its arbitrariness. In an argument foreshadowing Spooner’s “Essay on Natural Law,” Filmer identifies perhaps the most tyrannical feature of all governments: their claims to make laws for the people.

Finally, Filmer presents us with one last argument demonstrating the anarchist implications of consent theory. Filmer found no constitutional solution to the problem of anarchy; for even a limited government or “mixed monarchy,” as he termed it, was a contradiction in terms. Sovereignty must reside either in the people or in their monarch. It cannot be shared by both. Thus Hunton in his essay on monarchy caught himself “in a plain dilemma”:

 

If the King be judge, then he is no limited monarch; if the people be judge,
then he is no monarch at all. So farewell limited monarchy, nay farewell all
government, if there be no judge.[37]

 

If every man’s conscience is the arbiter of the fundamental controversies, if the appeal must be to the community at large to settle disputes with the monarch, then as Filmer concluded, “The wit of man cannot say more for anarchy.”[58] In Filmer’s opinion, the end result of this would be “utter confusion and anarchy.”[59]

This review of Filmer’s arguments demonstrates why his political tracts have an importance far surpassing the mere fact that Locke wrote in rebuttal to his Patriarcha. Filmer questioned the principle essential to all accounts of political obligation other than his own, the principle of consent.[60] Perhaps, it could be argued that Locke realized Filmer’s uncanny and unerring ways of pushing consent arguments to their radical anarchist conclusions required their own answer. But the fact remains that Locke’s efforts seem to have gone for naught.

Locke presented us with a mixed bag of answers in The Two Treatises of Government. One of the problems he had in his mind was the problem of the legitimacy of political communities, both past and present. How was it that many, many centuries ago, and while still in a state of nature, men came to form political institutions? And what, if any, bearing did their actions have on contemporary governments? In Locke’s writings the purpose of political authority was to protect life, liberty, and property of the citizenry. So long as these protections were offered by an agency that drew its authority from the consent of the people and did not degenerate into absolutism, political obligation appears to have been complete, according to Locke’s thinking.[61]

“To Locke there was no question ‘That the beginning of Politick Society depends upon the consent of the Individuals, to joyn into and make one Society,’ and he believed that reason and history clearly showed that ‘the Governments of the World, that were begun in Peace, . . . were made by the Consent of the People.’ “[62] Locke distinguished two sorts of consent “which subject an individual to the laws of a legitimate political society.”[63] For Locke, the question of how one becomes a member of a state, and why one is obliged to obey it were separate questions. His use of the concepts of tacit and explicit consent helped illustrate this. Membership was limited to those who had expressly consented. “Express consent demands the making of some overt sign of agreement by the consenting party to the legitimacy of the social structure which he himself intends to be taken as a promise to obey the rules in the future. An oath of allegiance taken to a king is an obvious example. . . .”[64] Nonmembers, but residents in the geographic area over which the state exercised jurisdiction, incurred their obligations by giving tacit consent. “Tacit consent is incurred,” according to Locke, “by anyone who voluntarily takes advantage of the resources of the country.”[65] One’s physical presence in the country’s territory is a sufficient condition for being held in this way to have consented tacitly.[66]

One of Locke’ s basic premises, to which he reverts frequently throughout The Second Treatise, is that “Every Man being, as has been shewed, naturally free, and nothing being able to put him into subjection to any Earthly Power, but only his own Consent. . . .” Therefore, Locke wishes to inquire what “it is to be considered . . . shall be understood to be a sufficient Declaration of a Man’s Consent, to make him subject to the Laws of any Government’? Locke answers:

 

No body doubts but an express consent, of any Man, entering into any society,
makes him a perfect member of that society, a subject of that Government.
The difficulty is, what ought to be looked upon as a tacit Consent, and how
far it bind, ie, how far any one shall be looked on to have consented and
thereby submitted to government, where he has made no expressions of it at all.
And to this I say that every Man that hath any possession or enjoyment of any
part of the dominions of any government doth thereby give his tacit consent,
and is as far forth obliged to obedience to the laws of that government during
such enjoyment as any one under it; whether this possession be of land to him
and his heirs forever, or a lodging only for a week, or whether it be barely
travelling freely over the highways and in effect it reaches as far as the
very being of anyone within the territories of that government.[67]

 

Locke clearly recognizes that exclusive territorial sovereignty is one of the characteristics of government. Everyone living within a given geographic area is subject to the jurisdiction of that area’s government. Locke indirectly realizes that the alternative to this would be anarchy, for he writes, “For it would he a direct contradiction, for any one, to enter into Society with others . . . And yet to suppose his Land, whose Property is to be regulated by the Laws of the Society, should be exempt from the Jurisdiction of that Government.”[68] Therefore Locke concludes that when one unites “his Person” to any commonwealth, “by the same he unites his Possessions, . . . and they become, both of them, Person and Possession, subject to the Government and Dominion of that Commonwealth. . . .”[69]

If we are to assign any meaning to Locke’s doctrine of consent, it is clear that people must have the opportunity to consent or not consent as they please. The only provision for not consenting in Locke’s treatise is emigration from the commonwealth. This is Locke’s escape from tyranny, for if people “are not permitted to emigrate, they can hardly be said to have consented.” Emigration is a logical necessity within the framework of Locke’s theory of consent, because without it, the whole theory loses its viability.[70] What Locke says is this: “The Obligation any one is under, by Virtue of such enjoyment, to submit to the government, begins and ends with the Enjoyment; so that whenever the Owner, who has given nothing but such a tacit consent to the Government, will . . . quit the said Possession, he is at liberty to go and incorporate himself into any other commonwealth,” or to begin another one.” Thus, emigration should be a right every person should enjoy at every moment, unless he has committed himself to the commonwealth forever.[72]

Unfortunately for Locke’s theory, his recognition of the right to emigration and to shed one’s citizenship was not even recognized in his own day. Locke writes as though no persons born in the English commonwealth, or of English parents abroad, acquire their citizenship until they consent to become members of the Commonwealth, “as each comes to Age.”[73] He claims that it is the practice of governments, “as well as by the Law of right Reason, that a Child is born a subject of no Country or Government,” particularly in the case of English parents bearing a child in France.[74]

The truth of the matter is that governmental practice and the common law of allegiance had already developed to such a point in Locke’s time that no child born within England, of parents who were subject to its jurisdiction, had any choice in the matter of what citizenship it acquired. They were considered to be English subjects by birth, by the mere fact of being born within the realm. Nor were English subjects permitted to shed their English citizenship at will, without the permission of the King. “The fundamental principle of the common law with regard to English nationality was birth within allegiance . . . and at common law it was firmly established that no citizen or subject possessed the power of throwing off his allegiance without the sovereign’s consent.”[75] Even “those born abroad of English parents, share the status of English subjects.” One’s status as a subject is ordinarily indelible and cannot be shed at will.[76] This was what it meant to be an English citizen throughout the seventeenth century. These interpretations had been confirmed by Calvin’s Case in 1609, so surely Locke should have been aware that his theories did not meet the common law decisions. Emigration at Locke’s time did not ordinarily permit the shedding of citizenship.[77]

We should not be surprised that Locke’s doctrine of tacit consent cannot be taken seriously. It was not good scholarship, even in his own day, nor did it really provide a logically consistent response to the problem of political obligation. It was no more than a saving hypothesis “brought in to meet the difficulty that in fact men do not expressly declare their consent to the regime under which they live. All that (really) remains of Locke’s teaching is that legitimate governments are those that secure the voluntary obedience of their subjects.”[78]

Despite the problems with Locke’s doctrine of consent, “his commitment to what he called consent is unassailable.”[79] There is no question as to what he wrote; the only question is, Did he really mean what he said? “But I moreover affirm, that all Men are naturally in that State [the state of nature] and remain so, till by their own Consents they make themselves member of some Political Society. . . .”[80] And again, “Men being, as has been said, by Nature, all free, equal and independent, no one can be put out of this Estate, and subjected to the Political Power of Another, without his own Consent.”[81]

Yet at the same time, Locke was familiar with the thrust of Filmer’s reductios and saw where his own doctrine was leading him. As Locke put it, “For if the consent of the majority shall not in reason, be received, as the act of the whole, and conclude every individual; nothing but the consent of every individual can make any thing to be the act of the whole: But such a consent is next impossible ever to be had. . . . Such a Constitution as this would make the mighty Leviathan of a shorter duration, than the feeblest Creatures; and not let it outlast the day it was born in. . . .” [82] Locke clearly realized that his own theory of consent, strictly interpreted, would lead to anarchy. His only wav out was to make “consent” include an agreement to abide by majority rule. “Whosoever . . . united into a Community, must be understood to give up all the power . . . to the majority of the Community. . .”[83]

Locke’s outlook on property also wrestled with the problem of consent. “The Supream Power cannot take from any Man any part of His Property without his own consent.”[84] Could one’s property be taken from him against his will, as when taxes are levied and collected? Locke answered this problem in the following manner. He realized that the right to collect funds coercively was one of the most important needs of a government: “Tis true, Governments cannot be supported without great Charge, and tis fit every one who enjoys his share of the Protection, should pay out of his Estate in proportion for the maintenance of it. But still it must be with his own Consent, i.e., the Consent of the Majority, giving it either by themselves, or their Representatives chosen by them.”[85]

It is plain that The Two Treatises is open to at least two readings: Locke, the individualist, whose consent theory leads to a radical libertarianism; and Locke, the conservative, who was attempting to justify the English political institutions of his time. It was not so long after the appearance of The Two Treatises in 1689 that Locke’s ideas were used to justify the radical position. “The transposition of Locke’s doctrine” to other political settings “did indeed have subversive implications,” for within a decade of the book’s appearance, its author and his ideas were used to support the rights of the Irish parliament and Irish people.[86] William Molyneux (1656-1698) was an Irish friend and correspondent of Locke’s, who represented Dublin University in the Irish parliament. During the late 1690s he was concerned with the effect of the recent legislation of the English parliament on the woolen and linen industries in Ireland. This and his correspondence with Locke led him in 1698 to publish “The Case of Ireland’s Being Bound by Acts of Parliament in England Stated.” His basic purpose was to prove the legislative independence of the Irish parliament, and in doing this, he resorted to Locke’s treatise as a justification for his position. “Molyneux used the book and named Locke as its author at a time when Locke refused to acknowledge it even in private, and without asking his permission.”[87] The book created a stir in the English House of Commons, and a committee was appointed to investigate it for suspicions of treason. The committee “unanimously resolved ‘that the said book was of dangerous consequence to the crown and parliament of England.’ “[88] History has it that Molyneux’s book was ordered to be burned by the common Hangman.[89 ]

What was it that made Molyneux’s book such a threat? Quite simply it was his insistence on a literal interpretation of Locke’s consent theory. His critics realized that it led straight toward anarchy. The heart of Molyneux’s argument sounds remarkably Lockean and anarchist. He wrote:

 

I shall venture to assert, that the Right of being subject only to such
laws, to which Men give their ‘own’ Consent, is so ‘inherent’ in ‘all’
Mankind, and founded on such ‘immutable’ Laws of Nature and Reason,
that ’tis not to be aliened, or given up by any Body of Men whatever. . . .
I have no other Notion of ‘Slavery’; but being bound by Law, to
which I do not consent.[90]

 

Molyneux clearly understood the relationship between property rights and consent. “Consent is a necessary condition for the transfer of title. To use or dispose of another person’s property without his consent is the fundamental act of injustice.”[91] According to Molyneux:

 

The Obligation of all Laws have the same Foundation, if ‘One’ Law may be
imposed ‘without Consent’, any ‘Other’ Law whatever, may be imposed on us
‘without our Consent’. This will naturally introduce ‘Taxing us without
our Consent’; and this as necessarily destroys our ‘Property.’ I have no
other Notion of ‘Property’, but a ‘Power of Disposing my Goods as I please’,
and not as another shall Command: Whatever another may ‘Rightfully’ take
from me ‘without my Consent’, I have certainly no ‘Property’ in. To ‘Tax’
me without Consent, is little better, if at all, than ‘downright Robbing me’.[92]

 

Molyneux was probably the first to explicitly relate these main elements of proprietary justice. Clearly there was no difference between taxation and robbery, if consent was unnecessary in the former case. Perhaps Molyneux would not have applied his theory in typical anarchist fashion to delegitimize all government (for he was arguing for an all-Irish parliament, which in all likelihood would itself have powers of taxation). Nonetheless, his ideas and reputation did survive his own death and were repeatedly “taken up with each burst of Irish national sentiment throughout the century, by Swift, Charles Lucas, by Garran and Pollock, even eventually by Wolf Tone.”[93]

Other than Molyneux’s claims for the Lockean theory of consent, its application to the colonial relationships within the British Empire remained unexamined for the most part until the 1760s. Most theorists, applying Locke’s doctrine of tacit consent, saw no incongruity between the legislative sovereignty of the English parliament and the conventional theory of Whig politics, which in turn was largely premised on The Two Treatises. The opponents of Molyneux in 1698 based their argument on the idea that emigration removed the right of direct representation in the English parliament. This eliminated the requirement for the émigrés’ explicit consent to the acts of the parliament in England.[94]

Throughout the eighteenth century, Locke’s idea of emigration and the idea of tacitly consenting to one’s government by maintaining residence within the geographic area of its jurisdiction were ridiculed as an unsound theory. Indeed Adam Smith in his Lectures on Justice. Police, Revenue, and Arms (circa 1763) argued that most people under the dominion of a government cannot be said to give consent to that government, in the sense that they would, consent to a contract. “To say that by staying in a country a man agrees to a contract of obedience to government is just the same with carrying a man into a ship and after he is at a distance from land to tell him that by being in the ship he has contracted to obey the master.”[95] David Hume, fifteen years earlier, asserted in his essay “Of the Original Contract” that it was ridiculous to claim “that political connexions are founded altogether on voluntary consent or mutual promise.” (“The magistrate would soon imprison you as seditious for loosening the ties of obedience, if your friends did not before shut you up as delirious for advancing such absurdities.”)[96]

 

Can we seriously say that a poor peasant or artisan has a free choice to leave
his country, when he knows no foreign language or manners, and lives from day to
day by the small wages which he acquires? We may as well assert that a man, by
remaining in a vessel, freely consents to the dominion of the master, though he
was carried on board while asleep, and must leap into the ocean and perish the
moment he leaves her.[97]

 

Hume concluded that if tacit consent and the obligation of obedience, which it entails, reached all the inhabitants of a territory, then the most outrageous tyrant could be said to govern with the consent of his subjects.[98] “If consent could be watered down like this, it would lose all value as a guarantee of individual liberty.”[99]

Perhaps the most interesting of the eighteenth century Lockean commentators was Josiah Tucker, who in A Treatise Concerning Civil Government (1781) “opined that Locke neglected to carry the consent doctrine to its logical end–i.e., anarchism.”[l00] Tucker (1713-1799) was a British clergyman with great interest in economic and political matters. He was an avid pamphleteer and polemicist. As matters were coming to the point of rebellion in the North American colonies, Tucker wrote of the American revolutionists as the “most ungrateful, ungovernable, and rebellious people” he had ever known.[l0l] He claimed that the Americans were virtually represented in parliament and “he never doubted the right to tax them.”[l02] Nevertheless, he took the unpopular stand, even before the outbreak of the revolution, that the American colonies should be allowed their independence. Their forceful inclusion in the British Empire would only lead to both political and economic disruption for Britain herself and was therefore to be avoided.

Despite the fact that he refused to support the subjugation of the colonies by force, the appeal of the Americans to Locke’s right of revolution “filled him with anxious forebodings.”[l03] As early as 1775, he declared that “Locke’s principles of government, if carried out as the Americans construed them, would destroy every government on earth.”[104] In 1778 he circulated a manuscript, “The Notions of Mr. Locke and His Followers . . . Considered and Examined,” which he later used in the preparation of his major work, A Treatise Concerning Civil Government (published 1781). To Tucker, the phrase “consent of the governed” was simply one “loaded with dynamite.”[105] He assailed the Lockeans first for thinking that their form of government by consent was the only true government and then for not living up to their very own principles. He viciously pointed out that the American revolutionaries, who claimed liberty for themselves, refused to liberate their slaves or extend the franchise to include unpropertied men or women. In proving that the adherents of Locke pushed his principles to a reductio ad absurdum, Tucker quoted Molyneux, and other late eighteenth century supporters of Locke, such as Joseph Priestly and Richard Price. Tucker referred to Sir Robert Filmer, but only in a derogatory way.[106]

Tucker was fully aware of all the implications to be drawn from the Lockean system, and it was those implications, more than anything else, that made him fearful of its advocacy. He clearly saw the integral relationship between taxes, government, and slavery. Tucker claimed that the declarations of the Lockeans ultimately reduced themselves to the pronouncement “that the very Essence of Slavery doth consist in being governed by Laws, to which the Governed have not previously consented.” 107] And he realized that if governments were to exist at all then “we must submit to Taxes” (which he clearly comprehended were compulsory levies and not voluntary contributions) because there was no other way of supporting them.[l08]

 

But say the Lockians, Taxes are the Free-Gift of the People:–Nay, they are the
Free-Gift of each Individual among the People: “For even the Supreme Power
(the Legislature) cannot (lawfully or justly) take from any Man any Part of his
Property without his own Consent.” This is Mr. Locke’s own Declaration.
And Mr. Molyneux corroborates it by another still stronger, viz. “To tax
me without my Consent is little better, if at all, than down-right robbing me.
” In short all the Lockians hold one and the same Language on this Head:
And therefore you must take their favourite Maxim for granted, or you will incur
their high Displeasure: “You are an Advocate for Despotism, if you do not
acquiesce in this Maxim: You attempt to defend what is down-right Robbery.[109]

 

Tucker viewed the Lockean system and the American revolution that it spawned as a “universal Demolisher of all Civil Governments, but not the builder of any.”[110] The root of the American rebellion was to be found in the premise that “the imposing of Laws on them of any Kind, whether good or bad in themselves, and whether for the Purposes of Taxation, or for other Purposes, without their own Consent, is . . . a most intolerable Grievance! a Robbery! and an Usurpation on the unalienable Rights of Mankind.”[111]

 

In short, the brave American were resolved not to be Slaves; but Slaves, it
seems, they must have been (according to the Lockian Idea) had they acknowledged
the Right of the Mother Country, even in a single Instance, to make Laws to bind
them without their Consent:–I say, even in a single Instance; for the Lockian
Mode of Reasoning is, that there is no Difference between being vested with
discretionary Power, and with a despotic Power. “Inasmuch as, if a Government
has any Right to rule me without my Consent in some Cases, it has a Right to rule
me in every Case; consequently it has a Right to levy every Kind of Tax, god or bad,
reasonable or exorbitant upon me, and to inflict all Sorts of Punishments whatever.”[112]

 

Tucker’s concept of government depended on the idea of quasi-contract or trust, on the obligation of subject and king to perform their implied duties. Reason, common sense, and the known laws of the land all coincided to reinforce the reciprocal duties of subject and governor in a manner unacceptable to those who rejected the tacit consent doctrine. One of Tucker’s insightful observations was that the objection of those who rested their arguments on “explicit consent” (as opposed to the recognition of a quasi-contract or tacit consent) was that their real objections were not so much against the law themselves or the manner in which they were administered, but rather against the “Right, Title, or Authority to make, or to execute any Laws at all, be they in themselves good or bad.”[113] The sole question between Tucker and his Lockean opponents was “Whether That Government is to be justly deemed an Usurpation, which is not founded on express mutual Compact of all the Parties interested therein, or belonging thereunto?”[114] Anarchists who took the Lockean notions to their logical finality were not concerned with the goodness or badness of governmental laws, but rather with the ultimate title or authority of governments themselves to legislate any laws at all. As Tucker puts it, “For the sole Point here to be determined, is simply this.–Had the Makers of such a Law any Right to make it, according to the Lockian Ideas of Right and Wrong?”[115]

To the anarchist, a man is a slave who is required to submit even to the best of laws or the mildest government that ever existed.[116] Coercion is still coercion regardless of how mildly it is administered. A man is free who submits to no one or no group of people, except as be himself has consented to it. “So the great Good of political Liberty, and the intolerable Evil of political Slavery, are according to the blessed Doctrine, resolved at last into the single Words–Consent, or Not Consent. . . .”[117] Although Tucker did not defend the anarchist conclusions of the Lockean principles, he was logician enough to see where they led. It was this power of mind that gives him, the non-libertarian, a place in the libertarian history of the consent doctrine.

The radical abolitionists of the mid-nineteenth century incorporated the ideas of explicit consent into their attacks on slavery. Not only was slavery a violation of the slave’s self-ownership rights, but it was obvious that people were forced into, and retained in, slavery against their will. Being held in bondage was a coercive situation, not one consented to by the slave. Being bound to pay taxes or support a coercive government was almost as evil as being made a slave. As Tucker pointed out, one of the earliest conclusions of the Lockeans, such as Molyneux, was that there was no other notion of slavery but being bound to a law to which one did not consent.

There are two interesting examples made of the idea of consent by well-known antislavery radicals in the 1840s. Henry David Thoreau, as early as 1840, was protesting the assumption that his parents’ membership in a church congregation automatically made him a member.
Continue to Part II

“Oh, Ye Are For Anarchy!”: Consent Theory in the Radical Libertarian Tradition – Part II


 

by Carl Watner
1986

 

(Much like the assumption that if one’s parents are English, one’s allegiance and citizenship are automatically British.) “In Thoreau’s day, the church taxed each member of its congregation, and the taxes were billed and collected by the town officials.”[118] The First Parish Church (Unitarian) of Concord “taxed” Thoreau in 1840, but he refused to pay. The tax was finally disallowed when at the request of some of the selectmen, Thoreau agreed to present them with the following statement: “Know all men by these presents, that I, Henry Thoreau, do not wish to be regarded as a member of any incorporated society which I have not joined.” Thoreau adds that “if I had known how to name them, I should then have signed off in detail from all the societies which I never signed on to; but I did not know where to find a complete list.”[119] One honestly wonders whether Thoreau ever considered himself as joining the Commonwealth of Massachusetts?

Thoreau’s friend and confidant Charles Lane, in his series of letters published in 1843 on “A Voluntary Political Government,” made a number of interesting comments about the meaning of citizenship. In a discussion of consent, Lane points out that the preamble to the state constitution of Massachusetts reads: “The body politic is formed by a voluntary association of individuals.” If this be the true case, Lane argues, then his advocacy of “voluntary political government” entails a principle already embraced by the Commonwealth of Massachusetts in her very own constitution. As Lane explains,

All, therefore, on behalf of which I am asserting may be summed up
as the restoration of the primary constitutional principle. I give
no strained or unusual value to the word “voluntary” on
this occasion. Either it means choice, or it means nothing at all.
If it does not assert the free voluntariness of every individual
who comes into “the body politic” it signifies nothing;
or at least nothing which common sense can lay hold of. If the
voluntariness is to be confined to those who have the power, and
they are to be at liberty to force every one into the association,
then I must esteem this word “voluntary” to be a solemn
mockery; and the sooner it is erased, and the term “forced”
put in its stead, the sooner the words of the constitution harmonize
with the idea of its framers, and be at one with the very practice of
its supporters.[120]

The nineteenth century thinker who, perhaps more than any other, elaborated on the significance and implications of government by consent was Lysander Spooner. Spooner (1808-1887) was a constitutional lawyer, abolitionist, and freethinker who became progressively more radical as be grew older. In an appendix to his Essay on Trial by Jury, published in 1852, Spooner noted (much like Molyneux and others) that it was a principle of the common law that no persons could be taxed without their personal consent. To Spooner, even before he saw the governmental carnage and atrocities of the Civil War, “taxation without consent” was “as plainly robbery” whether it was enforced by one man against millions, or enforced by millions against one man who did not consent. “Neither the numbers engaged in the act, nor the different characters they assume as a cover for the act” could ever alter the fact that property was being forcefully taken from at least one person against his will. Spooner defended the principle of “no taxation without consent” in the following manner:

If the government can take a man’s money without his consent there is no limit
to the additional tyranny it may practice upon him. . . . It is therefore a
first principle, a very ‘sine qua non’ of political freedom, that a man can
be taxed only by his personal consent. . . . Government have no more right,
in nature or reason to ‘assume’ a man’s consent to be protected by them, and
to he taxed for that protection, when he has given no actual consent, than a
fire or marine insurance company have to assume a man’s consent to be protected
by them, and to pay the premium, when his actual consent has never been given.
To take a man’s property without his consent is robbery; and to assume his
consent where no actual consent is given, makes the taking none the less robbery.
If it did, the highwayman has the same right to assume a man’s consent to part
with his purse, that any other man, or body of men, can have. And his assumption
would afford as much moral justification for his robbery as does a like assumption,
on the part of the government, for taking a man’s property without his consent.
The government’s pretense of protecting him, as an equivalent for the taxation
affords no justification.[121]

After the Civil War, Spooner wrote a series of pamphlets called No Treason. According to Spooner in these essays, governments and nations, if they can be said to rightfully exist at all, can exist only by consent, and this means: “the separate individual consent of every man who is required to contribute, either by taxation or personal service, to the support of the government. . . . Either the separate individual consent of every man who is required to aid, in any way, in supporting the government is necessary, or the consent of no one is necessary.”[122]

In No Treason, No. 2, Spooner argued that “either ‘taxation without consent is robbery’ or it is not. If it is not, then any number of men who choose, may at any time associate; call themselves a government, assume absolute authority over all weaker than themselves; plunder them at will; and kill them if they resist. If, on the other hand, ‘taxation without consent is robbery,’ it necessarily follows that every man who has not consented to be taxed, has the same natural right to defend his property against a tax-gatherer, that he has to defend it against a highwayman.” [123]

In his final pamphlet of this series, No Treason, No. 6, “The Constitution of No Authority,” Spooner broke new ground by demolishing the theory of tacit consent. Spooner argued that merely living in a certain geographic area under control of a government, or voting in government elections, in no way implied one’s consent to the government of that territory. Elections mean nothing; for Spooner showed that a majority of people never vote, and of those who do, the number supporting the elected candidates is so small (as a percentage of the population) as to be ludicrous. “Elections are secret; therefore, you cannot call representatives legal agents, since they do not know specifically whom they do represent.” Therefore, having voted in an election in no formal way demonstrates that one consented to anything. “On the question of the Constitution itself, no vote ever had been taken, and as a legal contract the Constitution has no validity.”[124] According to Spooner,

the Constitution was never signed, nor agreed to, by anybody, as a contract,
and therefore never bound anybody, and is now binding upon nobody; and is,
moreover, such a one as no people can ever hereafter be expected to consent
to, except as they may be forced to do so at the point of the bayonet.[125]

The anarchistic implications of all this should be quite clear. The state has no right to raise any taxes except as they are “voluntary” contributions or “contractual” obligations for services rendered.[126] In fact the historical origin of taxation demonstrates its relationship to the idea of consent. At least some forms of taxation “were matters of voluntary grant,” but “their history is bound up with the gradual growth of the right of the majority to bind the individual.” During the reign of Henry III (1227-1258), an example is cited of a nobleman claiming immunity from a tax “on the ground that he as an individual had not consented to its levy.”[127] As another commentator has pointed out, “consent no longer effectively safeguards the sanctity of private property if it ceases to be personal and individual.” Yet the very growth of such expressions as “no taxation without representation” tended to purposefully obscure this important point. Once the parliamentary practice became accepted by which “electors appointed representatives, or proxies, to give consent in their name,” the sense of individual consent to taxation “inevitably lost ground.”[128]

In its extreme form the doctrine of consent signifies that a man is bound only by what he consents to. If individual consent is the only rightful source of power, the question must be raised why “even a single objector should be coerced, possibly against his own conscience.”[129] This “anarchial principle” has always been embraced by radical libertarians, and certainly no one belabored the point more than did Spooner.”[130] As one of the major contributors to the development of the proprietary theory of justice in the libertarian tradition, one of Spooner’s greatest achievements was “to demolish the tacit consent doctrine, particularly as it applied to the U.S. Constitution. Spooner’s natural rights theory, combined with his refusal to recognize the surrender of rights through tacit consent, brings out the radical anarchism latent in the Lockean tradition.”[131]

Certainly one critical element of the proprietary theory of justice was the view that one’s just property titles could not be rightfully alienated without one’s consent. That is what it meant to own property or exercise dominion over one’s own. This was noted by some of the predecessors of the Levellers, as well as by the Levellers and other seventeenth century political thinkers. Two years after Ponet’s treatise appeared, Christopher Goodman published his Superior Powers in 1558, in which he embraced natural rights, “declaring that men ‘may lawfully claim’ their liberty ‘as their own possessions,’ and concluding that ‘if they suffer this right to be taken from them,’ they are letting themselves be robbed no less than if they let their rulers remove any of their other goods.”[132] A century later, Richard Baxter, an English clergyman, reiterated the same point: “Propriety is naturally antecedent to government. . . . Every man is born with propriety in his own members, and nature gives him a propriety in . . . [the] just acquisitions of his industry. Therefore no rule can justly deprive men of their propriety, unless it be . . . by their own consent. . . . And men’s lives and liberties are the chief parts of their propriety.”[133] The radicalism of consent doctrine was twin-edged. No one could be obliged to obey a government to which he or she did not consent; but even more significantly, no one could be bound to contribute their “lives” or “properties” to such a government either. The necessity of having voluntary consent to taxation or conscription makes government an impossibility.

Radical political philosophy since the seventeenth century has been characterized to a large extent by these forms of “voluntaryism,” “by an emphasis on the assent of individuals as the standard of political legitimacy”[134] This review of consent theory in the libertarian tradition has sought to demonstrate that the individualist and voluntaryist character of the consent doctrine would actually “deprive every existing polity of its legitimacy.”[135] Its most perceptive critics, such as Sir Robert Filmer and Josiah Tucker, clearly saw this, and their critiques of consent theory were largely premised on this realization. Both Filmer and Tucker believed that the supporters of consent were “either internally inconsistent or disastrous in their prospective practical implications. Either their positions must be instances of remarkable stupidity or they must be held in bad faith. If they mean what they say, their beliefs would imply anarchy.”[136] They charged their opponents “with either evading the question or adopting theories that logically destroyed the moral authority of government. . . .”[137] Other others who embraced Lockean ideas were often not aware of the ultimate implications that could be deduced from their initial premises. There is no question but that “consent implies voluntariness and the association of almost every individual with the government which has control over him is clearly involuntary.”[138] So for nearly three centuries now, the most perceptive political theorists have perceived that there is a large, unbridgeable chasm between the idea of consent and government. There is simply no way to cross that bridge, for inevitably to contend that government rests on consent is to begin the descent on the slippery slope to anarchism.”[139]

NOTES

a. Author’s Note: I would like to thank George Smith for originally pointing out many of the historical connections to be made in the intellectual history of the consent doctrine, especially for his references to Filmer and Tucker.

1. A. S. P. Woodhouse, ed., Puritanism and Liberty (Chicago: University of Chicago Press 1951), p. 59 of The Putney Debates.
2. George H. Smith, “William Wollaston on Property Rights,” Journal of Libertarian Studies 2 (1978):217-24, at 224.
3. Ibid.
4. Winthrop S. Hudson, John Ponet (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1942). Note that this volume also includes a photographic reprint of Ponet’s work (A Shorte Treatise of Politike Pawer; And of the True Obedience Which Subiectes Owe to Kynges and Other Civile Governaurs, With an Exhortacion to All True Naturall Englishemen, 1556). References to Ponet refer to this photographic reprint. See Ponet, A Shorte Treatise, title page and pp. 21, 35, 47, 79, 98.
5. Quentin Skinner, The Foundations of Modern Political Thought, Vol. 2 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1978), pp. 223, 320.
6. Hudson, op. cit., p. 144, and Ponet, op. cit., p. 88.
7. Hudson, op. cit., p. 137, and Ponet, op. cit., pp. 26-28.
8. Ponet, op. cit., p. 107.
9. Hudson, op. cit., p. 158.
10. Skinner, op. cit., p. 343.
11. Hudson, op. cit., p. 160.
12. Ibid., p. 210.
13. Ibid., p. 216, citing Charles Francis Adams, ed., The Works of John Adams, Vol, 6 (Boston: Charles C. Little and James Brown, 1851), p. 4.
14. The Oxford English Dictionary, Vol. I (Oxford: At The Clarendon Press, 1933), see “anarchical,” “anarchism,” and “anarchy,” pp. 307-8.
15. Gordon Schohet, Patriarchalism in Political Thought (New York: Basic Books, 1975), p. 107.
16. The Oxford English Dictionary, op. cit., p. 307.
17. Woodhouse, op. cit., Introduction, p. 51.
18. William Haller, ed., Tracts on Liberty in the Puritan Revolution, Vol. 3 (New York: Columbia University Press, 1934), p. 172, which is p. 56 of Parker’s text.
19. Woodhouse, op. cit., Introduction, p. 33.
20. Ibid., pp. 53, 65-68.
21. Ibid., p. 69, which is pp. 3-4 of Overton’s text.
22. Ibid., p. 75.
23. Ibid., pp. 72, 75, 85-86.
24. Ibid., p. 322, Sec. 8, “Leveller Principles,” citing from the Levellers’ “Large Petition.”
25. Carl Watner, ed., A Voluntary Political Government; Letters from Charles Lane (St. Paul: Michael E. Coughlin, 1982), p. 33.
26. Woodhouse, op. cit., Introduction, p. 87.
27. Carl Watner, “ ‘Come What, Come Will!’ Richard Overton, Libertarian Leveller,” Journal of Libertarian Studies 4 (1980): 405-32, at 406, citing Perez Zagorin, A History of Political Thought in the English Revolution (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1954), p. 41,
28. Ibid., p. 408, citing H. N. Brailsford, The Levellers and the English Revolution (London: Cresset Press, 1961), p, 264.
29. Woodhouse, op. cit., The Putney Debates, p. 75.
30. Watner, op. cit., p. 409, citing Woodhouse, op. cit., Introduction, p. 91.
31. Woodhouse, op. cit., The Putney Debates, p. 53.
32. Ibid., p. 66. Note, however, that Wildman was arguing for a representative government with an expanded franchise, and not for anarchism.
33. Woodhouse, op. cit., Documents Relating to the Putney Debate, p. 440.
34. James Daly, Sir Robert Filmer and English Political Thought (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1979), p. 83.
35. John W. Robbins, “The Political Thought of Sir Robert Filmer” (Ph.D. dissertation, Johns Hopkins University. 1973), p. 17; and Peter Laslett, “Sir Robert Filmer,” William and Mary Quarterly 5 (1948, 3rd series):521-46, at p. 546.
36. Daley, op. cit., p. 86; and Peter Laslett ed., ”Patriarcha” and Other Political Works of Sir Robert Filmer (Oxford: Basic Blackwell, 1949), p. 36.
37. Daley, op. cit., p. 89.
38. Schochet, op. cit., p. 129.
39. J. W. Allen, “Sir Robet Filmer,” in F. J. C. Hearnshaw, The Social and Political Ideas of Some English Thinkers of the Augustan Age (London: George A. Harap & Co., 1928), pp. 27-46, at 28.
40. Laslett, ed., Works, p. 294. All references to Filmer’s works are to those appearing in the Laslett edition and will be cited as Laslett, ed., Works.
41. lbid., p. 285.
42. lbid., p. 286.
43. lbid., p. 81.
44. Allen, op. cit., p. 36.
45. From Laslett’s “Introduction” in Laslett, ed., Works, cit., p. 16.
46. Schochet, op. cit., p. 123.
47. Laslett, ed., Works, p. 82.
48. lbid.
49. lbid.
50. lbid., p. 225.
51. lbid., p. 287.
52. Ibid.
53. Ibid., p.211.
54. Ibid., p. 277. Emphasis added.
55. Robbins, op. cit., p. 170.
56. Laslett, ed., Works, p. 254.
57. Ibid., p. 259.
58. Ibid., p. 300.
59. lbid., p. 297.
60. From Laslett’s Introduction, Works, p. 31.
61. Schochet, op. cit., p. 260.
62. Ibid., p. 261, citing Locke’s Second Treatise, sections 117 and also sections 95, 112, 119-121, 192, 197, 198. Note all references to Locke’s Second Treatise will refer to Peter Laslett, ed., Two Treatises of Government (Cambridge: At the University Press, 1960). Citations will not be by page number but rather to sections. Hence, Laslett, ed., Locke, II, 117 refers to section 117 of the Second Treatise.
63. John Dunn, The Political Thought of John Locke (Cambridge: At the University Press, 1969), p. 131.
64. Ibid., p. 133.
65. Ibid., p. 131.
66. Gordon J. Schochet, ed., Life, Liberty, and Property: Essays on Locke’s Political Ideas (Belmont, Calif.: Wadsworth Publishing Co., 1971), p. 8. Schochet in his Introduction makes the point that Locke distinguished between expressly consenting to membership in political society and mere presence, or tacit consent.
67. Laslett, ed., Locke, II, 119.
68. Ibid., II, 120.
69. Ibid.
70. Dunn, op. cit., p. 140.
71. Laslett, ed., Locke. II, 121.
72. Dunn, op. cit., p. 133, citing Laslett, ed., Locke, II, 115, 116, and 121. This borders on a problem Filmer raised, which is how a person can commit himself to citizenship for life. Is it possible that once express consent is given, it can never be withdrawn?
73. Laslett, ed., Locke, II, 117.
74. Ibid., II, 118.
75. Corpus Juris, Vol. 11 (New York: American Law Book Co., 1917), pp. 783 and 787 under reference “Citizens.”
76. Dunn, op. cit., p. 137 citing Sir William Holdsworth, A History of English Law, Vol. 9, 3rd ed. (London: Methuen & Co., 1944), pp. 84, 86.
77. Even today, governments jealously guard the right of emigration and are concerned about the related loss of tax revenues that emigration entails. For example, the United States Internal Revenue Code, Sections 877 and 2107, did (and may still) provide that anyone who renounced U.S. citizenship with the purpose of tax avoidance would still be responsible for paying taxes to the U.S. government for ten years after such renunciation. As one commentator put it: “The United States government deems citizenship a privilege to be matched by the burden of Taxation.” Lloyd Shefsky and Lee Barbkoff, “Taxation and Emigration.” Tax Haven Review 2 (1975):10.
78. P. H. Partridge, Consent and Concensus (New York: Praeger, 1971), p. 22.
79. Schochet, op. cit., p. 261.
80. Laslen, ed., Locke. II, 16.
81. Ibid., II, 95.
82. Ibid., II, 98.
83. Ibid., II, 99.
84. Ibid., II, 138.
85. Ibid., II, 140.
86. John Dunn, Political Obligation in Its Historical Context (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1980), p. 68.
87. Ibid. Dunn at footnote 35, p. 314, cites from Molyneux’s correspondence with Locke: “How justly they can bind us without our consent and representives, I leave the author of the Two Treatises of Government to consider.”
88. The Dictionary of National Biography, vol. 13 (London: Oxford University Press, 1967-1968), p.587.
89. Ibid., which claims that this is a false belief. See H. F. Kearney, “The Political Background to English Mercantilism 1695-1700,” Economic History Review 2 (1958-1959, 2nd series) at p. 491 for the statement that the book was condemned to be burned.
90. Robert Livingston Schuyler, ed., Josiah Tucker: A Selection from His Economic and Political Writings (New York: Columbia University Press, 1931). pp. 416-17. Tucker in A Treatise Concerning Civil Government (London: T. Caldwell, 1781) cites this and the next passage as being from pp. 113 and 169 of Molyneux’s book. For reprint of these passages, see also Carl Watner, “The Proprietary Theory of Justice in the Libertarian Tradition”, Journal of Libertarian Studies 6 (1982):289-316, at 301-2.
91. Smith, op. cit., p. 222.
92. Schuyler, op. cit., p. 416. .
93. Dunn, Political Obligation, pp. 68-69.
94. Ibid., p. 69.
95. Herbert W. Schneider, ed., Adam Smith’s Moral and Political Philosophy (New York: Hafner Publishing Co., 1948), p. 289, from Adam Smith’s “Lectures on Justice, Police, Revenue, and Arms,” Part I, Division I, Section I.
96. Henry Aiken, ed., Hume’s Moral and Political Philosophy (New York: Hafner Publishing Co., 1948), p. 359, from David Hume’s essay “Of The Original Contract.”
97. Ibid., p. 363.
98. Ibid., p. 365.
99. J. W. Gough, The Social Contract, 2nd ed. (Oxford: At the Clarendon Press, 1957), p. 139.
100. George Smith, op. cit., p. 224.
101. Schuyler, ed., op. cit., p. 35, citing p. 435.
102. Ibid., p. 35.
103. Ibid., p. 41.
104. Ibid., citing p. 378.
105. Ibid., p. 41.
106. Apparently Josiah Tucker did not want to be associated with Filmer as a defender of the divine right of kings. Undoubtedly Tucker wanted to be free of any claim that his argument and that of Filmer were similar. For the one reference by Tucker to Filmer, see ibid., pp. 450-52.
107. Ibid., p. 452.
108. J. W. Gough, John Locke’s Political Philosophy (Oxford: At the Clarendon Press, 1951), p. 90. Locke would probably have been prepared to “allow taxation to be levied by decision of a majority,” but this is as far as he would have gone. “He would have required strictly individual consent to justify any other kind of interference with private property.”
109. Schuyler, ed., op. cit., p. 444.
110. Ibid., p. 459.
111. Ibid., p. 460.
112. Ibid.
113. Ibid., p. 479.
114. Ibid., p. 412.
115. Ibid., p. 452.
116. Ibid., p. 480.
117. Ibid.
118. Walter Harding, ed., The Variorum Civil Disobedience by Henry David Thoreau (New York: Twayne Publishers, 1967), p. 61.
119. Ibid., p. 45, from “The Essay on Civil Disobedience.”
120. Carl Watner, ed., A Voluntary Political Government. pp. 40, 83.
121. Charles Shively, ed., The Collected Works of Lysander Spooner (Weston, Mass.: M & S Press, 1971), from “An Essay on Trial by Jury” (1852) in The Collected Works, vol. 2, pp. 222-23.
122. Spooner, No Treason, No.1 (1867), in Ibid., vol. 1, pp. 10-11. 123. Spooner, No Treason. No. 2 (1867), in Ibid., vol. 1, p. 13.
124. Charles Shively, Introduction to Lysander Spooner, No Treason, No. 6, “The Constitution of No Authority” (1870), in Ibid., vol. 1, p. 3.
125. Spooner, No Treason, No. 6, in Ibid., vol. 1, p. 59.
126. Dunn, Political Obligation. op. cit., p. 43.
127. A. F. Pollard, The Evolution of Parliament (New York: Longman’s, Green & Co., 1920), p.143.
128. Gough, Locke’s Political Philosophy, op. cit., p. 49.
129. Ibid., p. 58.
130. Ibid.
131. Watner, “Proprietary Theory,” op. cit., p. 304, citing George Smith, op. cit., p. 224. 132. Quentin Skinner, op. cit., Vol. II, p. 320.
133. Richard Schlatter, Richard Baxter and Puritan Politics (New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press, 1957), p. 39, citing from Baxter’s Second Part of the Nonconformists Plea for Peace (1680), pp. 54-55.
134. Patrick Riley, “How Coherent is the Socia1 Contract Tradition?” Journal of the History of Ideas 34 (1973):543-62, at 543. His reference however is to the term “voluntarism,” not voluntaryism.
135. Dunn, Political Obligation. op. cit., p. 48.
136. Ibid., p. 63.
137. J.W. Allen, op.cit., p.42.
138. C. W. Cassinelli, “The ‘Consent’ of the Governed”, Western Political Quarterly 12 (1959):391-409, at 398.
139. Watner, “Proprietary Theory,” op. cit., p. 303, referring to this as a point made by George Smith.

Those “Impossible Citizens”: Civil Resistants in 19th Century New England


CARL WATNER

1979

Most libertarians view civil disobedience or resistance to the State differently than members of the general public.  Many people, of a variety of persuasions, recognize the right of the individual to resort to self-defense when attacked or threatened by the criminal.  In the libertarian view, and by libertarian definition, only the criminal resorts to the initiation of force against the peaceful and the innocent.  Where the libertarian and the non-libertarian part company is over the criminality of State initiated compulsion.  To the libertarian, the whole State apparatus is criminal.  Relying on taxation for its very existence, it obtains its income by threatening or using force to collect its revenues–not by relying on voluntary subscriptions or mutual trade.  The inference, for libertarians at least, is that it is right to oppose both the common criminal and the State, since both aggress against individual rights. Hence the libertarian proclivity for and interest in civil disobedience.[l]

  Historically libertarians have not been the only people opposed to the State, although they may have been the only group to have branded the State as illegitimate and criminal to its core.  Religious groups, such as the early Christians and Quakers, were attacked by the States within which they lived.  Conscientious objectors have long opposed State policy and their opposition has not always been limited to conscription and the refusal to pay taxes to support governmental wars.  Those with conscientious scruples have resisted compulsory vaccination, compulsory schooling of their children, and even rejected the use of government money.[2]  Such groups and the individuals composing them have never initiated aggression against their neighbors.  They were peaceful dissenters who did not conform to the demands of their government. Every act of aggression against their lives or property implied an injustice. Whether they chose to react non-violently, such as the non-resistant, William Lloyd Garrison, or whether they chose to offer active resistance, such as the forceful John Brown, they all in their own way were resisting demands of coercive governments.

  The best known civil resistant of 19th Century New England was Henry David Thoreau (1817-1862).  For several years, Thoreau did not voluntarily pay his taxes, even under protest; rather he resisted the State by not paying his taxes at all.  “The impressive thing about Thoreau’s dealing with the State is that he did not stop with theorizing but acted.” “He not only objected to the law, he made himself an object for the law to deal with.”[3]

  In his essay, “On The Duty of Civil Disobedience,” Thoreau relates the story of his own tax resistance.  During the 1840’s, state law in Massachusetts imposed on every male inhabitant above the age of 20 an annual poll tax assessment, subject to a maximum tax of $1.50. The poll tax was simply a source of revenue for the State.  If a person should neglect or refuse to pay his tax, the tax collector was authorized to seize the property of the delinquent, or in the absence of sufficient property, the tax collector was empowered to seize the body of the debtor and commit him to prison, there to remain until he shall have paid the tax and the charges of commitment and imprisonment. The latter is exactly what happened to Thoreau on either July 23 or July 24, 1846.[4]  As he related in Walden: “One afternoon, near the end of the first summer, when I went to the village to get a shoe from the cobbler’s, I was seized and put into jail, because, as I have elsewhere related, I did not pay a tax to, or recognize the authority of the State. . . .”[5]  Thoreau was not desirous of being a bad neighbor, but rather only being a bad subject of the State.  As he said, “It is for no particular item in the tax-bill that I refuse to pay it.  I simply wish to refuse allegiance to the State, to withdraw and stand aloof from it effectually.  I do not care to trace the course of my dollar, if I could, till it buys a man, or a musket to shoot one with–the dollar is innocent–but I am concerned to trace the effect of my allegiance.”[6]

  Thoreau had one earlier encounter with the city authorities of Concord, Massachusetts, in 1840, when he had refused to pay “a certain sum toward the support of a clergyman whose preaching my father attended, but never I myself.” He demanded that his name be removed from the church tax rolls and at the suggestion of the town selectmen, he filed a statement with them saying: “Know all men by these presents, that I, Henry Thoreau, do not wish to be regarded as a member of any incorporated society which I have not joined.”  If he had known how to name them all, Thoreau adds that he would have appended a list of all the societies to which he did not belong.[7]  Thoreau no more wished to be a member of any society that he did not voluntarily join, than he wished to be a citizen of the State without his consent.  “To be strictly just,” the authority of government “must have the sanction and consent of the governed.  It can have no pure right over my person and property but what I concede to it.”[8] Further, Thoreau recognized the right to rebel against injustice: “All men recognize the right of revolution: that is, the right to refuse allegiance to and to resist the government, when its tyranny or inefficiency are great and unendurable,”[9]

  The essay “On The Duty of Civil Disobedience” shows that Thoreau’s opposition to government was both on general principles and on specific issues.  Of the latter, he repeatedly asserts his abolitionist and anti-war views:

I cannot for an instant recognize that political organization as my government which is the slaves government also. . . . [W]hen the friction comes to have its machine, and oppression and robbery are organized, I say let us not have such a machine any longer.  In other words, when a sixth of the population of a nation which has undertaken to be the refuge of liberty are slaves, and a whole country is unjustly overrun and conquered by a foreign army, and subjected to military law, I think it is not too soon for honest men to rebel and revolutionize. What makes this duty the more urgent is the fact, that the country so overrun is not our own, but ours is the invading army.[10]

  Thoreau realized that majorities ruled over minorities because they are physically the strongest, but that did not prevent him from advocating the rights of the minority and even individual secession from government: “I do not hesitate to say that those who call themselves abolitionists should at once effectually withdraw their support both in person and property from the government of Massachusetts, and not wait till they constitute a majority of one. . . .”[11] “Why do they not dissolve . . .the union between themselves and the State,–and refuse to pay their quota into its Treasury?”[12]

  Being concerned with his own self-respect and personal integrity, Thoreau queried: “Must the citizen ever for a moment resign his conscience to the legislator?”  And he answered, “I think we should be men first and subjects afterwards.  It is not desirable to cultivate a respect for law so much as for the right.  The only obligation I have the right to assume, is to do at any time what I think right.”[13] For Thoreau,

There is a higher law than civil law–the law of conscience–and that when the laws are in conflict it is the citizen’s duty to obey the voice . . . within rather than that of the civil authorities without. If he will go to prison rather than obey an evil law, he will through his courage and his martyrdom arouse the conscience of the people “en masse” and through their resistance they will clog the machinery of tyranny by filling the courts and jails and thus bringing about the repeal of the offensive law.[14]

  Nor was Thoreau the only New Englander of his time to have this attitude towards natural law and conscience.  Thoreau’s refusal to pay his poll tax was not the first such episode of tax resistance in Massachusetts. There were at least two earlier precedents involving people known to Thoreau.  A. Bronson Alcott (1799-1888) was a well-known school teacher, writer and transcendentalist.  His English associate in Fruitlands, their co-operative farm, Charles Lane, supported Alcott in his tax resistance and also became a resistant himself.  Lane had arrived from England in October 1842, with the purpose of visiting Alcott.  Within a month of his arrival on American soil, Lane had begun advocating abolitionism, the overthrow of the American “slave” government and the immediate secession of every right-minded man.[15] Lane’s arrest occurred near the end of 1843, and was described by Emerson in his letter of December 17, 1843 to Margaret Fuller: “Mr. Lane was here lately again for two or three days having been arrested for his taxes as he stopped with the Harvard Stage at the tavern. He declined bringing any friend to answer for him and was put into jail. Rockwood Hoar heard of it and paid the debt and when I came home from seeing you in Boston I found him at my house.”[16]  Lane strenuously objected to the use of the general warrant which was used to arrest him and Alcott, and later Thoreau.  Tax delinquents were treated more harshly than debtors of private creditors and there was no legal appeal possible from imprisonment for failure to pay one’s taxes. Thoreau, too, protested against this arbitrary law of imprisonment:

One would think that a deliberate and practical denial of its authority was the only offense never contemplated by government; else why has it not assigned its definite, its suitable and proportionate penalty? If a man who has no property refuses but once to earn nine shillings for the State he is put in prison for a period unlimited by any law that I know of, and determined only by the discretion of those who placed him there; . . . [17]

  Bronson Alcott was the first to protest.  On January 17, 1843, he was arrested (but not committed) for failure to pay his 1842 poll tax.  His own Journals for this year have been lost, but fortunately there is a very clear description of his resistance which appeared in a letter written by Lane and published in William Lloyd Garrison’s Liberator on January 27, 1843.[18]  Lane insisted in his letter to the Liberator that Alcott’s resistance “does not rest upon the plea of poverty” but on a moral opposition to coercive taxation. Under the title of “State Slavery–The Imprisonment of A. Bronson Alcott–Dawn of Liberty,” Lane wrote:

It is often said, that in a condition of society where one is obliged to let pass so much that is immoral, it is not worthwhile to undergo so much inconvenience as close imprisonment on account of State prosecution.

  Very different to this however has been the feeling of A. Bronson Alcott, of Concord; and being convinced that the payment of the town tax involved principles and practices most degrading and injurious to man, he had long determined not to be a voluntary party to its continuance. Last year by the leniency of the collector in prepaying the $1.50 the question was not brought to issue. . . .

  This year a collector was appointed who could execute the law and although no doubt it went hard with him to snatch a man from his home, from his wife, from the provision and education of his little children, in which latter he found Mr. Alcott serenely engaged, he nevertheless did it. He witnessed with his own eyes the little hasty preparations. . . , the packing of a few personal conveniences to ward off the inclemencies of the season, and yet, with no higher authority than the general warrant in his pocket, which without particular investigation, trial, or inquiry hands over the liberty of every townsman to his discretion, he took a fellow citizen . . . to a long commitment.

  To the country jail, therefore, Mr. Alcott went, or rather was forced by the benignant State and its de1icate instrument. . . .

  Having worked up to this point, it appears that the enemy’s courage failed. The constable-collector, having brought his victim to the jail, the next step was to find the jailer who was not at home.  The prisoner, of course, waited patiently; and nearly after 2 hours had been thus passed, the constable announced that he no longer had the right to detain his captive.  On inquiring how that happened, he said that both the tax and costs had been paid.  To the question, by whom the payment had been made, he replied by naming a gentleman who may be regarded and who would willingly be regarded as the very personification of the State.

  In these facts, humble as the individual and the circumstances may appear, we have a wide and deep subject for reflection. . . . This act of non-resistance, you will perceive, does not rest on the plea of poverty.  For Mr. Alcott has always supplied some poor neighbor with food and clothing to a much higher amount than the tax.  Neither is it wholly based on the iniquitous purposes to which the money when collected is applied. For part of it is devoted to education and education has not found a heartier friend in the world than Bronson Alcott.  But it is founded on the moral instinct which forbids every moral being, to be a party, either actively or permissively, to the destructive principles of power and might over peace and love.

  Suppose the tax were levied by the town . . . and the full value on the amount were to be returned the next day to each payer in bread.  Would it not be a sacred duty in every man, in the virtuous integrity of his nature, to deny such a proceeding?  Doubtless it would.  All but the meanest souls would thereby be raised to dis-annex themselves from the false and tyrannous assumption, that the human will is to be subject to the brute force which the majority may set up.  It is only tolerated by public opinion because the fact is not yet perceived that all the true purposes of the corporate state may as easily be carried out on the revolutionary principle, as all the true purposes of the collective church.  Every one can see that the Church is wrong when it comes to men with the Bible in one hand and the sword in the other.  And is it not equally diabolical for the State to do so? The name is of small importance. When Church and State are divorced by public opinion, they may still carryon an adulterous intercourse.

  Then look at the peculiar law in this case.  When a debtor is imprisoned by an ordinary creditor, he can be bailed out, and have considerable liberty to employ himself, preserve his health, and the like. But the impersonal town is an inexorable monster and permits not his debtor to quit the prison walls.  He is treated as a convicted felon. No trial, no jury is permitted him.

  Many are the points worthy of consideration involved in this uncouth, barbaric, unchristian state of the law; and I earnestly trust you will not allow the occasion to escape your enlightened and benevolent pen, nor fail to inform the public at large of the facts.

Yours, sincerely,

C[harles]. L[ane].

Concord, Mass. January 16, 1843

  The tax is traditionally said to have been paid by Squire Samuel Hoar, the first citizen of the town.[19]  Both Thoreau and Emerson preserved their reaction to Alcott’s bravado.  Thoreau, in a letter to Emerson, wrote:

I suppose they have told you how near Alcott went to jail; but I can add a good anecdote to the rest.  When Staples [the tax collector] came to collect Mrs. Ward’s taxes, my sister Helen asked him what he thought Mr. Alcott meant–what his idea was–and Sam Answered, “I vum believe it was nothing but principle, for I never heerd a man talk honester.”[20]

Emerson, for his part, wrote in his Journal for 1843:

Alcott thought he could find as good grounds for quarrel in the State tax as Socrates did in the edicts of the judges.  Then I said, “Be consistent, and never more put an apple or kernel of corn into your mouth.  Would you feed the Devil?”  Say boldly “I will not any longer belong to this double-faced, equivocating, mixed, jesuitical Universe.”[21]

Mrs. Alcott noted in her own Journal for January 17, 1843 that it was a day of some excitement, “as Mr. Alcott had refused to pay his town tax and they had gone through the form of taking him to jail. After waiting some time to be committed, he was told that it was paid by a friend.  Thus we were spared the affliction of his absence and he the triumph of suffering for his principles.”[22]

  Alcott, in spite of his earlier experience, was still resisting payment of the poll tax in 1846.  In his Journal for May 4th of that year, he noted that Staples was threatening to advertise his land to pay for the tax.  Alcott still rejected the State for forcing itself upon “the freedom of the free-horn and the wisest bearing is to over-hear, let it have its own way, the private person never going out of his way to meet it.  It shall put its hand into a person’s pocket if it will, but I shall not put mine there on its behalf.”[23] Later that same year when Staples arrested Thoreau, Alcott wrote that he had an “earnest talk with Emerson dealing with the civil powers and institutions.”  In Alcott’s words, “E[merson] thought it mean and skulking and in bad taste,” for Thoreau to have refused to pay his taxes.”[24]

  Alcott and Lane were involved in a co-operative farm and reforming venture known as Fruitlands, near Harvard, Massachusetts, during 1844-1845. Among the individuals congregated at the Fruitlands farm was another civil resistant by the name of “Old Jew” Palmer or Joseph Palmer of “No Town.”  In November 1840, both Alcott and Palmer had been present at a gathering of religious reformers, known as the Chardon Street Convention.  At one session, there was an outcry over Palmer’s beard. Alcott rose to inquire, “in the first place, whether in the opinion of the assembly there was anything in the essential nature of a beard which prevented its wearer from becoming a Christian, and secondly, he wished to know if they had really come to discuss beards or rather, as he supposed, certain other fundamental questions.”[25]  Palmer’s claim to fame as a civil resistant was his absolute insistence on wearing a full beard in an age when beards were ridiculed and worn only by Jews.

  Palmer himself had fought in the War of 1812 and he had an eccentric character, but was steadfast and upright and immovable when it came to his principles. “Wearing a beard became a fixed idea with him, and neither the law of the land nor the admonitions of the church could make him falter in his determination to claim freedom of action in this respect.”[26] His nick- name, “Old Jew” Palmer, was no reflection on his religious affiliation, but only showed the bigotry of his persecutors. His farm at “No Town” was very successful and was located on a tract of land which lay outside of Fitchburg and Leominster, Massachusetts. As it belonged to no township, and was untaxed, it came to be known as “No Town.”  “So when he married the widow Tenney, rumors circulated through Fitchburg that the marriage was not legal because he did not publish the banns at the meeting house at “No Town.”  But investigation proved the marriage legal because he had published the banns in his own handwriting on a large piece of paper which he had tacked to the trunk of a fine old pine tree which grew near his home.”[27]

  One day Palmer was attacked by four men, intent to shave off his beard. With the aid of an old jack-knife he carried, Palmer was able to thwart his assailants.  However afterwards he was “arrested for committing an unprovoked assault and ordered by Justice Brigham to pay a fine, which he refused to do, as he claimed to be acting for maintenance of a principle.”  He was thrown into jail and lodged with the debtors where he remained for over a year.  When once asked why he wore his beard, “he said he would tell if any one could tell him why some men would, from 52 to 365 times a year, scrape their face from their nose to their neck.”[28]  He refused to pay his fine, although he was a man of property and he far outstayed his sentence. He refused to leave the jail because he thought he was being cheated on his upkeep, which he had to pay out of his own pocket.  “The sheriff and jailers, tired of having him there, begged him to leave. Even his mother, Margaret Palmer, wrote to him ‘Not to be so set.’ But nothing could move him.  He said they had put him in there and they would have to take him out, as he would not walk out. They finally carried him out in his chair and placed it on the sidewalk.”[29] On his tombstone in the old North Leominster graveyard is said to be the carving of the head of an old man with a flowing beard and underneath it the inscription: “Joseph Palmer, died October 30, 1875–Persecuted for Wearing the Beard.”

  Concerned as Palmer was with his beard, he was also a temperance advocate and an abolitionist.  The abolition of slavery and the cessation of government support to the slave system was of great concern to nearly all the New England resistants.  Particularly annoying to them was the enforcement of the Fugitive Slave Law of 1793 and 1850. When Boston was forced to aid in the return of the fugitive slave, Sims, in 1851, Alcott wondered in his Journal, if, “It would not be a handsome piece of honor and justice to withhold the payment of the assessment for this item of the tax-bill when it shall be claimed by the municipality. . . .I am tempted to try it. Certainly the prison could not be put to better use than the holding of honest men, to the discredit of unrighteous laws.”[30] A few years later, Alcott displayed his courage and fidelity to principle when he risked his life entering the Boston Court House, which was under siege by a mob.  At the time, the fugitive slave, Anthony Burns, was under the protective custody of the government (pending his return to the South) and an unsuccessful attempt was being made to rescue him.[31] Of the personalities mentioned so far, only Thoreau and Emerson were not outright abolitionists.  Nor was Emerson a civil resistant, although he did go so far as to advocate that judges and magistrates interpret the law and Constitution for themselves.  This was also a favorite theme of Thoreau’s.  Emerson concluded “not merely that the Fugitive Slave Law was to be disobeyed by those who felt it to be immoral, but that the official interpreters and executives were bound to make and enforce righteous laws of their own; . . . The first duty of a judge was to read the law in accordance with equity, and if it jarred with equity, to disown the law.”[32]

  The anti-slavery and abolition movements had a long tradition of resistance and opposition to government.  From the beginning of the abolition movement the question of violence was significant.[33]  How was the movement to express its opposition and what course of action were the slaves and abolitionists to follow?  By the late l830’s, the movement in America had answered this question and had split into two distinct factions.  One radical faction, led by William Lloyd Garrison [1805-1879], called for the immediate abolition of slavery, non-participation in government, and non-resistance.  However for many abolitionists, gradual emancipation, office holding and voting, and the use of force in self-defense were legitimate and a question of expediency only. Those led by Garrison, on the other hand, realized that slavery was

not the casual temporary seizure by the Southerners of a few million of Negroes, but the ancient and universal recognition, contrary to the Christian teaching, of the right of coercion on the part of certain people in regard to certain others.  A pretext for recognizing this right has always been that men regarded it as possible to eradicate or diminish evil by brute force, i.e., also by evil.  Having once realized this fallacy, Garrison put forward against slavery neither the suffering of the slaves, nor the cruelty of the slaveholders, nor the social equality of men, but the eternal Christian law of refraining from opposing evil by violence, i.e., of “non-resistance.” Garrison understood that which most advanced among the fighters of slavery did not understand: that the only irrefutable argument against slavery is the denial of the right of any man over the liberty of another under any conditions whatsoever. . . . Garrison understanding that the slavery of the Negroes was only a particular instance of universal coercion, put forward a general principle with which it was impossible not to agree–the principle that under no pretext has any man the right to dominate, i.e., to use coercion over his fellows.  Garrison did not so much insist on the right to be free as he denied the right of any man whatsoever, or any body of men, forcibly to coerce another man in any way.[34]

  These non-resistant abolitionists were the pacifists of the 19th Century peace movement.  Garrison led a splinter group away from the American Peace Society, and in Boston, on September 20, l838, they formed the New England Non-Resistance Society.  The key clause in their constitution was that

The members of this society agree . . . that no man or body of men . . . have a right to take the life of man as a penalty for transgression, that no one who professes to have the spirit of Christ, can consistently sue a man at law for redress of injuries, or thrust any evildoer into prison, or fill any office which he would come under obligation to execute penal enactments–or take part in military service–or acknowledge allegiance to any human government–or justify any man in fighting in defense of property, liberty, life or religion; that he cannot engage in or countenance any plot to revolutionize or change by physical violence any government however corrupt or oppressive.[35]

  The term “non-resistance” which was chosen to identify Garrison and his followers was derived from Christ’s injunction to individuals not to resist evil.[36]  In 1835, when threatened by a Boston mob, Garrison had proclaimed his fidelity to this ideal: “I will perish sooner than raise my hand against any man, even in self-defense, and let none of my friends resort to violence for my protection.”[37] Garrison and his followers realized that if a slaveholder once became a non-resistant, he could never again strike a slave, never resort to that law of violence by which a slave was compelled to labor and in which the relation of master and slave originated and by which it must continually be sustained.[38]

  Personal non-violence, however, was only one aspect of Garrisonian non-resistance. Those who deplored Garrison’s view of government, dubbed him and his followers as “no-government” men.  To renounce all manifestations of government, as the Garrisonian non-resistance men did, was to make them quasi-anarchists or “no-government” men.  “Actually the Garrisonian non-resistants resented and disclaimed the name of ‘no-governmentism.’ They insisted that they were striving for and placing themselves under the only true and effective government, the government of God. They maintained that they opposed not government, but human pretensions to govern.”[39]  Thoreau had used the term and had made the distinction that what he called for was not “no-government” but a better government.”[40]  Thoreau recognized the right of self-defense and violent revolution, contrary to the position of the non-resistants.  Thoreau had taken the affirmative position in a debate with Alcott before the Concord Lyceum in January 1841, on the question: “Is it ever proper to offer forcible resistance?”[41] Despite this difference with the non-resistants, Thoreau agreed with their position on non-participation in government.  He invited all public officers and tax collectors to “Resign your office,” and concluded that “When the subject has refused allegiance and the officer has resigned his office, then the revolution is accomplished.”[42] The non-resistant agitation for resignation had little effect, for as late as 1854, Thoreau still doubted if there were a judge in the entire state of Massachusetts who was prepared to resign his office and get his living innocently whenever it was required of him to enforce the Fugitive Slave Law.[43]

  All office holding and voting were proscribed under the non-resistant philosophy. The principle of democratic control of government through majority rule came under attack, too.  Since no group of human beings could rightfully coerce others, it was wrong for the majority of voters to enforce their choices on a minority.  In the Liberator of September 28, 1838, Garrison protested against participation in any government:

As every human government is upheld by physical force and its laws are enforced virtually at the point of the bayonet, we cannot hold any office which imposes upon its incumbent the obligation to compel men to do right on pain of imprisonment or death.  We therefore voluntarily exclude ourselves from every legislative and judicial body and repudiate all human politics, worldly honor, and stations of authority. If we cannot occupy a seat in the legislature, or on the bench, neither can we elect others to act as our substitutes in such capacity.[44]

Henry Clarke Wright, abolitionist, non-resistant, and associate of Garrison, held a similar view:

It is wrong to hold an office in which we must consent to be vested with life-taking or war-making powers or to come under an obligation to use it. . . It is wrong to vote for others to office which it is wrong for us to hold.  We must look to the character of the office itself and not to the candidate or measures he proposes, however good these may be.  To exercise the franchise even to erect the abolition of slavery would be wrong, would be to vote for murder to prevent theft.[45]

Wright based much of his argument on the implied threat of force behind the ballot. He claimed that every vote carried with it the threat of war, of a bullet, if one did not abide by the desires of the majority.  “A bullet is in every ballot; and when the ballot is cast in to the box, the bullet goes in with it.  They are inseparable as the government is now constituted. . . . The ballot box is the first step–the gallows or the battlefield the last; and whosoever takes the first must take the last.  There is no consistent or honest stopping place between them.”[46]

  In spite of their non-participation stance, the non-resistants did not develop a stand against the payment of taxes.  “All the New England non-resistants, from Garrison on down, complied with Caesar’s demands.”[47] Tax-paying was seen as submission to compulsion exerted by the government, much as a non-resistant might submit to a burglar.  Therefore tax-paying, in their eyes, was non-resistance.  Garrison and his followers excused themselves with the argument that since they paid their taxes against their will, they were not guilty of disobedience and stayed within the legal limits in expressing opposition to government. “As for taxes, it is only our voluntary acts for which we are responsible. When did government ever trust tax-paying to the voluntary good will of its subjects?  When it does, non-resistants will refuse to pay.”[41] Only Alcott of the leading abolitionists went so far as to suffer arrest or imprisonment rather than pay his tax.[49]

  Non-resistants such as Garrison and Wright were somewhat perplexed by John Brown’s raid on Harper’s Ferry.  On the one hand, they hated the institution of slavery.  On the other, they rejected the use of violence in any, form to secure any end, however agreeable.  Regardless of their pacifist stance, both sympathized with Brown’s violent effort. Speaking at a protest meeting in Boston, on the day of Brown’s execution, Garrison said:

I am a non-resistant–a believer in the inviolability of human life under all circumstances; I, therefore, in the name of God disarm John Brown and every slave in the South.  But I do not stop there; if I did I should be a monster.  I also disarm in the name of God every slaveholder and tyrant in the world. . . . I am a non-resistant, and I not only desire, but have labored unremittingly to effect the peaceful abolition of slavery . . . yet as a peace man–an “ultra” peace man–I am prepared to say: “Success to every slave insurrection in the South, and in every slave country.”  I do not see how I compromise or stain my peace profession in making that declaration. Whenever there is a contest between the oppressed and the oppressor, . . .God knows that my heart must be with the oppressed and against the oppressor. . . . I thank God when men who believe in the right and duty of wielding carnal weapons are so far advanced that they will take those weapons out of the scale of despotism, and throw them into the scale of freedom.[50]

  Wright wrote a pamphlet shortly after John Brown’s execution entitled, No Rights, No Duties: Or, Slaveholders, As Such, Have No Rights, Slaves As Such Owe No Duties.  An Answer To A Letter From Hon. Henry Wilson, Touching Resistance To Slaveholders Being The Right And Duty Of The Slaves, And Of The People Of The Slaves Of The North.[50]

The thesis he presented was simple.  Slaves have no obligations at all to their masters, who good or bad, deserve no more respect or consideration than a gang of pirates or kidnappers.  Freedom must be won by the slaves themselves in alliance with their sympathizers among white freemen–by all and every means that the latter would feel justified in using against “burglars, incendiaries, and highway robbers” who might threaten them.  “It is the duty of the people and States of the North to invade slaveholding States to free the slaves, and annihilate the power that enslaves them.”  There are but two sides in the conflict to break up these kidnapping, piratical hordes of the South, called States. . . . You must fight for liberty or slavery–for the pirates or their victims.[52]

  In this pamphlet, Wright advocated the revolutionary doctrines practiced by Brown and preached by Thoreau and Lysander Spooner.  Thoreau, in his final years, was heavily influenced by the activities of John Brown, whom he had met.  “At the news of John Brown’s capture, Thoreau was on fire, arguing with his neighbors, giving speeches, and generally supporting the course of action John Brown had chosen.”[53] Thoreau specifically approved of the Harper’s Ferry raid and remarked in his address, “A Plea for Captain John Brown”:

It was his [Brown’s] peculiar doctrine that a man has a perfect right to interfere by force with the slaveholder, in order to rescue the slave. I agree with him.  Those who are continually shocked by slavery have some right to be shocked by the violent death of the slaveholder, but no others.  Such will be more shocked by his life than by his death.  I shall not be forward to think him mistaken in his method who quickest succeeds to liberate the slave.  I speak for the slave when I say that I prefer the philanthropy of Captain Brown to that philanthropy which neither shoots nor liberates me. . . . We preserve the so-called peace of our community by deeds of petty violence everyday.  Look at the policeman’s billy and handcuffs!  Look at the jail! Look at the gallows! . . . I think I know that the mass of my countrymen think that the only righteous use of Sharp’s rifles and revolvers is to fight duels with them when we are insulted by other nations or to hunt Indians or shoot fugitive slaves with them, or the like. I think that for once the Sharp’s rifles and revolvers were employed in a righteous cause.  The tools were in the hands of one who could use them.[54]

      Several days before his execution, Brown was asked what he had in mind when he made his attack on Harper’s Ferry arsenal.  Brown answered: “I knew there were a great many guns there that would be of service to me, and if I could conquer Virginia, the balance of the Southern states could nearly conquer themselves, there being such a large number of slaves in them.”[55]  According to the Chatham Constitution of May 1858, Brown intended no offensive warfare against the South, but only to restore the inherent rights of the Negroes there. “Not revolution, but justice, not aggression but defense.”56

  Had Brown and his men been successful, they would have implemented the designs of Lysander Spooner’s “Plan for the Abolition of Slavery.” This manifesto was printed in the summer of 1858, and included a notice to the “Non-Slaveholders of the South.”  Brown was familiar with Spooner and the two had met in Boston sometime between May 10 and June 2,1859.  At that time, Brown requested that Spooner cease circulation of his broadsides since their further publication might embarrass Brown’s future plans.  After the failure of the raid at Harper’s Ferry, Spooner’s “Plan” was published in a New York newspaper and was described as Gerrit Smith’s blueprint for Brown’s expedition.  In a subsequent suit for libel, Smith (using Spooner as his attorney) settled the case out of court.  The Spooner manifesto offers a highly consistent rationale for Brown’s attack, but Spooner in later correspondence made it very clear that Brown knew nothing of it until after it was printed.[57]  The two men arrived at the same conclusions independently, reasoning from the common premise that one was legitimately entitled to come to the assistance of the slave and forcibly resist the oppression of the slaveholder.

  Spooner’s reasoning was based on the following four principles:

1. That the slaves have a natural right to their liberty.

2. That they have a natural right to compensation (so far as the property of the Slaveholders and their abettors can compensate them) for the wrongs they have suffered.

3. That so long as the government under which they live refuse to give them liberty or compensation they have the right to take it by stratagem or force.

4. That it is the duty of all, who can, to assist them in such an enterprise.[58]

Based on these premises, Spooner urged that all political institutions of the slaveholder be spurned and ignored.  In their place should be established government which recognizes slaveholding as a crime and which grants to the slaves civil actions for damages for the wrongs already committed against them. The slaves should be recognized as the rightful owners of the plantations they had worked, which would be awarded to them for the damages they had already suffered.  The non-slaveholders of the South were also encouraged to form vigilance committees or leagues of freedom, whose duty it should be to see that justice was done to the slaves and that punishment was meted out to the slaveholders. 

  Realizing that some might object to the distribution of the slaveholders’ property to their slaves, Spooner wrote:

Perhaps some may say that this taking of property by the Slaves would be stealing, and should not be encouraged.  The answer is that it would not be stealing, it would be simply taking justice into their own hands and redressing their own wrongs.  The State of Slavery is a state of war.  In this case it is a just war, on the part of the negroes–a war for liberty and a recompense for injuries and necessity justified them in carrying it on by the only means their oppressors have left to them.  In war, the plunder of enemies is as legitimate as the killing of them, and stratagem is as legitimate as open force. The right of the slaves, therefore, in this war, to take property is as clear as their right to take life, and their right to do it secretly is as clear as their right to do it openly.  And as this will probably be their most effective mode of operation for the present, they ought to be taught, encouraged, and assisted to do it to the utmost so long as they are unable to meet their enemies in the open field.  And to call this taking of property, stealing is as false and unjust as it would be to call the taking of life in just war, murder.[59]

Spooner’s reasoning rested on the recognition of the slave’s rightful claim to personal liberty as well as to reparations for having been a slave.  To achieve liberty and compensation required that the slaves escape from their masters and form guerrilla bands, and assemble the means to sustain themselves in war against the slaveholders.  “These bands could do a good work of kidnapping individual slaveholders, holding them as hostages for the good behavior of whites remaining on the plantation, compelling them to execute deeds of emancipation, and conveyances of their property to their slaves.”[60]  If the property of the slaveholder could not be converted to the use of the slaves, then Spooner advised its destruction.  Spooner suggested that the white non-slaveholders of the South abandon their present governments: “Pay not taxes to their government, if you can either resist them or evade them; as witness and juror give no testimony and no verdicts in support of any slaveholding claims.”

  Those whites who voluntarily assisted the slaveholders in keeping their slaves under subjection were the object of special attention by Spooner:

You are one of the main pillars of the Slave System.  You stand ready to do all that vile and inhuman work which must be done by somebody but which the more decent slaveholders will themselves not do. . . . If you are thus indifferent as to whom you serve, we advise you henceforth to serve the slaves instead of their masters.  Turn about and help the robbed to rob their robbers.  The former can afford to pay you better than the latter.  Help them to get possession of the property which is rightfully their due, and they can afford to give you liberal commission.[61]

  Spooner’s position on the right of the slaves to commission assistance based on a sharing of the proceeds of plunder realized from the just wars of the slaves against their masters may have been unique:

If it is right for the Slaves to take the property of their masters, to compensate their wrongs, it is right for you [the non-slaveholders of the South] to help them. . . . It will be perfectly easy for you, by combining with the slaves to put them in possession of the plantations on which they labor, and of all the property upon them.  They could afford to pay you well for doing them such a service.  They could afford to let you share with them in the division of property taken.[62]

  In his “Plan for the Abolition of Slavery” Spooner addressed himself to those Northerners who were willing to come to the aid of the slaves.  Spooner recognized that “when a human being is set upon by a robber, ravisher, murderer, or tyrant of any kind, it is the duty of bystanders to go to his or her rescue by force, if need be.  In general nothing will excuse men in the non-performance of this duty, except the pressure of higher duties (if there be such), inability to afford relief, or too great danger to themselves or others.” Legislation notwithstanding, “it is the duty of the non-slaveholders of this country, in their private capacity as individuals,–without asking the permission or waiting the movements of the government–to go to the rescue of the Slaves from the hands of their oppressors.”[63]

  Private war against the slaveholders of the South was what Spooner advocated. It was John Brown, however, who put Spooner’s reasoning into practice.

[I]n revolutions of this nature, it is necessary that private individuals should take the first step.  The tea must be thrown overboard, the Bastille must he torn down, the first gun must be fired, by private persons, before a new government can be organized or the old one will be forced to adopt the measures which the insurgents have in view.[64]

No one could have been more radical or daring than John Brown in calling for the abolition of slavery.  In 1859, Spooner was still committed to favoring some type of government.  As the Civil War progressed. Spooner continued to spin out the implications of his natural law reasoning. By the late 1860’s he had carried his natural rights theory to its infinitely radical conclusion: individualist anarchism.[65]

  Even prior to the Civil War, Spooner had offered strong theoretical support to disobedience to the State.  He believed that if one is coerced, if one lives under a tyranny, then one is fully justified in resorting to force in return or in disobeying government law.  He maintained that private war was a form of individual self-defense and that force in response to force was always justified.  As part of his theory, Spooner recognized a higher law than State law; that natural justice supersedes State legislation and the results of State jurisprudence. If the Fugitive Slave Law commanded the return of the slaves, then it was wrong because it contradicted natural law, and it must be disobeyed. Eventually Spooner arrived at the conclusion that all (State) legislation was a crime, an absurdity, and a usurpation.

  Both Spooner and Thoreau were “impossible citizens,” who judged the State and all its laws for themselves and acted according to the dictates of their own consciences rather than according to the demands of the State.  It is interesting to note the similarity between the thinking of Spooner and Thoreau.  As contemporaries, Spooner preceded Thoreau in actively opposing the State. Spooner openly challenged the requirements of the Massachusetts legislature concerning admittance to the State Bar in 1833.  In 1844, he had operated a private mail company in contravention of the federal laws imposing a government monopoly on mail delivery.  Spooner relied on a strict construction of the Constitution and a theory of natural rights and natural justice to defend his behavior.  With the same theories he also defended active rebellion against the State and eventually came to deny its authority.  Thoreau went to jail to offer testimony to his convictions.  He supported John Brown’s attempt to free the slaves in Virginia. He advocated peaceful revolution, whereby the masses withdrew their support from the State. Thoreau was one of the first to draw attention to the duty of civil disobedience.  He placed primary emphasis on loyalty to one’s conscience and natural law rather than to the State.  As “impossible citizens,” libertarians and civil resistants today would be hard pressed to match the daring, the determination, and the quality of resistance that we have found in 19th Century New England.

NOTES

1. For a critical analysis of the State see Benjamin Tucker, Instead of a Book (New York: B. Tucker, Publisher, 1893), especially his essay “The Relation of the State to the Individual.” Also see Murray Rothbard. For a New Liberty (New York: Macmillan Co., 1973).

2. Mulford Sibley and Phillip Jacob, Conscription of Conscience (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1952), pp. 1-2.

3. Raymond Adams, “Thoreau’s Sources for Resistance to Civil Government,” 42 Studies in Philology (1945), p. 646.

4. John C. Broderick, “Thoreau, Alcott, and the Poll Tax,” 53 Studies in Philology (1956), p. 614.  Also see Henry Canby, Thoreau, (Boston: Houghton, Mifflin and Co., 1939), pp. 233-239 and 472-473.

5. Henry David Thoreau, Walden and “On The Duly of Civil Disobedience” (New York: New American Library, 1960), p. 118.

6. Ibid, p. 236.

7. Walter Harding, The Days of Henry Thoreau (New York: Alfred Knopf, 1966), pp. 199-200. Also see Thoreau. op. cit., p. 233.

8. Thoreau, op. cit., p. 240.

9. Ibid., p. 225.

10 Ibid., pp. 224-225.

11. Ibid., p. 229.

12. Ibid., p. 228.

13. Ibid., p.229.

14. Harding, op. cit., p. 207.

15. Odell Shepard, Pedlar’s Progress: The Life of Branson Alcott (Boston: Little Brown and Co., 1937), p. 345 and 353.

16. Ralph L. Rusk, ed., The Letters of Ralph Waldo Emerson (New York: Columbia University Press, 1939), III, 230.

17. Thoreau, op. cit., p. 229

18. The Liberator (January 27, 1843). p. 4.

19. F. B. Sanborn, Bronson Alcott at Alcott House. England and Fruitlands, New England (Cedar Rapids: The Torch Press, 1908), p. 47.

20. Ibid., p. 45.

21. Ibid., p. 49.

22. Odell Shepard, ed., The Journals of Bronson Alcott (Boston: Little Brown and Co., 1938), p. 151.

23. Ibid., p. 179.

24. Ibid., p. 183.

25. Shepard, op. cit., p. 282.

26. Clara Endicott Sears, Bronson Alcott’s Fruitlands (Boston: Houghton Mifflin and Co., 1915), p. 53.

27. Ibid., p. 55.

28. Ibid., p. 60.

29. Ibid., p. 66.

30. Shepard, ed., op. cit., p. 246.

31. Gilbert Seldes, The Stammering Century (New York: John Day and Co., 1928). p. 220.

32. James Elliot Cabot, A Memoir of Ralph Waldo Emerson (Boston: Houghton Mifflin and Co., 1887), II, 597-98.

33. John Demos, “The Anti-Slavery Movement and the Problem of Violent ‘Means’,” 37 New England Quarterly (1964). p. 50l.

34. Fanny Garrison Villard, William Lloyd Garrison on Non-Resistance (New York: Nation Press, 1924), pp. 48-49.

35. Demos, op. cit., p. 510.

36. Lewis Perry, Radical Abolitionism-Anarchy and the Government of God in Antislavery Thought (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1973), p. 57.

37. Villard, op. cit., p. xi.

38. Demos, op. cit., p. 512.

39. Perry, loc. cit.

40. Thoreau, op. cit., p. 223.

41. Adams, op. cit., pp. 647-649.

42. Thoreau, op. cit., p. 231.

43. Henry David Thoreau, The Writings of Henry David Thoreau, “Slavery in Massachusetts” (New York: AMS Press, 1968), IV, 401.

44. Adams, loc. cit.

45. Peter Brock, Pacifism in the United States (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1968), p. 599.

46. Ibid., p. 600.

47. Brock, loc. cit.

48. Broderick, op. cit., p. 617.

49. Ibid., p. 617. Brock also comments on p. 600 that the anti-slavery movement did not “produce its Thoreaus to spend their night of lonely protest in the local jail or to endure the prolonged distraints suffered earlier by the Quakers during the Revolutionary War.”

50. Brock, op. cit., p. 683.

51. Henry C. Wright, No Rights, No Duties (Boston: Printed for the Author, 1860).

52. Brock, op. cit., p. 684.

53. Gilman M. Ostrander, “Emerson, Thoreau, and John Brown.” 53 Studies in Philology (1956). pp. 723-724.

54. Writings of Henry David Thoreau, IV, 433-434.

55. Jules Abels, Man on Fire: John Brown and the Cause of Liberty (New York: Macmillan Co., 1971), p. 242.

56. James Redpath, The Public Life of John Brown (Boston: Thayer and Eldridge, 1860). p. 233.

57. Charles Shively. ed., The Collected Works of Lysander Spooner, Vol IV–Anti-Slavery Writings (Weston, Mass.: M & S Press, 1971). See pp. 4-7 of the “Introduction” to “A Plan for the Abolition of Slavery” and “To the Non-Slaveholders of the South.”

58. Spooner, “To the Non-Slaveholders of the South,” column 1.

59. Ibid,, column 1.

60. Ibid., column 2. On this paint Spooner adds that no objection could be made to the fact that deeds of emancipation and conveyances of property were made under duress. “[l]n as much as such contracts would be nothing more than justice; and men may rightfully be coerced to do justice,” they could not be contested.

61. Ibid., column 3.

62. Ibid., column 3.

63. Spooner, “A Plan for the Abolition of Slavery,” column 1.

64. Ibid., column 3.

65. Murray Rothbard, “Introduction” to Lysander Spooner’s Natural Law of the Science of Justice, The Libertarian Forum (September 1974), p. 1.

“Come What, Come Will!” Richard Overton, Libertarian Leveller


 

by Carl Watner

The Levellers were a group of politically active soldiers and civilians whose organized efforts during the English Civil War (1642-1649) were based on their beliefs in individual liberty.  John Lilburne was their popularly recognized leader, but it is in the works of his associate, Richard Overton, that we find the most consistent expression of their incipient libertarianism.  In this essay, we will make first a preliminary survey of the libertarian aspects of the Leveller movement, and then a more detailed examination of the pamphleteering career of Richard Overton.

  From our vantage point in the twentieth century, not all Leveller thinking is consonant with modern libertarianism, but it is probably a fair statement to say that the Leveller organization was the first modern political movement to embrace the principles of individual liberty to any great extent.  One modern historian of the movement, H. N. Brailsford, has distinguished three basic ideas in the web of Leveller thought. First, the Levellers were quite concerned with the realm of each person’s individuality or self-propriety, as they termed it.  Although they never explicitly used the term self-ownership, self-propriety had the same connotation: the right of each and every person to control his or her own body and soul free of coercive molestation. During a period of bitter religious strife, the Levellers stressed religious freedom–the right of each person to worship (or not to worship) as he or she chose. They also emphasized the right of the individual to decide whether or not to bear arms; in short, the right to be free of conscription. Secondly, the Levellers affirmed the individual’s right of association with other like-minded people, whether it be a voluntary church or a group of people printing their own books and pamphlets without government censorship. This also included the right of combination for political ends, which at that time meant the writing and distribution of petitions and all the meetings and publicity that this entailed.  Their third basic idea involved equality of all before the law, both of rich and poor, noble and simple; and, particularly and most importantly, the equality of all in the sphere of political power.  The Levellers advocated the abolition of all class privileges and government grants of monopoly, the simplification of legal procedure, and a more widespread form of manhood suffrage.  They also called for an end to tithes, excise duties, customs duties, imprisonment for debt, and conscription.[1]

  The Levellers were not socialists or left-wing supporters of Cromwell, but rather individualist.[2]  Following the Anabaptist tradition, they disowned coercion of all innocent people and affirmed a position of broad religious tolerance.[3]  They were the first political movement outside of the Netherlands to stand for unqualified toleration, including acceptance of Jews and Catholics in England.  Nor did they wish to charge the state with the responsibility for enforcing personal morality. No Leveller petition ever included among the reforms demanded the repression of swearing and drinking, or the more strict observance of the Sabbath, or the banishment of fiddlers from the taverns.  The Levellers made the final breach with theocracy when they modified their appeal for religious toleration to a plea for the complete divorce between religion and the state. Theirs is the distinction of being the first movement in the modern world to call for a secular republic.[4]

  Although they were accused of “setting up an utopian anarchy of the promiscuous multitude,” they were not outright anarchist.[5]  Towards the end of their existence as an organized political party, Walwyn, one of their four recognized leaders, wrote:

That we are for Government and against Popular Confusion, we conceive all our actions declare, when rightly considered, our aim having been all along to reduce it as near as might be to perfection, and certainly we know very well that depravity and corruption of man’s heart is such that there could be no living without it; and that though Tyranny is excessively bad, yet of the two extremes, Confusion is the worst: Tis somewhat a strange consequence to infer that because we have labored so earnestly for a good Government, therefore we would have none at all; Because we would have the dead and exorbitant Branches pruned, and better sciens grafted, therefore we would pluck the Tree up by the roots.[6]

  Yet they recognized that no man could be bound, in a political sense, but by his own consent.[7]  They admitted of no sovereignty anywhere except in the individual.  The Levellers “seriously accepted the possibility of any man refusing obedience to commands incompatible with his idea of reason or justice.  This may appear anarchic, but to them it was the ultimate guarantee of liberty.”[8]

  In the context of the English Civil War, the Levellers believed that resistance to King Charles I and his party was not resistance to “magistracy”, as government was called, but rather resistance to tyranny.  Overton wrote that tyranny could never be true magistracy and that every man was duty bound to endeavor to bring about the extirpation and removal of the usurpers and oppressors from the seat of government.[9] Therefore the Levellers held that resistance and rebellion against an existing tyrannical government was lawful and right. Although the Levellers were originally aligned with Cromwell and the Independents, they soon realized that Cromwell, with Parliament under his control, was merely another usurper.  Thus, if tyranny was resistible in a king, then they concluded that it was also resistible in Parliament.[10]

  The Leveller’s general devotion to English common law and the traditional British liberties is best exemplified in Lilburne’s attitude towards the trial and execution of Charles I.  Lilburne opposed trying the king by a special court.  He had no objection in principle to the trial of the king, or to his execution if he were found guilty. However, according to Lilburne’s view, neither the Long Parliament nor the Rump was entitled to try the king or send him to trial.  He wished to postpone all action against the king until some sort of constitutional settlement could be made.  To Lilburne, this meant the acceptance by the people at large of the Agreement of the People.  Any action which the Rump took against the king would be arbitrary and an abuse of the power of the sword.  The High Court of Justice, which was appointed to try the king, was an extraordinary tribunal, an invention of a political emergency and packed with partisans.  The vague charge of treason against the king was open to the fatal criticism that it was based on no known law.  Instead, Lilburne urged that the king was entitled to a trial by jury in the regular courts of the land and subject to the judgment of twelve jurors, like every other Englishman. The charge for which he should stand was that he had counseled and commissioned murder (on the battlefield).[11]  Despite their enmity towards the king, Lilburne and most of the other Levellers were objective enough in their thinking to realize that if arbitrary treatment could be meted out to the king, contrary to known forms of law, then they, too, might be subject to such capricious treatment.  Overton, alone among the Leveller leaders, approved without reservation the manner and execution of judging the king; he called it the finest piece of justice that was ever had in England.

  Although much Leveller support originated in the Army, they were always cautious lest the military power of the Army supersede civilian legal authority. Of course, their fears were borne out.  In their eyes, an English soldier was first an English citizen, with all the concomitant rights and duties of a citizen; and then, only secondarily, were they “volunteer” soldiers who had taken up arms to defend the parliamentary cause. In their estimation, they could not be sent overseas without their own consent.  Therefore Cromwell’s attempt to subdue Ireland, together with the chronic shortage and lateness of pay for the soldiers, generated much discontent in the Army, manifesting itself in a libertarian opposition to imperialism and militarism.  The Levellers saw the Catholic Irish as their fellow men, who were as much entitled to claim their own liberty as were the Levellers themselves.  Their code of ethics bridged foreign borders.  In general, the Levellers rated the sovereignty of the individual’s conscience high above the commands of military generals or the jurisdiction of the state.  The Levellers established the moral foundation for opposition to Cromwellian imperialism by recognizing the individual Irishman’s claim to his own land.  They asked if it was not as unjust to take away the laws and liberties of the Irishmen as it was to deprive an Englishman of his.  Leveller anti-militarism and anti-imperialism was climaxed by the death of a young Leveller soldier, who was cashiered, court-martialed, and shot by Cromwell’s orders. Refusing to wear the usual bandage over his eyes, Robert Lockyer faced, without fear, the firing squad which shot him to death.  Before he fell he told those firing the shots that their obedience to superior orders did not acquit them of murder.[12]  The Leveller defense of the right of the Irish to keep their own fields and practice their own faith is the earliest, and not the least distinguished, example in English history of the struggle of a popular party against imperialism.”[13]

  In Leveller opinion, Cromwell’s imperialism was just another instance of his and Parliament’s failure to govern by law after having succeeded Charles I to power.  Lilburne and Overton saw the English nation as having therefore been reduced to the original law of nature, and they reasoned that individual citizens no longer owed any obedience or allegiance to these tyrannical politicians.  The Levellers proposed that a new political settlement be made in which all Englishmen would give their consent to the Agreement of the People.  The Agreement was a written, “constitutional” document prepared and revised several times by the Leveller leaders.  It called for the abolition of the Long Parliament and the selection of a new Parliament based on more equitable and democratic rules.  The Agreement itself was not to be passed upon by Parliament, since it was meant to be superior to Parliament.  The Levellers hoped that the document would be unanimously adopted by members of the Army and then be signed by the people at large at the first general election.  It was clearly the forerunner of our modern constitutions and plainly illustrates the Leveller’s premise that society could be constituted on an entirely voluntary basis.[14]

  The adoption by Leveller thinkers of a “state of nature” theory was quite evident in the Putney Debates, which took place between the Levellers and the Army grandees in 1647.  The debates illustrate the radical nature of Leveller thought. In regard to the Army’s past promises, the Levellers theorized that nothing was binding if it conflicted with reason, justice, and the safety of the people.[15]  When Henry Ireton, Cromwell’s son-in-law, claimed that the Levellers would destroy all property, they confidently appealed to the law of nature to demonstrate that the right to property is guaranteed by the law of nature, and not, as Ireton maintained, merely by positive government laws.[16] Clarke, one of the Leveller debaters, argued that the Law of nature is the basis of all constitutions.  “Yet really properties are the foundations of constitutions, and not constitutions of property. For if so be there were no constitutions, yet the law of nature does give a principle for every man to have a property of what he has or may have which is not another man’s.  This natural right of property is the ground of mine and thine.”[17]  Furthermore, it is the law of nature that teaches the individual his rights and their attendant duties: the right and duty of self-preservation, and the natural limits of obedience, and the right and duty of resistance to tyrannical rulers. It teaches him what are the ends of government; and it inculcates the basic principles of social life–the principles of natural justice and equity which dictate the political equality of all men within the state and which are based upon the maxim “to do unto others as you would have them do unto you.”[18]

  The Levellers, especially Lilburne, were sensitive about their name and its connotations, and they protested repeatedly that they had no intention of levelling men’s estates (i.e., forcefully distributing property from the rich to the poor).  There is no question, however, that it was their intention to end every form of political and legal privilege, privilege which served to enrich members of the governing class.[19] The basic rift in society, for the Levellers, was not the division between wage earner and capitalist, but between the rich who profited from government monopolies and privileges and the poor and middle class who suffered from such favoritism.  In effect, the Levellers saw a conflict between the producers and the politicians in society.  Within a few months after the Putney Debates, the Levellers were espousing a remarkably class-conscious theory of the State, in which the Independent leaders were seen as part of a conspiracy of the rich and powerful to keep down the poorer and more industrious people.[20]

  Lilburne was one of the firmest defenders of a positive social order based on property.[21] He was not opposed to the taking of interest on money loans nor for the renting of land.  He claimed that the Levellers were the truest and most constant asserters of liberty and property (“which are quite opposite to community and levelling”).[22] In one of his later books, Lilburne states his strongest disavowal of levelling.  He not only denies his party’s intention to level property, but also condemns any who do aim to level property.  In Lilburne’s opinion and judgment,

this Conceit of Levelling of property and Magistracy is so ridiculous and foolish an opinion, as no man of brains, reason, or ingenuity, can be imagined such a sot as to maintain such a principle, because it would, if practiced destroy not only any industry in the world, but raze the very foundation of generation, and of subsistence or being of one man by another.  For as industry and valour by which the societies of mankind are maintained and preserved, who will take the pains for that which when he hath gotten is not his own, but must be equally shared in, by every lazy, simple, dronish sot? or who will fight for that, wherein he hath no other interest, but such as must be subject to the will and pleasure of another, yea of every coward and base low spirited fellow, that in his sitting still must share in common with a valiant man in all his brave and noble achievement? The ancient encouragement to men that were to defend their Country was this: that they were to hazard their persons for that which was their own, to wit, their own wives, their own children, their own Estates.  And this, give me leave to say, and that in truth, that those men in England, that are most branded with the name of Levellers, are of all in that Nation, most free from any design of Levelling, in the sense we have spoken of.[23]

  No Leveller leader ever called for the compulsory redistribution of property, but Walwyn did go so far as to advocate a voluntary sort of communism, if it were first agreed upon unanimously by those participating. In Walwyn’s opinion the attempt to induce the levelling of men’s estates was most injurious, “unless there did precede an universal assent thereunto from all and every one of the People.”  He further pointed out:

The Community amongst the primitive Christians, was Voluntary, not Coercive; they brought their goods and laid them at the Apostles feet, they were not enjoined to bring them, it was the effect of their Charity. . . .

  We [the Levellers] profess therefore that we never had it in our thoughts to Level men’s estates, it being the utmost of our aim that the Commonwealth be reduced to such a pass that every man may with as much security as may he enjoy his propriety.[25]

Though each Leveller leader had his own opinion on the subject, their commonly subscribed statements explicitly demanded that Parliament be legally bound not to level men’s estates, destroy propriety, or make all things common.[25] They all insisted that property was a natural right of the individual. It was on this concept of natural right that they based their case, not only for individual property, but also for government by consent and for civil and religious liberties. Their fundamental position was that every man is naturally the proprietor of his own person.[26]

  This fundamental position is most strikingly set forth in some of Richard Overton’s pamphlets, which were written as Leveller propaganda. Both in his An Arrow Against All Tyrants (October 10, 1646) and in his Appeal (July 1647) he endorses a principled and far-reaching theory of natural rights from which he derives all civil and political rights.  The two opening paragraphs of the Arrow deserve being quoted in full:

To every individual in nature is given an individual property by nature, not to he invaded or usurped by any: for every one as he is himself, so he hath a self propriety, else could he not be himself, and on this no second may presume to deprive any of, without manifest violation and affront to the very principles of nature, and of the Rules of equity and justice between man and man; mine and thine cannot he, except this be; No man hath power over my rights and liberties, and I over no man’s; I may he but an Individual, enjoy my self, and my self propriety, and may write myself no more than my self, or presume any further; if I do, I am an encroacher and an invader upon an other man’s Right, to which I have no Right.  For by natural birth, all men are equally alike and born to like propriety, liberty, and freedom, and as we are delivered of God by the hand of nature into this world, every one with a natural, innate freedom and propriety (as it were writ in the table of every man’s heart, never to be obliterated) even so are we to live, every one equally and alike to enjoy his Birth-right and privilege; even all whereof God by nature hath made him free.

  And this by nature every one desires aims at, and requires for no man naturally would be befooled of his liberty by his neighbor’s craft, or enslaved by his neighbor’s might, for it is nature’s instinct to preserve it self, from all things hurtful and obnoxious, and this in nature is granted of all to be most reasonable, equal and just, not to be rooted out of the kind, even of equal duration with the creature: And from this fountain or root, all just human powers take their original; not immediately from God (as Kings usually plead their prerogative) but mediately by the hand of nature, as from the represented to the representors; for originally, God hath implanted them in the creature, and from the creature those powers immediately proceed; and no further: and no more may be communicated than stands for the better being weal, or safety thereof: and this is man’s prerogative and no further, so much and no more may be given or received thereof: even so much as is conducent to a better being, more safety and freedom, and no more; he that gives more sins against his own flesh; and he that takes more, is a Thief and Robber to his kind: Every man by nature being a King, Priest and Prophet in his own natural circuit and compass, whereof no second may partake, but by deputation, commission, and free consent from him, whose natural right and freedom it is.[27]

In the Appeal Overton makes an even more positive assertion of the reason for natural right and self-propriety:

It is a firm Law and radical principle in Nature, engraven in the tables of the heart by the finger of God in creation for every living moving thing, wherein there is a breath of life to defend, preserve, award, and deliver it self from all things hurtful, destructive and obnoxious thereto to the utmost of its power: Therefore from hence is conveyed to all men in general, and to every man in particular, an undoubted principle of reason, by all rational and just ways and means possibly he may, to save, defend and deliver himself from all oppression, violence and cruelty whatsoever, and (in duty to his own safety and being) to leave no just expedient unattempted for his delivery therefrom: and this is rational and just; to deny it is to overturn the law of nature, yea, and of Religion too; for the contrary lets in nothing but self murder, violence and cruelty.[28]

  Here is Overton’s ultimate justification for himself and the Leveller movement. In tones that presage those of John Locke of the 1680’s and Thomas Paine of the 1770’s, Overton marshals the dogmas of natural liberty in support of popular government by consent, toleration, and freedom of the press.[29] Here is the “proprietorial quality of the Levellers’ individualism.” Every man and woman, being an individual person, is entitled to self-propriety. “What makes a man human is his freedom from other men.” Man’s essence is his freedom and that can only mean self-control over one’s own person and capacities.  However, self-proprietorship did not mean passive enjoyment.  “The Levellers demanded this manifold property in one’s own person as a prerequisite of active use and enjoyment of one’s capacities.  Men were created to improve, and enjoy by improving, their capacities.  Their propriety in themselves excluded all others, but did not exclude their duty to their creator and to themselves.”[30]

  The little known of Overton’s career is that it was short and hectic. The best of his writings were written while he was in jail.  He probably spent some part of his early life in Holland, where he learned the printing trade and imbibed the Anabaptist tradition of dissent. By the mid-1640’s he had made the acquaintance of John Lilburne and joined with him in attacking the established church.  In 1643, Overton wrote an anonymous tract entitled Man’s Mortality, setting forth his sectarian views on religion.  He was repeatedly denounced as a heretic, but kept writing his various satirical and anti-clerical pamphlets which he printed on his own press.  In 1646, Overton became concerned over the imprisonment of Lilburne and participated in drafting A Remonstrance of Many Thousand Citizens, and Other Free-Born People of England, to Their Own House of Commons. Occasioned Through the Illegal and Barbarous Imprisonment of that Famous and Worthy Sufferer for His Country’s Freedoms, Lieutenant Col. John Lilburne (July 7, 16461.[31]

  The Remonstrance opens with a very clear statement of the Leveller theory of government– one based on consent of the governed and on a delegation of powers from the citizenry to their elected representatives.

We are well assured, yet cannot forget, that the cause of our choosing you to be Parliament-men, was to deliver us from all kind of Bondage, and to preserve the Common-wealth in Peace and Happiness: For effecting whereof, we possessed you with the same Power that was in our selves, to have done the same; For we might justly have done it our selves without you, if we had thought it convenient. . . .

  But ye are to remember, this was only of us but a Power of trust, (which is ever revokable, and cannot be otherwise,) and to be employed to no other end, than our own well-being. . . . We are your Principals, and you our Agents; it is a Truth which you cannot but acknowledge; For if you or any other shall assume, or exercise any Power, that is not derived from our Trust and choice thereunto, that Power is no less than usurpation and Oppression, from which we expect to be freed, in whomsoever we find it; it being altogether inconsistent with the nature of just Freedom, which ye also very well understand.[32]

After outlining the historical failure of former kings to maintain the people’s liberties, the Remonstrance declares that men of the present age will no longer bear the tyranny of Charles I and that the members of Parliament, who

were chosen to work our deliverance, and to Estate us in natural and just liberty agreeable to Reason and common equity; for whatever our Fore-fathers were; or whatever they did or suffered, or were enforced to yield unto; we are men of the present age, and ought to be absolutely free from all kinds of exorbitances and molestations or Arbitrary Power, and you we choose to free us from all without exception or limitation, . . .and we were full of confidence that ye also would have dealt impartially on our behalf, and made us the most absolute free People in the world.[33]

  The Remonstrance also illustrates the Leveller attitude towards religious toleration.  Although it admits that the House of Commons might propose what form of religion they deem best and might offer such to the public, the authors of Remonstrance firmly declare that no Englishman can be compelled to embrace a state religion.

Whereas truly we are well assured, neither you, nor none else, can have any into Power at all to conclude the People in matters that concern the Worship of God, for therein every one of us ought to be fully assured in our own minds, and to be sure to Worship him according to our Consciences.

  Ye may propose what Form ye conceive best, and most available for Information and well-being of the Nation, and may persuade, and invite thereunto, but compell, ye cannot justly; for ye have no Power from Us so to do, nor could you have; for we could not confer a Power that was not in our selves, there being none of Us, that can without wilfull sin bind our selves to Worship God after any other way, than what (to a tittle,) in our own particular understandings, we approve to be just.[34]

  The Remonstrance ends with a list of grievances that the Levellers have against the House of Commons, by whom they believe that they have been betrayed.  A call is made for an “agreement of the people,” since the members of the House of Commons know that the “Laws of this Nation are unworthy a Free-People, and deserve from first to last, to be considered, and seriously debated, and reduced to an agreement with common equity, and right reason, which ought to be the Form and Life of every Government.”[35]  The Levellers were particularly grieved about the practice of conscription, and in probably one of the earliest attacks on that practice they wrote:

We entreat you to consider what difference there is, between binding a man to an Oar, as a Gally-slave in Turkey or Algeria, and Pressing of men to serve in your War; to surprise a man on the sudden, force him from his Calling, where he lived comfortably, from a good trade; from his dear Parents, Wife or Children, against inclination, disposition to fight for a Cause he understands not, and in Company of such, as he has no comfort to be with; for Pay, that will scarce give him sustenance; and if he live, to return to a lost trade, or beggary, or not much better: If any Tyranny or cruelty exceed this; it must be worse than that of a Turkish Gally-slave.[36]

The Levellers also complained about the imposition of customs duties on imports and claimed that their collection was most prejudicial to the nation. There were so many customs officers that “it is a very slavery to have any thing to do with them.”  The Levellers lamented that “Truly it is a sad thing, but too true, a plain quiet-minded man in any place in England, is just like a harmless sheep in a Thicket, can hardly move or stir, but he shall be stretched, and loose his wool.”[37]

  Overton continued to express his support for Lilburne, and about August 1, 1646 he published another one of his anonymous pamphlets, An Alarum to the House of Lords.  In it Overton rebelliously warned the Lords that “if timely cautions will not avail with you, you must expect to be bridled, for we are resolved upon our natural Rights and Freedoms, and to be enslaved to none, how magnificent so ever, with rotten titles of honor.”[38]  Lilburne had been imprisoned partly because of his written attacks on the vested interests of the day.  According to Overton, Lilburne’s writings 

have been dangerous to all corrupt Interests in the Commonwealth; as

First, to all Arbitrary Power, In King, or Lords, or any other.

Secondly, To the Power and delusion of the Clergy, and their oppression of Conscionable Religious People.

Thirdly, to the most prejudicial ways of our Legal Trials in all Courts, and to the burdensome Society of Lawyers; that live upon the impoverishing of the industrious and laborious People; things which he proveth to have been forced upon this nation by Conquest, and continued against Reason, and the weal of the People.

Fourthly, To all Monopolists, and engrossers of trade: as the Merchant Adventurers, and the like: all which he hath (as others), proved to the Ruin of the People: and because of this his love to Truth, Justice, and his Country; and his opening of these things; and his opposition thereof to the uttermost of his Power: all these mighty Parties, put all their policy and strength in one, utterly to destroy him.

  But he hath a good cause: and all good people (that desire not to 1ive by the Oppression of others,) on his side: and that your Lordships will find; for all these things will be laid open at the Sun, and every man will see wherefore it is you call his Books scandalous, seditious, dangerous Pamphlets, and why the Clergy, the Judges, Lawyers, and Monopolists, are his deadly adversaries, even because he deals plainly between you all; and the people, whom you labor by all means jointly to keep in bondage and Vassalage to your wills.[39]

  The House of Lords reacted against Overton’s Alarum by issuing orders for his immediate arrest, which took place on August 11, 1646, less than two weeks after the appearance of the pamphlet.  Overton was held as a prisoner of the Lords and eventually lodged in Newgate prison. It was not until September 16, 1647, after more than a year in prison, that he was freed by order of the House of Commons.  While imprisoned, Overton wrote and published some of his best pamphlet attacks on the Lords and Parliament.

  A Defiance, the first of his “prison” pamphlets, appeared on September 9, 1646, less than a month after his initial arrest. In his confrontations with the House of Lords, Overton took exactly the same stand as had Lilburne.  Overton simply denied their authority to question him, as he believed that, as a commoner, he was not at all subject to their jurisdiction.

I bid defiance to their injustice, usurpation and tyranny, and scorn even the least connivance, glimpse, jot, or tittle of their favor: let them do as much against me by the Rule of Equity, Reason, and Justice for my Testimony and Protestation against them in this thing as possibly they can, and I shall be content and rest: for Nihil quod est contra rationem est licitum; Nothing which is against reason is lawful, it is a sure maxim in law, for Reason is the life of Law.  But if they transgress, and go beyond the hounds of rationality, justice, and equity, I shall to the utmost of my power make opposition and contestation to the last gasp of vital breath; and I will not beg their favor, nor lie at their feet for mercy; let me have justice, or let me perish. I’ll not sell my birth-right for a mess of pottage, for Justice is my natural right, my heirdom, my inheritance by lineal descent from the loins of Adam, and so to all the sons of men as their proper right without respect of persons.  The crooked course of Favor, greatness, or the like, is not the proper channel of Justice; it is pure, and individual, equally and alike proper unto all, descending and running in that pure line streaming and issuing out unto all, though grievously corrupted, vitiated, and adulterated from generation to generation.[40]

  One of the great issues between Lilburne and Overton, and the House of Lords, was the question of self-incrimination.  Literally, these were the men who made the U. S. Constitution’s Fifth Amendment privilege against self-incrimination a reality.  According to Overton, the law of England bound no man to betray himself, as the abolition of the Star Chamber proceedings had confirmed, and his refusal to answer the interrogatories of the Lords, he asserted, was not evidence of his guilt, but only of his obstinacy in adhering to his legal rights.[41]

  An Arrow, Overton’s next pamphlet, was issued from prison on October 12, 1646.  As quoted earlier, the opening passages from An Arrow set forth Overton’s theory of natural self-propriety.  Overton then goes on to discuss representation and “magisterial,” or governmental, powers. He points out that a holder of governmental office is not immune to breaking either the common or natural law, and that government office must not be used as a shield or excuse for law-breaking. Any government officer, whether king or member of parliament, may be rightfully resisted if he has not complied with the law.  In Overton’s circumstances, this meant that neither King nor Lords could legally direct his apprehension or imprisonment until he had first been tried and convicted by a jury of his peers.  In a case such as his, any commoner might rightfully resist the agents or ministers of government, much as they would resist the unlawful advances of trespassers, thieves, burglars, felons, and murderers.  “No legal conviction being made, the person invaded and assaulted by such open force of Arms may lawfully arm themselves, fortify their Houses (which are their Castles in the judgment of the Law) against them, yea disarm, beat, wound, repress and kill them in their just necessary defense of their own persons, houses, goods, wives, and families, and not be guilty of the least offense.”[42]

  Still imprisoned in 1647, Overton issued yet another of his “prison” pamphlets on February 10th of that year.  He was still bound to state his case to the world and bring attention to his plight and that of his wife and family.  Overton’s intransigence had not waned even though he had been imprisoned since August 1646.  Around November 3, he had been brought before a Committee of the House of Commons, at their order, for an inquiry into the reason for his incarceration by the House of Lords.  He had hoped for justice at the Committee’s hands and, in this new pamphlet, entitled Commoners Complaint, had resolved

in myself, that as in heart I defied all injustice, cruelty, tyranny, and oppression, all arbitrary usurpation and usurpers whatsoever, so in person (come life, come death, come what come would) I would not be so treacherous to my own self, to my wife and children, and especially to this Nation (the Land of my Nativity) in general, as personally to yield my active submission of any limb that was mine (either in substance or in show).[43]

In effect his attitude was that, if his jailers did not have a valid warrant for remanding him back to Newgate prison, then he would not “set forth one leg before another” for them and they should have to carry him if he was to be returned to jail.

  Much of the Commoners Complaint is devoted to explaining Overton’s reasons for his course of resistance.  He wanted his reasons to be known, lest his actions be misunderstood by the public. He begins his defense by pointing out:

All State-Deprivation of life, limb, goods, liberty or freedom, either is, or should be, all and every particle thereof, the just execution of the Law executing: For in Equity, the Action executing is indivisible from the Law, and only and precisely proper thereto, and not at all to the party executed: yea, though a man legally guilty of death should be condemned by the same legal Authority (or rather by persons therein entrusted) to cut his own throat; yet were he in equity not bound thereunto, but in so doing should be guilty of his own blood. And the Law of our Land makes no man his own Executioner. . . .and nature itself teaches that no man shall be his own Butcher or Executioner, for in so doing, he should sin against his own flesh, which is a thing most unnatural and inhumane.

  But my rejection of carrying my own Body to the Gaol, was no other but the refusal to be my own Executioner therein, for though it were not of that degree of cruelty and inhumanity to my own flesh, as to cut my own throat; yet was it of the same nature and kind.  And therefore if the one must be condemned as unjust, illegal and unnatural, so must the other in its kind, so that as I was not bound, with my hands to cut my own throat, so with my feet, I was not bound to carry myself to prison.”[44]

  Overton then discourses on the relationship of Equity and Law and is not afraid to place the reason and equity of the law above Law itself:

Though the Letter of the Law should enjoin its Condemnants to be their own executioners, yet were that by its own equity condemned, nulled, and made void, for the letter must be subject to the equity: and look how much the letter transgressed the equity, even so much it is unequal, and is of no validity or force, for the Law taken from its original reason and end is made a shell without a kernel, a shadow without a substance, a Carcass without life: for the equity and reason thereof is that which gives it a legal being and life, and makes it authoritative and binding, if this be not granted, injustice may be a Law, tyranny may be a Law, lust, will, pride, covetousness, and what not? may be Laws; for if equity be not the bounder of the Law, over the corrupt nature of man, all will fall into confusion, and one man will devour another.”[45]

Overton did not want it said of him that he “went to prison”; rather it must be said of him that “he was carried there.”  Though his actions and resistance had no precedent in law he was prepared to argue the rationality of his behavior.  “Reason” was his only justification and “reason has no precedent; for reason is the fountain of all just precedents.”[46]  He was prepared to live or die to uphold his principles:

For as I am a Freeman by Birth, so I am resolved to live and die, both in heart word and deed, in substance and in show, maugre the Arbitrary malice of the House of Lords: yea if ought else I can devise to show my actual enmity and defiance against their arbitrary power, I’ll do it, though it cost the life of me, and mine, and therefore I care not who lets them know.[47]

Cementing his attitude with a bit of humor, Overton claimed that his legs were not subject to the jurisdiction of the Lords. Being free of their jurisdiction “from the Crown of my head to the Sole of my feet,” he knew no reason why he should “foot it for them,” or “dance” to their arbitrary warrants, except that they might “play to the good old tune of the Law of the Land.”[48]

  During his appearance before the Committee of the House of Commons, Overton engaged in a debate on which House of Parliament had jurisdiction over him.  It was his contention that, if the House of Commons had authority to recall him from jail and question him in committee, then he must be subject to their jurisdiction and not the jurisdiction of the House of Lords.  Therefore his jailers from Newgate had no authority to return him to prison, especially since the Commons’ Committee had not issued a warrant for his return.  Overton was playing a dangerous game, but he even went so far as to offer to return with his jailers, if he were entreated to do so by the Committee.  Though offering the Committee more in law than he had to, he was baiting them. They refused to urge him back to prison; but had they done so, Overton could have claimed that he was thereby subject to their jurisdiction. Nevertheless, Overton reveals that he was prepared to defy the Committee, even had it requested his voluntary return to Newgate:

For do you think that 1 am such a fool to part with my liberty, for nothing. Sir, our liberties have been bought at a dearer rate, then to be trifled and slighted away. . . .

  But now Sir, I would not have you think from these demands of mine, that I would be subject to an arbitrary power more in you then in the other, for truly in those demands there was tacitly couched a supposition of that which I knew could not be granted. . . .but and if I had been imprisoned thereon, after I had given their Lordships that Sob, you should have heard from me with a witness; for I cannot suffer oppression and be silent.[49]

  At any rate, Overton’s jailers dragged him away from the Committee and carried him by boat toward Newgate.  When he was landed, they pleaded with him to walk up a long hill under his own power.

I was not minded to be their DRUDGE, or to make use of my feet to carry the rest of my body to the Gaol, therefore I let them hang as if they had been none of my own, or like a couple of farthin Candles dangling at my knees, and after they had dragged me in that admireable posture a while, the one took me very reverently by the head, and the other as reverently by the feet, as if he had intended to have done Homage to his Holiness’ great Toe, and so they carried me: but truly Sir, I laughed at the conceit in my sleeve. [Eventually they wearied and soon carried me] just as if I had been a dead Dog, they dragged and trailed my body upon the stones, and without all reverence to my cloth, drew me through the dirt and mire.[50]

Upon his arrival at Newgate prison, they placed him in the lower room, or the Lodge as it was called.  Somehow Overton still managed to have a copy of Sir Edward Coke’s Institutes on the Magna Charta in his possession. Mr. Briscoe, the jailer, spying the book, demanded to have it, which Overton promptly refused.  Overton was mobbed and eventually the book was wrestled from him.  “And thus by an assault they got the great Charter of Englands Liberties and Freedoms,” and thus being “stripped of my armour of proof, the Charter of my legal Rights, Freedoms, and Liberties, after the aforesaid barbarous manner, they hurried me up into the common Gaol.”[51]  There, although he was placed in a pair of leg irons, he purposefully refused to either answer the call of the warden, or commission anyone to knock off the leg irons.  Finally the warden had Overton carried to his office, where Overton preached to the warden.  Overton told the warden that he

scorned to crouch or debase his Spirits to the lawless cruelty of any merciless tyrants or Gaolers whatsoever: they may devour my Carcass, and make that bend and break with their cruelty, but I trust in God, that in heart and action to the utmost of my power in the pursuance of justice and truth, 1 shall bid defiance to the last gasp of breath to all their oppressions and tyrannies whatsoever.”[52]

  During the course of his imprisonment, around January 6, 1647, Overton’s wife and his brother had been arrested and committed to Maiden Lane prison by order of the House of Lords.  The following day another raid was perpetrated on his dwelling, when agents of the Lords were searching for Overton’s sister and her husband.  Fortunately, the two escaped along with Overton’s three children.  Rightfully he laments, “so, Father, Mother, Children, and All, being driven out of House and home, the Doors were shut up; and I, and mine, exposed to the utter ruin and confusion of those insulting, domineering, merciless, Usurpers and Tyrants, The House of Lords.”[53]  Overton then relates how his wife was commanded by the City Marshall to be moved from Maiden Lane prison to Bridewell, “that common Center and receptacle of bauds, whores, and strumpets, more fit for their wanton retrograde Ladies, than for one, who never yet could be taxed of immodesty, either in countenance, gesture, words, or action.”[54]

  Overton’s wife refused to budge and told the Marshall that she would not stir except upon order or warrant of the House of Commons.  The Marshall flew into a fit of angry rage and called for a couple of porters to move her.  When they came, Overton relates, the porters told the Marshall “that they would not meddle with a woman that was with child, and had a young sucking infant in her arms, lest in doing so they might do that today which they might answer for tomorrow.” [55]  A cartman similarly refused to haul Mary Overton to Bridewell. Finally the Marshall gathered his sheriffs and deputies and they broke down the door in order to violently lay hands on her.  They “dragged her down the stairs, and in that infamous barbarous manner, drew her headlong upon the stones in all the dirt and the mire of the streets, with the poor Infant still crying and mourning in her Arms, whose life they spared not to hazard by that inhumane barbarous usage.”[56] Overton was concerned not only for her life and the brutal treatment she had received, but thought that her reputation would be ruined forever by being jailed in Bridewell.

  In concluding the Commoners Complaint, Overton stressed that the House of Commons should redress the situation of all those arbitrarily imprisoned by the House of Lords.  If the Lords may rule by prerogative,

then farewell all liberty and property, all Laws; justice, and equity; and if it must be so, I pray you bear us no longer in suspense and expection of redress, hut forthwith let our Doom be proclaimed to the whole world, that the Commons of England may know what to trust to; that we may loose our labor no longer in petitioning, appealing, complaining, and seeking for relief at your hands. . . .for my part I care not though you and all men forsake me, so long as I know the Lord liveth, who will once judge every man according to his deeds, whether good or evil, and then I am sure I shall have righteous judgment. . . .

  I scorn their mercy, and dare them to do their worse: let them find Prisons, Dungeons, Irons, Halters, etc., and I’ll find Carcass, Neck, and Heels, for one in contempt to their usurped jurisdiction; for resolved I am to break before I bend to their oppressions.”

  Sometime in 1647, Mary Overton wrote her own petition to the House of Commons, addressed To the Right Honorable, the Knights, Citizens, and Burgesses, the Parliament of England, Assembled at Westminster, the Humble Appeal and Petition of Mary Overton, Prisoner in Bridewell.  In it she related the story of her own arrest and the tribulations of herself, her husband, and family at the hands of the House of Lords. Her petition is full of legal citations, unlike the writings of her husband.  Overton had apparently been misinformed, for Mary states that Thomas Overton and also her own brother were taken in the raid upon her home.

  Mary Overton’s main plea is that justice be dispensed towards her and towards her husband and the rest of their family.

In case by Law it shall be found that your Petitioners husband, herself and her brother have done ought worthy of death, or other exemplary punishment, that they may forthwith receive their just execution accordingly. But and if your Petitioner, her husband and brother be legally found not guilty of any transgression of the known Laws of the Land, that then by an Order from this House they may forthwith be discharged from under the vassallage and bondage of those insulting and tyrannizing lords; and that for the future you would be pleased to protect them and the rest of their National Brethren the free Commoners of England from the like Prerogative-insolencies, cruelties and oppression: and that in case this House by the Law of the Land shall find your Petitioners husband, her self and her brother wronged and abused, that you would according to justice give them full and ample reparations for their long and unjust imprisonment, like as you have done of late to sundry of your own Members your Petitioners Fellow Commoners; that you will not any longer deny them the benefit of the Law, which is their birthright and inheritance, and let them not be deprived of that which every monthly Sessions you do allow to thieves and murderers, to have a free and speedy trial.[58]

  Meanwhile, Richard Overton was still in Newgate, and on July 8, 1647 he published yet another “prison” pamphlet.  His Commoners Complaint had been directed to the House of Commons and had no appreciable effect. Having obviously lost some confidence in the ability of the House of Commons to secure his release, Overton took the unprecedented step of appealing directly to the English populace and Army.  Realizing that he might he condemned for this bold appeal, Overton again used an argument which he had presented in his Commoners Complaint: “That Reason has no precedent, for Reason is the fountain of all just precedents. . . . therefore where that is, there is a sufficient and justifiable precedent.”

And if this Principle must be granted of, and obeyed by all, as by no rational man can be denied, then. . .[my] Appeal in this nature if grounded upon right Reason is justifiable and warranted, even by That which gives an equitable Authority, life and being to all just Laws, precedents and forms of Government whatsoever, for Reason is their very life and spirit, whereby they are all made lawful and warrantable. . . ; which is the highest kind of Justification and Authority for human Actions that can be; . . .right Reason (the fountain of all justice and mercy to the creature) shall and will endure for ever; it is that by which in all our Actions we must stand or fall, be justified or condemned; for neither Morality nor Divinity among Men can or may transgress the limits of right reason, for whatsoever is unreasonable cannot be justly termed Moral or Divine, and right reason is only commensurable and discernable by the rule of merciful Justice and just mercy.”[59]

  Overton then justifies his own Appeal by referring to “right reason.” First he points out that it is a law of nature and religion that people may use all just and expedient means to free themselves from oppression. His Appeal is such a means and is therefore legitimate. Secondly, “necessity” justified his course of action in the Appeal.  Parliament had taken up arms against the King out of “necessity” and had proclaimed it “no resistance of Magistracy to side with the just principles and law of nature.”[60] Therefore if any from the House of Commons condemned his Appeal, they were implicitly condemning their own rebellion against the King. Lastly, referring to his arguments of self-propriety, which appeared in An Arrow, Overton argues that in appealing to the commoners and soldiers he is tracing “sovereignty” to its actual source:

All authority is fundamentally seated in the office, and but ministerially in the persons; therefore, the persons in their Ministrations degenerating from safety to tyranny, their Authority cease and is only to be found in the fundamental original, rise and situation thereof, which is the people, the body represented; for though it ceaseth from the hands of the betrusted, yet it does not, neither can it cease from its being, for Kings, Parliaments, and etc. may fall from it, but it endure forever, for were this not admitted, there could be no lawful redress in extremity. . . : it always is either in the hands of the Betrusted of the Betrusters, while the Betrusted are dischargers of their trust, it remains in their hands, but no sooner the Betrusted betray and forfeit their Trust, but (as all things else in dissolution) it returns from where it came, even to the hands of the Trusters: for all just human powers are betrusted, conferred, and conveyed by joint and common consent, for to every individual in nature, is given an individual propriety by nature, not to be invaded or usurped by any, (as in my Arrow Against Tyranny is proved and discovered more at large) for every one as he is himself has a self propriety, else could not be himself, and on this no second may presume without consent; and by natural birth, all men are equal and alike born to like propriety and freedom, every man by natural instinct aims at his own safety and weal.[61]

   After discussing the imprisonment of his family and his own encounter with the House of Lords, Overton analyzes the war against the King. Most important to his argument is the demonstration that Parliament has shown that “resistance to tyranny” is an admissible principle of action, even though tyrants be clothed in “magisterial” robes.

Therefore it is in vain for our Members in Parliament to think that we will justify or tolerate the same [tyranny] among them, which we will not endure in the King, to pluck off the Garments of Royalty from oppression and tyranny, and to dress up the same in Parliament Robes: No, no, that was ever and is far from our hearts, and we shall justify or allow the same no more in the one than in the other, for to allow it in the one is to justify it in the other, for it is equally unequal in both, and in it self resistable wheresoever it is found, for were it not resistable, all defensive war whatsoever were unlawful. . . . [W]e are bound to the utmost of our power to arm and fortify ourselves for our just and necessary defense, and by force of Arms to repel and beat back the invading assaulting enemy, whether it be an enemy for the confusion and extirpation of our persons, or for destruction and ruin of our Laws, our freedoms and liberties, for bondage and slavery are not inferior to death, but rather to be more avoided, condemned, and resisted than present destruction, by how much the more that kind of destruction is more languishing than present, and in pursuance of the just and necessary defensive Opposition we may lawfully, and are in Conscience bound to destroy, kill, and slay the otherwise irresistible enemy for our own preservation and safety whether in our lives, our Laws or our liberties: And against the justice of this defensive principle no degrees, Orders or titles among men can or may prevail, all degrees, Orders and titles, all Laws, Customs and manners among men must be subject to give place and yield thereunto, and it unto none.[62]

Thus he concludes that those resorting to a “defensive resistance” do not become traitors and rebels against true government.

For tyranny is no Magistracy, therefore the resistance of Tyrants is no resistance of Magistrates, except it be of such so nominally; but really and essentially monsters and pests of humanity; . . .for Magistracy has its proper compass and confines, and the actors and actions in that compass are thereby rendered Magisterial actors and actions to be obeyed by all, and resisted by none; and so such as are resisters thereof, are no Resisters of Magistracy, Authority and Government; but the resistance of the excursions or actions out of that compass and capacity, is no resistance of Magistracy or Magistrates, for it is not their persons which makes their Ministrations Magisterial, but their Ministerial Magistrations which makes their persons Magisterial persons: for Magistracy is not inherent or consistent in the person, but in the office; their persons must run a parallel line in their Ministration with their office, or else their formal deputation or Commissions will not entitle them to the true definition of Magistrates; for the office is but accidentally consistent in the form or external Commission, radically and essentially in the due Ministration.[63]

  Countering the claims of religious pacifists, Overton recognizes that all people are entitled to maintain their natural human “being” and subsistence upon earth by resorting to self-defense, if necessary.  Pacifism he argues would result in the utter confusion of humanity and the depopulation of nations.  Nevertheless, he agrees that religious doctrine must not be promulgated by the sword, although he sees no contradiction in a religious person embracing the principle of self-defense when coercively attacked: “And if the Magistrate should so far extend his compulsive force under pretense of religion and conscience, to the destruction of our human subsistence or being, we may upon the points of your human subsistence and being, lawfully make our defensive resistance, for in itself it is defendable against all opposition or destruction from whence or from whomsoever it shall be.”[64]  Overton concludes his Appeal by urging all the commoners and soldiers to embrace his cause. If they will not, he writes, then “I have reckoned my cost, and can in this cause for my Country upon honest and just privileges, lay down my life, as freely and willingly, as my most malicious enemies can make it a sacrifice to their fury: Do therefore, as it seems good in your own eyes; I have discharged my conscience, and what I have done, I have done; and commit the issue thereof unto God.”[65]

  Overton was finally released from prison in September or November 1647, after another inquiry by the House of Commons. Although Leveller agitation continued throughout 1648, we do not find Overton back in print until March 1649 with a pamphlet entitled The Hunting of the Foxes, which set forth Leveller grievances against the Army.[66]  In the meantime, the second phase of the Civil War had commenced and the Scottish Army had been defeated by Cromwell.  King Charles I had been seized by the Parliamentary Army in December 1648 and executed on January 30, 1649.  Although the King’s trial and execution were the result of “a fanatical minority of Independents,” “ideologically the trial of Charles and the abolition of kingship were the product of Leveller propaganda.”[67] The second Agreement of the People been published by the Levellers in December 1648, and by mid-1649, they were becoming increasingly disenchanted with Cromwell and the Independents. The Army was moving towards a dictatorship; censorship and military law had already been imposed, and Cromwell had refused to adopt the second Agreement of the People.[68]

  It was no wonder, then, that in 1649 Lilburne and other Levellers had composed a new address to Parliament, titled The Second Part of Englands New Chains Discovered (March 24, 1649).  It was a direct and bitter attack on the Army and the Independents, “provocative of mutiny and disorder.”  One historian has described what ensued as follows:

The Independents had no choice but to resolve the dispute by suppression. On March 24 the Rump declared the pamphlet contained “much false, scandalous, and reproachful Matter.” Further, it was “highly seditious. . .destructive to the present Government. . .tended to Divison and Mutiny in the Army.”  The authors they declared “guilty of High Treason, and should be proceeded against as Traitors.”

  Accordingly, on March 28, between four and six in the morning, troops of horse and foot surrounded the homes of Lilburne, Walwyn, Prince, and Overton, roused them roughly from their beds, carried them off to Whitehall, there to await questioning by the Council of State.  The story of their arrest and subsequent examination is told vividly by Lilburne, Prince, and Overton, in The Picture of the Council of State, published only six days later.  The dramatic situation was ideal for propagandistic effect, and the Levellers promptly identified the principle of political justice with their own sufferings at the hands of the Grandees.  Each of the four men refused to answer interrogatories that would have incriminated himself . . . , Lilburne and Overton . . . denying the legality of both the Rump and the Council of State. Lilburne was permitted to make a long speech pointing out that it was not in the power of Parliament to execute the laws, denying the power of the Council to imprison him in a military prison, and threatening to burn the very military prison they should consign him to.  Looking fixedly at Cromwell, Lilburne said, “I must be plain with you, I have not found so much Honor, Honesty, Justice, or Conscience, in any of the principal Officers of the Army, as to trust my life under their protection, or think it can be safe under their immediate fingers.” After Overton, Prince, and Walwyn had been questioned, Lilburne put his ear to the door of the chamber: “I . . . heard Lieutenant General Cromwell (I am sure of it) very loud, thumping his fist up the Council Table, till it rang again, and heard him speak in these very words, or to this effect; I tell you Sir, you have no other Way to deal with these men, but to break them in pieces;and thumping upon the Council Table again, he said Sir, let me tell you; yea, and bring all the guilt of blood and treasure shed and spent in this Kingdom upon your heads and shoulders; and frustrate and make void all that work, that with so many years industry, toil and pains you have done, and so render you to all rational men in the world, as the most contemptible generation of silly, low spirited men in the earth.” [69]

Such was the strength of the Leveller movement, that Cromwell had to resort to outright repression in order to maintain his position.

  In his narrative in The Council of State, Overton describes the rough and abusive treatment that he and his friends received during the raid upon his living quarters.  Always ready to assert his legal rights, he demanded to see the warrant for his arrest and to see the search warrant authorizing invasion of his quarters. When he was finally brought before the Council of State, he again demanded the production of their authority to detain him for questioning. He unequivocally refused to answer their questions:

Gentlemen, it is well known, and that unto your selves, that in cases criminal, as now you pretend against me, it is against the fundamental Laws of this Commonwealth to proceed against any man by way of Interrogatories against himself, as you do against me. . . .So that for my part, Gentlemen, I do utterly refuse to make answer unto any thing in relation to my own person, or any man or men under heaven; but do humbly desire, that if you intend by way of Charge to proceed to any Trial of me, that it may be (as before I desired at your hands) by the known established Laws of England, in some ordinary Court of Justice appointed for such cases (extraordinary ways never being used, but abominated, where ordinary ways may be had) and I shall freely submit to what can be legally made good against me.[70]

  Besides claiming a privilege against self-incrimination, Overton also pointed out that he was innocent until proven guilty and that ex post facto laws could have no bearing on his particular case.

I am guilty of nothing, not of this paper, entitled The Second Part of Englands New Chains, in case I had never so much an hand in it, till it be legally proved: for the Law looks upon no man to be guilty of any crime, till by law he be convicted; so that I cannot esteem myself guilty of any thlng, till by the Law you have made the same good against me.

  And further Sir, I desire you to take notice, that I cannot be guilty of the transgression of any Law, before that Law be in being; it is impossible to offend that which is not: Where there is no Law there is no Transgression: Now, those Votes on which you proceed against me are but of yesterdays being; so that, had I an hand in that Book whereof you accuse me, provided it were before those Votes, you cannot render me guilty by those Votes.[71]

  Even though he was facing the possibility of a second imprisonment, Overton was as defiant and belligerent as ever, declaring that he could never coexist with oppression:

It is well known, and I think to some here [before the Council of State], that I have ever been an opposer of oppression and tyranny. . . . I suppose no man can accuse me, but that I have opposed Tyranny where-ever I have found it: It is all one to me under what name, or title soever oppression be exercised, whether under the name of King, Parliament, Council of State, under the name of this, or that, or any thing else; For tyranny and oppression is tyranny and oppression to me where-ever I find it, and where-ever I find it I shall oppose it, without respect of persons.

  I know I am mortal and finite, and by the course of nature my days must have a period, how soon I know not; and the most you can do, it is but to proceed to life; and for my part, I had rather die in the just vindication of the poor oppressed people of this Commonwealth, then to die in my bed; and the sooner it is, the welcomer, I care not if it were at this instant, for I value not what you can do unto me.[72]

Despite their eloquent pleas for freedom, the Leveller leaders were kept in prison.

  It was probably next to impossible to stifle the outbursts of such men as Lilburne and Overton, and from prison they soon published another declaration, A Manifestation, (April 14, 1649), which, although apparently written in the main by Walwyn, reflected the ideas of all four prisoners.  The Levellers were concerned to demonstrate that they were not to he associated with the communal land diggers and that they did not preach chaotic anarchy, although they were firmly opposed to the military government of Cromwell. Walwyn therefore attempted to defend the Levellers’ course of action during the Civil War.  The Levellers had engaged in political activity out of self-defense, but they were concerned to show that their own politics would not end up in an oppressive government, were they to succeed.  This of course is a danger inherent in all radical political parties: that they can end up replacing one set of oppressions with another.

And whereas it is urged, That if we were in power, we would bear ourselves as Tyrannically as others have done: We confess indeed, that the experimental defections of so many men as have succeeded in Authority, and the exceeding difference we have hitherto found in the same men in a low, and in an exalted condition, makes us even mistrust our own hearts, and hardly believe our own Resolutions of the contrary.  And therefore we have proposed such an Establishment, as supposing men to be too flexible and yielding to worldly Temptations, they should not yet have a means or opportunity either to injure particulars, or prejudice the Public, without extreme hazard, and apparent danger to themselves.  Besides, to the objection we have further to say, That we aim not at power in our selves, our Principles and Desires being in no measure of self-concernment: nor do we rely for obtaining the same upon strength, or a forcible obstruction; but solely upon that inbred and persuasive power that is all good and just things, to make their own way in the hearts of men, and so to procure their own Establishments.”[73]

  A Manifestation ends on a conciliatory note by referring to the revision of the Agreement of the People, which the Leveller leaders were preparing. The Agreement would allow the world to see what the Leveller movement was about, and if accepted would lead to peace.

And thus the world may clearly see what we are, and what we aim at: We are altogether ignorant, and do from our hearts abominate all designs and contrivances of dangerous consequence which we are said (but God knows, untruly) to be laboring withall.  Peace and Freedom is our Design; by War we were never gainers, nor ever wish to be; and under bondage we have been hitherto sufferers. We desire, however, that what is past may be forgotten, provided the Commonwealth may have amends made it for the time to come. And this from our soul we desire.”[74]

  On May 1, 1649, Lilburne, Walwyn, Prince, and Overton, still prisoners in the Tower of London, published their revision of An Agreement of the Free People of England.  Tendered as a Peace Offering to This Distressed Nation.  The Agreement was composed of thirty articles and incorporated all the Leveller demands as taken from their most important petition.[75]  In the Agreement they display a profound distrust of authoritarian power but do place a great amount of confidence in the judgment of the voting public. In the Agreement are such libertarian planks as: 

XI. We do not empower them [the representatives in Parliament] to impress or constrain any person to serve in war by Sea or Land every mans Conscience being to he satisfied in the justness of that cause wherein he hazards his own life, or may destroy an others.

XVI. We agree and Declare That it shall not be in the power of any representative to punish or cause to be punished, any person or persons for refusing to answer questions against themselves in Criminal cases.

XVIII. That it shall not be in their power to continue or make any Laws to abridge or to hinder any person or persons from trading or merchandizing in to any place beyond the Seas, where any of this Nation are free to Trade.

XIX. That it shall not be in their power to continue Excise or Customs upon any sort of Food or any other Goods, Wares, or Commodities. . . .

XX. That it shall not be in their power to make or continue any Law, whereby men’s real or personal estates, or any part thereof, shall be exempted from payment of their debts; or to imprison any person for debt of any nature, it being both unchristian in itself, and no advantage to the Creditors, and both a reproach and a prejudice to the Commonwealth.

XXI. That it shall not be in their power to make or continue any Law, for taking away any mans life, except for murder, or other like heineous offenses destructive to human Society, or for endeavoring by force to destroy this Agreement, but shall use their uttermost endeavors to appoint punishments equal to offenses: that so men’s Lives, Limbs, Liberties, and estates, may not be liable to be taken away upon trivial or slight occasions as they have been; . . . and in all other capital offenses recompense shall be made to the parties damnified, as well out of the estate of the Malefactor, as by loss of life, according to the conscience of his jury.[76]

  Overton was kept in the Tower until November 1649, and during that time he published two pamphlets in support of the Agreement of the People.  The first was titled Overton’s Defiance of the Act of Pardon (July 2, 1649) and the second was The Baiting of the Bull of Bashan (July 9, 1649).  In the first Overton makes it clear that the Agreement is the summation and goal of his political activities.  In his estimation, no sacrifice would be too great, so long as it was adopted:

My Friends, of this therefore be you confident, that my silence has not proceeded from any degeneration or instability in me to that Righteous Cause (summed up in our draft of an Agreement of the people, subscribed, published, and offered by us four as a peace offering, to the consideration of the people of England, May 1, 1649) that Paper (or rather the contents or premises thereof) is the price, glory, and end of my endurance, neither life, liberty or reparation or any thing that man or earth affords is valuable with me in comparison thereof, that is my all in all; I desire neither life, liberty or reparation (seeing God has called me to the work) but as it may stand in subordination to that Agreement; while I have life or breath it shall never want a truer asserter to uphold and promote the same to the utmost of my power, let the hazard and danger to myself be what it will . . . . for that Agreement, I will have, or else I’ll die at their feet; I’ll have no accord or peace with them at all till they have yielded that: whether at liberty or in prison, it is all one to me.”[77]

It was Overton’s belief that without the Agreement there would be no security for either person or property in the Commonwealth.  He makes it plain that he does not trust Cromwell and the army grandees. (“I’ll trust them no further than I can fling their great Bull of Bashan by the tail.”)[78] He exhorts those Levellers still at liberty to promote the Agreement and not to expect that their four imprisoned leaders can “remove mountains”; at least not without their help.

  Apparently the Leveller prisoners had been offered a pardon, on terms which Overton found quite unacceptable.  In the Defiance of the Act of Pardon Overton also laments the defection of former comrades from the ranks of the Levellers into the arms of Cromwell’s faction.  Referring to himself as “little brisk Levelling Dick in the Tower,” Overton makes it clear to both his followers and opponents that he will not dishonor himself or the cause by renouncing the Agreement or changing factions:

Therefore know all men by these presents, that I, Richard Overton . . .out of a tender regard that I have to the Liberties of my Country, and credit of that honorable cause, do hereby defy, renounce, abhor, detest and scorn that Act of Pardon as to my Liberty thereby, and do rather choose continuance and increase of Bonds, than conditional submission or assent thereunto in the least: . . . I am so far from submission to their corrupt and wicked interest, that I will first eat the flesh off from my bones; first rot and perish in Gaol, before I will so far how to them, as in the least to woo them or any of their creatures, either directly or indirectly in person or by proxy for my liberty: my cause is not bad, but with patience I can suffer till I be justly delivered without blemish or speck of infamy to the same; the honor of it, I honor above my life or liberty.

  In the Defiance, Overton had used some rather strong and vulgar language, and in The Baiting of the Bull he continues on with its use, incorporating it into some pointed and satirical metaphors. Although the Agreement was not meeting with much popular acceptance, Overton believed that undue gravity and melancholy in the Levellers’ cause was wrong.  It was his opinion that “modest mirth tempered with due gravity makes the best composition.”[79] And he later adds, that “one pennyworth of the Agreement of the People, with a little good resolution taken morning and evening, will work out this corruption, cleanse, and purify the blood.”[80] His earlier pamphlet, he says, seemed but “as music to the house of Mourning” and did not seem to rouse the Levellers to action. He points out a common characteristic of political movements, that “When there is anything of venture or hazard, while tis in the Embryo, who is not then but busy and forward [promoting it]? but when tis put upon the personal test for execution, Oh then one has bought a piece of ground, and must be excused; another a yoke of Oxen, and he must go see them; and a third has married a wife.”[81]  Yet he believes that if the ordinary Leveller saw a person threatened with danger, be would not hesitate to venture his own life in order to save the other.  Why then are the Levellers unwilling to aid their own political cause?  As Overton points out, there is much more at risk in the triumph of their cause than in the rescue of a single person:

Our cause is of a more transcendent value, and we suffer for it; and can you see it destroyed in us, and we for it, and not be as natural as in a private relation? the lives, liberties and freedoms of all is contained in it?  If your neighbors Ox or his Ass were in a ditch, it is a shame to pass by and not to help; and behold, here’s all in the ditch, then, why venture you not your time, your labors, your moneys, etc. to redeem our all, our Cause, the nation, and us in it, and with it.”[82]

  Overton was eventually released from the Tower in November 1649, when Lilburne was placed on trial.  Although acquitted, Lilburne and the Leveller movement had reached their zenith and were literally spent.  Little record is left of the activities of Overton after he was freed. There is record of his involvement in spying and fomenting rebellion against the Protectorate, and in 1659 he was again in prison. In 1663, he was ordered arrested for printing material contrary to the government of Charles II.[83]

  Overton’s pamphlets certainly offer a unique autobiographical assessment and perspective of the Leveller movement.  Richard Overton, in both word and deed, was a fearless man, true to his ideals of justice, without regard for personal consequence.  The words of another Leveller, contemporary to him, perhaps best epitomize Overton’s spirit:

Had they [the Levellers] counted the cost, the difficulty when they had taken up arms against the king? They were bound, . . . not by difficulties but by justice.  Though death lay ahead, and the sea on three sides, they should unflinchingly carry on.  Whatever great leap the Agreement called for, [they] should have no fear: “When I leap I shall take so much of God with me, and so much of just and right, as I shall jump sure.”[84]

NOTES

1. H. N. Brailsford, The Levellers and the English Revolution (London: Cresset Press, 1961). p. 418. There is a wide disparity in secondary, historical interpretations of the Leveller movement. Probably the two most individualistic interpretations of the Levellers are this book by Brailsford and one by C. B. Macpherson, Political Theory of Possessive Individualism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1962).

2. Howard Shaw, The Levellers (London: Longmans Green and Co., 1968). p. 102. See also Brailsford, The Levellers and the English Revolution, pp. 549-550.

3. Brailsford, The Levellers and the English Revolution, pp. 379-380.

4. Ibid., p. 550.

5. D. B. Robertson, The Religious Foundations of Leveller Democracy (New York: Kings Crown Press, 1951). p. 74.

6. Richard Overton, A Manifestation, in Don M. Wolfe, ed., Leveller Manifestoes of the Puritan Revolution (New York: Thomas Nelson and Sons, 1944), p. 391. This is one of several collections of Leveller documents which are indispensable to the study of the general movement. Others include: William Haller and Godfrey Davies, eds., The Leveller Tracts, 1647-1653 (New York: Columbia University Press, 1944); William Haller, ed.,Tracts on Liberty in the Puritan Revolution, 1638-1647, 3 vols. (New York: Columbia University Press, 1934); and A. S. P. Woodhouse, ed.,Puritanism and Liberty Being the Army Debates, 1647-9, Clarke Manuscripts (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1951).

7. Robertson, Religious Foundations, p. 73.

8. Perez Zagorin, A History of Political Thought in The English Revolution (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, l954), p. 41.

9. See Robertson, Religious Foundations, pp. 76-81.

10. Ibid., p. 77.

11. Brailsford, The Levellers and the English Revolution, pp. 457-58.

12. Ibid., pp. 498-506.

13. Ibid., p. 384.

14. Ibid., p. 264.

15. Woodhouse, “Introduction,” Puritanism and Liberty, p. 28.

16. Ibid., “lntroduction,” p. 91.

17. Ibid., “Putney Debates,” p.75.

18. Ibid., “Introduction,” p. 91.

19. Brailsford, The Levellers and the English Revolution, p. 315.

20. Macpherson, Political Theory, p. 152.

21. Brian Manning, The English People and the English Revolution, 1640-1649 (London: Hennemann Publishers, 1976). p. 296.

22. Ibid., p. 295.

23. Quoted in Robertson, The Religious Foundations, p. 87.

24. Overton, A Manifestation, pp. 390-91.

25. Macpherson, Politica1 Theory, p. 138.

26. See Macpherson’s discussion in ibid., pp. 137-57.

27. Overton, An Arrow Against All Tyrants (1646). pp. 3-4. Copy from the Huntington Library collection. I would like to thank Carey Bliss, Curator of Rare Books and Manuscripts at the Henry E. Huntington Library, San Marino, Calif., who was most helpful in supplying copies of documents in the collection.  I also obtained a copy of An Arrow from Duke University, Durham, N.C.  It has also been reprinted by the Rota Press of the University of Exeter, England (ISBN 0-90461745X).

The same quotation also appears in Macpherson, Political Theory, pp. 140-41.

28. Overton, An Appeal from the Degenerate Representative Body, in Wolfe, Leveller Manifestoes, pp. 162-63.  The same quotation appears in Macpherson, Politica1 Theory, p. 141.

29. Haller, Tracts on Liberty, 1:114.

30. Macpherson, Political Theory, p. 142.

31. Overton, A Remonstrance of Many Thousand Citizens, in Wolfe, Leveller Manifestoes, pp. 113-30.

32. Ibid., p. 113.

33. Ibid., pp. 114-15.

34. Ibid., p. 122.

35. Ibid., p. 124.

36. Ibid., p. 125.

37. Ibid., pp. 126-27.

38. Overton, An Alarum to the House of Lords (1646), p. 6. Copy from the Huntington Library collection.

39. Ibid., pp. 6-7.

40. Overton, A Dance Against All Arbitrary Usurpations (l646). p. 6. From the Huntington Library collection.  The title of this essay . . .”Come What, Come Will,” is taken from A Defiance, p. 13.

41. See Leonard Levy, The Origins of the Fifth Amendment (New York: Oxford University Press, 1968), pp. 293-300.

42. Overton, An Arrow, p. 9.

43. Overton, Commoners Complaint (1647), p. 3.  Copy from the Huntington Library collection.

44. Ibid., pp. 4-5.

45. Ibid., p. 6.

46. Ibid.

47. Ibid., pp. 9-10.

48. Ibid., p. 10.

49. Ibid., pp. 12-13.

50. Ibid., p. 13.

51. Ibid., p. 14.

52. Ibid., pp. 15-16.

53. Ibid., p. 16.

54. Ibid., p. 17.

55. Ibid., p. 18.

56. Ibid., p. 19.

57. Ibid., pp. 22-23.

58. Mary Overton, The Humble Appeal and Petition of Mary Overton (1647), p. 12. Copy from Temple University, Philadelphia.

59. Richard Overton. An Appeal, p. 158.

60. Ibid., p. 161

61. Ibid., p. 162.

62. Ibid., pp. 176-78

63. Ibid., p. 180.

64. Ibid., p. 182.

65. Ibid., p. 188.

66. Overton, The Hunting of the Foxes, in Wolfe, Leveller Manifestoes, pp. 355-83

67. Ibid., p. 94.

68. Ibid., pp. 99-100.

69. Ibid., pp. 100-101.

70. Overton, A Picture of the Council of State, in Haller and Davies, The Leveller Tracts, p. 223.

71. Ibid., p. 224.

72. Ibid., pp. 224-25.

73. Overton, A Manifestation, p. 394.

74. Ibid., p. 396.

75. Wolfe, Leveller Manifestoes, p. 397.

76. Lilburne, Walwyn, Prince and Overton, An Agreement of the Free People of England, in ibid., pp. 405-407.

77. Overton, Overton’s Defiance of the Act of Pardon (1949), pp. 4-5.  Copy from the Huntington Library Collection.

78. Ibid., p. 7.

79. Overton, The Baiting of the Great Bull of Bashan (1649). p. 3.  Copy from the Huntington Library collection.

80. Ibid., pp. 2-3.

81. Ibid., p. 4.

82. Ibid., p. 6.

83. C. H. Firth, Dictionary of National Biography (London: Oxford University Press. 1967-68), 14:1281.  Firth’s “Richard Overton” entry, from which this reference is made, lists Overton’s writings and gives a picture of his tumultuous life.

84. Wolfe. Leveller Manifestoes, p. 54.

  A more recent collection of Leveller documents, which re-sparked my interest in the Leveller movement is G. L. Aylmer, ed.. The Levellers in the English Revolution (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1975). Further interpretation of the movement can be found in Henry Holorenshaw, The Levellers and the English Revolution (London: Victor Gollancz, 1939).  Two (less helpful) articles which have come to my attention are: Iain Hampsher-Monk, “The Political Theory of the Levellers,” Political Studies 24, no. 4 (1976): 397-422; and J. C. Davis, “The Levellers and Christianity,” in Brian Manning, ed., Politics, Religion, and the English Civil War (New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1973), pp. 225-50.

  While it does not appear that any biography has been written detailing the life of Richard Overton, there are several studies of the life and thought of John Lilburne, Leveller leader.  Two biographies that I referred to are: M. A. Gibb, John Lilburne (London: Lindsay Drummond, 1947); and Pauline Gregg, Free-born John (London: Harrap Publishers. 1961).

  The reader is referred to the National Union Catalog, Pre-1956 Imprints, vol. 435, in which the listings under Mary and Richard Overton provide the names and locations of their material in the U. S

The English Individualists as They Appear in Liberty*


by Carl Watner

1982

The leading English individualists as they appear in Benjamin Tucker’s journal, Liberty, are Auberon Herbert, Wordsworth Donisthorpe, Joseph Hiam Levy, Joseph Greevz Fisher, John Badcock, Jr., Albert Tarn, and Henry Seymour. Ranked approximately according to their contributions and involvement in Liberty, this group also includes M. D. O’Brien, J. M. Armsden, W. C. Crofts, A. E. Porter and J. C. Spence.[1]Their activities and writings serve as the focal point for research into the history of late-nineteenth and early-twentieth century individualist anarchism in England.Liberty, an international clearinghouse for libertarian ideas during the almost three decades of its existence (1881-1908), reported on and editorialized about the ideology and politics of the English individualist movement.The purpose of this paper is to bring to light some of the little known history and ideas of the movement, based on articles in Liberty and other sources.

The English individualist anarchist movement was no more or less unified than its ideological counterpart in the United States.Auberon Herbert (1838-1906), a one-time member of Parliament, called his philosophy “voluntaryism” and was the world’s leading advocate of voluntary taxation.For over a decade, he edited and published an individualist journal, called Free Life.One of his supporters, M. D. O’Brien, went to jail for refusing to send his children to school.[2] Wordsworth Donisthorpe (1847-?) was a near-anarchist barrister and small-time coal mine owner, who, with his cousin, W. C. Crofts (1846-1894), formed the State Resistance Union in 1880.He edited a journal called Jus, and his organization was the forerunner of The Liberty and Property Defence League.Joseph Hiam Levy (1838-1913) was a teacher of economics at Birkbeck College and became involved with the Personal Rights Association in 1878. He eventually became secretary of this organization and edited its journals for many years.Levy was the leading individualist advocate of limited government with compulsory rights of taxation. He was also involved in the anti-vivisection movement.J. Greevz Fisher, John Badcock, Henry Seymour, and J. H. Levy were all involved in the Legitimation League formed in London around 1892 for the purpose of changing the bastardy laws so that offspring born out of wedlock were not deprived of their rightful inheritances.Fisher formed the Parents’ Defence League, whose apparent purpose was to passively resist compulsory schooling of children.[3]Although little else is known about Fisher, he was a clear economic thinker, as his contributions to Liberty demonstrate. He presented one of the two known refutations of money-crankism during the nineteenth century.[4]John Badcock, Jr. (1861?-1926) was an egoist and follower of the doctrines of Max Stirner.He was an accountant by profession and later became a dealer in Chinese art.[5]Albert Tarn was one of Tucker’s agents for Liberty in England.He published the Herald of Anarchy and Free Trade magazines during the early 1890’s.[6]Henry Seymour, John Armsden, and Badcock were associated in the Free Currency Propaganda movement, which advocated repeal of the Bank Charter Act of 1844, repeal of the legal tender laws, and destroying the Bank of England’s monopoly hold on the money supply.By increasing the supply of money in circulation, the propagandists hoped to lower the rate of interest and diminish the capitalists’ profits.Their ideas on interest, and on the causes of poverty, wealth, and capital were well outlined in contributions appearing in Liberty. Henry Seymour was a free-thinker and friend of Charles Bradlaugh. In the mid-1880’s he published a journal called The Anarchist,and was well acquainted with the London anarchists of all persuasions.

This disparate group of activists and thinkers were truly individualists; no two were wholly alike in their philosophy.What united them was their general adherence to a doctrine of individual freedom in economic enterprise and social relations, which they believed should not be restricted by governmental regulations.Every one of the group mentioned had at least minor differences with Tucker and the editorial doctrines of Liberty.Although some of the English individualists refused to call themselves anarchists, their doctrines were perilously close to anarchism.Benjamin Tucker defined anarchism as the doctrine that the State should be abolished and all the affairs of men be carried out on a voluntary basis.[7]More than likely, Herbert, Donisthorpe, Tarn, Seymour, and Badcock would have accepted this statement as an expression of their own political beliefs. J. H. Levy definitely would not.

In an appendix on “Political Terminology” appearing in his debate with Herbert on Taxation and Anarchism, Levy charted out the differences among the English individualists.Both the communist anarchist and the individualistic anarchist, wrote Levy, are “opposed to the existence of government; and, though they differ as to what should be done when the State had been got rid of, and would probably be at each other’s throat the moment the authority which they both assail was removed, the range of their agreement entitled them equally to the general designation of Anarchists.”[8]True individualism, according to Levy, asserts that “compulsory co-operation is good up to the point at which freedom is maximized,” and that “it is harmful when pushed beyond that point.It affirms that government can promote happiness only by maintaining the widest practicable liberty, which it regards as the political–as distinguished from the ethical–summum bonum; and it judges all political measures by their tendency to promote or impede the attainment of this end.”[9]Referring indirectly to Herbert, Levy claimed that no individualist would ever dub himself an anarchist, “though some Anarchists call themselves Individualists.”[10]

The main bone of contention between Herbert and Levy was illustrated in their exchange of views in Taxation and Anarchism, which appeared as a publication of The Personal Rights Association in 1912, several years after Herbert’s death.This discussion between Levy and Herbert was the out-growth of a speech delivered by Levy in January 1890, entitled “The Outcome of Individualism,” and of his contributions to the Personal Rights Journal of October 1890. Levy attacked “the whole scheme of so-called ‘Voluntary Taxation”‘ because it seems to show a “deficiency of analytic power.”

Its projectors appear to think that they can substitute for the State an organization supported by voluntary contributions. . . . Taxation must be, potentially at least, co-extensive with government.The way to reduce it is severely to limit the functions of government to the maximizing of liberty, to abolish privilege, and to exercise due vigilance over the expenditure of State revenue.Such vigilance is becoming every day farther removed from possibility by the growth in complexity of the functions assigned to the State. This is the evil which must be attacked.”[11]

Herbert opened his attack on Levy by rebutting Levy’s challenge that “voluntary taxation” was a contradiction in terms.He claimed that Levy’s use of the concept “compulsory co-operation” was an even “greater” contradiction. Summarizing his position, Herbert argued as follows:

What I contend for is that no force-system should over-ride the consent of a man who has not aggressed against the person or property of his neighbour. I say that a man’s consent as regards his own actions is the most sacred thing in the world, and the one foundation on which all human relations must be built.To me it seems idle to talk of Individualism where this consent is not held sacred. . . [T]he moment I am told that the individual may be caught by the collar and compelled to form a society, may he compelled to share in making laws, may be compelled to maintain these laws, I feel that I am no longer standing on Individualistic ground. . . . Believing, then, that the judgment of every individual who has not himself aggressed against his neighbour is supreme as regards his own actions, and that this is the rock on which Individualism rests–I deny that A and B can go to C and force him to form a State and extract from him certain payments and services in the name of such State. . . . The only difference between the tax-compelling Individualist and the State-Socialist is that whilst they both have vested the ownership of C in A and B, the tax-compelling Individualist proposes to use the powers of ownership in a very limited fashion, the Socialist in a very complete fashion.I object to the ownership in any fashion.[12]

Responding to Herbert’s arguments, Levy maintained that Herbert was mounting “an Anarchistic attack on Individualism.” “It is a direct confirmation of my statement that voluntary taxationists have fallen into Anarchism without knowing it.”[13]Victor Yarros, in his editorial capacity with Liberty, confirmed Levy’s judgment in this matter by arguing: “Voluntaryism is simply Mr. Herbert’s preferred synonym for Individualistic Anarchism.”[14]

The discussion between Levy and Herbert largely revolved around the way in which each formulated his view of individualism.Herbert held that compulsory taxation was opposed to the principles of individualism, to such an extent that the two could never be reconciled in any satisfactory way.Herbert was quite prepared to offer a philosophic basis for individualism from the anti-taxationist point of view:

(1). The great natural fact of each person being born in possession of a separate mind and separate body implies the ownership of such mind and body by each person, and rights of direction over such mind and body; it will be found on examination that no other deduction is reasonable.

(2). Such self-ownership implies the restraint of violent or fraudulent aggressions made upon it.

(3). Individuals, therefore, have the right to protect themselves by force against such aggressions made forcibly or fraudulently, and they may delegate such acts of self-defence to a special body, called a government. . .

Condensed into a few words, our Voluntaryist formula would run: “The sovereignty of the individual must retain intact, except where the individual coerced has aggressed upon the sovereignty of another unaggressive individual.”[l5]

Interestingly enough, Levy flatly rejected this formulation of individualism. Levy asserted: “It seems to me that Mr. Herbert has wandered into the cloud land of meta-politics. . . . I certainly shall not accept such a ‘philosophical basis for Individualism,’ because ‘no other deduction’ of the same sort ‘is reasonable.’There is no deduction at all, but a gross and palpable petitio principii. “[16]In short, Levy concluded that “Mr. Herbert’s formula is that of Anarchism.”[17]

Herbert rejected Levy’s claim that he was an anarchist.According to his own understanding, anarchists would not retain any form of organization to repress aggression or crime.They would not maintain any sort of defense agencies to function as police or courts.The difference between him and Levy was that while he would retain such organization in his ideal society, he would not force those disapproving of the police or courts to pay for them; Mr. Levy, in contrast, would compel the conscientious objectors to pay for them just the same.[18]”We agree that there must be a central agency to deal with crime–an agency that defends the liberty of all men, and employs force against the uses of force; hut my central agency rests upon voluntary support, whilst Mr. Levy’s central agency rests on compulsory support.”[19]The question between Levy and Herbert, as Herbert saw it, was: “Are the principles of Individualism most truly followed when the tax for the support of this [central] agency is taken voluntarily or compulsorily?”[20]

Viewing himself not as an anarchist but as an individualist, Herbert maintained that in an anarchistic society no such central agency for the repression of crimes and aggressions could exist.”My charge against Anarchism is that it sees many forms of crime existing in the world, and it refuses to come to any settled opinion as to what it will do in the matter.If it says it will do nothing, then we must live under the reign of the murderer, tempered by Judge Lynch; if it says it will have some form of local jury, then we are back into government again at once.[21]Herbert acknowledged that there were existing schools of anarchism, “represented in America by Mr. Tucker, and some philosophical Anarchists in England,” but as far as he could see, “none of these schools are prepared to tell us clearly what they will do about ordinary crime.”It was Herbert’s contention that “the moment they begin to deal with crime according to any fixed method and settled precedent, they are at once back into Archism.”[22]The dividing line between statism and anarchism was, according to Herbert: “Do you intend to provide an agency for dealing with crime according to fixed rules and methods, or not? The way in which you pay your agency–though a very important matter in itself, must be looked upon as a non-essential element in the difference between the two systems.”[23]As Herbert saw it, the anarchists espoused no fixed or objective standards by which to repress crime and aggression.”[24]

Levy, for his part, was a perceptive critic.Barring confusion over the labels “individualism” and “anarchism.” Levy realized that taxation was the very essence of government as it had always existed.”A voluntary association for defence could exist without it; but such an association would not be government.”[25] Nor could he accept Herbert’s analysis of the essential distinction between individualism and anarchism as being based on whether or not a central agency of defense was retained in their respective ideal societies. Levy rightly claimed “that there is nothing in Anarchism to prevent those who hold it from retaining any sort of organization for the repression of invasive conduct, so long as that organization is a voluntary one; and in this proviso they do not differ from Mr. Herbert.”[26] Levy maintained that Herbert had not thought out the consequences of his doctrine.What would happen, he asked, if one group of people in a voluntary taxationist society declined to recognize the “definition of rights promulgated by this voluntary association in which they took no part. . . ?”Suppose such a group “endeavored to set up a rival association of their own, . . .what would he do?”[27]

Would he [Herbert] prevent the formation of any such association?If so, does not this mean compulsory submission to the dictates of the association patronized by him?And if he would not interfere with the establishment of rival associations of this kind, with different views from his own association as to rights and methods, this would only defer for a little time the overruling of the weaker party. Where the ideas of such rival organizations clashed there would be conflict. The effective minority would be subdued in one way or another, and for all practical purposes they would be compelled to co-operate with the effective majority or to submit to it.[28]

As we shall see, Levy, the individualist, threw at Herbert the same arguments as those raised by the anarchist critics of his idea of voluntary taxation.

Herbert was wrong in viewing anarchism as not allowing for the existence of competing defense agencies to repress and fight crime.There was, however, an element of truth in his criticism of the individualistic anarchist movement of his day.Tucker, for example, maintained that local juries could render judicial decisions and claimed that anarchists viewed the functions of government as they would any other economic service provided by the market.Competing agencies would provide defense services, such as police protection and court decisions, on a voluntary and competitive basis.Where Herbert was correct in his criticisms of Tucker and other contemporary anarchists was that they failed to specify that all such competing defense agencies would be bound by a rational and objective code of libertarian legal principles and procedures based on the defense of person and property.[29]

Levy was correct in asserting that Herbert had not thought through the problems of voluntary taxation.Although coming from different perspectives, both Levy and Herbert’s anarchist critics, such as Rothbard, ask of Herbert and the proponents of voluntary taxation: “Would they use force to compel people not to use a freely competing defense agency within the same geographic area?”As Rothbard writes: “The voluntary taxationists have never attempted to answer this problem; they have rather stubbornly assumed that no one would set up a competing defense agency within a State’s territorial limits.”[30] Clearly, if the government of a voluntary taxation society chose to outlaw all competing defense agencies, it would not function as the voluntary society sought by its proponents.”It would not force payment of taxes,” but it would monopolize the provision of defense services.”On the other hand, if the government did permit free competition in defense service, there would soon no longer be a central government over the territory.Defense agencies, police and judicial, would compete with one another in the same uncoerced manner as the producers of any other service on the market. . . . Defense service would at last be made fully marketable”[31]

Despite these flaws in his theory, Herbert realized that Levy’s theory of individualism was marred by the existence of compulsory taxation in a society trying to maximize freedom.Herbert understood that compulsion was a contradictory element in such a society and that taxation had to be eliminated.However Herbert erred in not realizing that “freely competing judicial agencies would have to be guided by a body of absolute law to enable them to distinguish objectively between defense and invasion.”[32]This point was not crystal clear even to Tucker or his followers, although at one point Tucker declared that “Anarchism does mean exactly the observance and enforcement of the natural law of liberty.”[33]It was left up to the twentieth-century individualist anarchists to explain the importance of a libertarian legal code. For example, Rothbard posits that his view of libertarianism includes, “not only the abolition of the State, but also the general adoption of a libertarian law code.”If the bulk of the population were to become persuaded to abolish the State, then they must already have been convinced that the aggressions the State commits are immoral violations of liberty and private property: “on what other basis can we convince them to abolish their revered government apparatus?”[34]

In the various discussions of voluntary taxation which appeared in Liberty, Tucker came very close to espousing this viewpoint.In response to a series of queries from Donisthorpe, Tucker noted: “A system of Anarchy in actual operation implies a previous education of the people in the principles of Anarchy, and that in turn implies such a distrust and hatred of interference that the only band of voluntary cooperators which could gain sufficient support to enforce its will would be that which either entirely refrained from interference or reduced it to a minimum.”[35]Although he did not follow up on this insight, Tucker realized that the implementation of anarchy carried with it the implication that people generally understood and accepted a libertarian legal code.

In other discussions of voluntary taxation with the English individualists, Tucker threw out a series of challenges to his correspondents. In Liberty of November 1, 1890, around the same time that Levy and Herbert were beginning to exchange views, Tucker reprinted several paragraphs written by Levy in the Personal Rights Journal.In these paragraphs, Levy plainly stated that anarchism implies the right of an individual to stand aside and see a man murdered or a woman raped. In contrast, Levy asserted that individualism would not only restrain the active invader but would also coerce into cooperation the man who would otherwise be a passive witness of aggression.Tucker accepted this judgment and pointed out that to coerce the peaceful non-cooperator is to violate the law of equal liberty.It is just as “impossible to attain the maximum of liberty by depriving people of their liberty as to attain the maximum of wealth by depriving people of their wealth. . . . [T]he means is absolutely destructive of the end.” Tucker understood that with compulsory taxation abolished, there could be no State.”The defensive institution that will succeed it will be steadily deterred from becoming an invasive institution through fear that the voluntary contributions will fall off.This constant motive for a voluntary defensive institution to keep itself trimmed down to the popular demand is itself the best possible safeguard against the bugbear of multitudinous rival political agencies.”Tucker concluded his editorial by citing his chief interest in Levy’s article. Tucker was excited by Levy’s “valid criticism of those Individualists who accept voluntary taxation but stop short, or think they stop short of Anarchism, and I shall wait with much curiosity to see what Mr. Greevz Fisher, and especially Mr. Auberon Herbert, will have to say in reply. Mr. Donisthorpe probably will he heard from also, but he really does not fall within Mr. Levy’s criticism.He is, as Mr. Levy says, more of an Anarchist than anything else. . . . On the whole Anarchists have more reason to be grateful to Mr. Levy for his article than to complain of it. It is at least an appeal for intellectual consistency on this subject, and as such it renders unquestionable service to the cause of plumb-line Anarchism.”[36]

Four issues later, Tucker published a letter from Donisthorpe to the editor of Free Life, which he captioned “Discrepant Boundaries.” In the letter, Donisthorpe claimed that he saw no contradiction in the expression “voluntary taxation.”Addressing Auberon Herbert, Donisthorpe wrote:

My quarrel with your Individualism is that the world is not ready for it. My individualism is absolute Anarchy qualified by a regard for social evolution. . . . Mr. Levy seems to me to hold with us moderate Anarchists that at present we require a residuum of State action.But where I think he errs is in supposing that this is the necessary and permanent condition.In the perfect (or more perfect) state of social development, I agree with your view.In the present state Mr. Levy and I are more in line, looking on the State as a necessary institution. We diverge when he insists on regarding it as a permanent institution. Perhaps I should even outrun you a little in the future.I am inclined to think with Tucker, that even the administration of justice will fall into private hands, though it is hard to foresee the construction of the judicial system.” [37]

Several months later, Tucker published another article taken from Herbert’s Free Life entitled “Justice and Taxation” and written by one of Herbert’s associates, M. D. O’Brien.In it, O’Brien set forth both his and Herbert’s view of voluntary taxation.Opening on the note that all individualists are in agreement that it is right to restrain by force the man who aggresses by force upon another man, O’Brien chided the “Taxation-Individualists” (“to use a ‘Free Life’ term”) for thinking it right to coerce a peaceful non-invader.In agreement with O’Brien, Tucker wrote:

a man’s non-aggressive earnings are his own, and there is no other warrant, save force, for a majority confiscating any portion of them . . . . We are only justified in using force when force is used to us, and all the helpers we get should be volunteers, not people whom we have impressed, or, what is the same thing, the impressed earnings of those people.[38]

In a much earlier piece (which was subsequently reprinted in Instead of a Book, Tucker referred to “some very interesting and valuable discussion” which “is going on in the London Jus concerning the question of compulsory versus voluntary taxation.”F. W. Read had written to Donisthorpe, editor of Jus, that voluntary taxation implied the existence of five or six voluntary states in England. Tucker pointed out that he saw nothing wrong or unusual with such a situation.After all, Tucker explained, there were more than five or six churches in England and many more than five or six insurance companies.”Though Mr. Read has grasped one idea of the voluntary taxationists,” he failed to see the other important idea behind it: “the idea that defence is a service, like any other service; that it is labor both useful and desired, and therefore an economic commodity subject to the law of supply and demand; . . .that, competition prevailing, patronage would go to those who furnished the best article at the lowest price; that the production and sale of this commodity are now monopolized by the State; that the State, like almost all monopolists, charges exorbitant prices; that, like almost all monopolists, it supplies a worthless or nearly worthless, article; . . .the State takes advantage of its monopoly of defence to furnish invasion instead of protection; . . .and, finally, that the State exceeds all its fellow-monopolists in the extent of its villainy because it enjoys the unique privilege of compelling all people to buy its product whether they want it or not.”Tucker concluded that only by five or six “states” hanging out their shingles and competing with one another could people be assured of quality service at reasonable rates.”And what is more,–the better their services, the less they would he needed; so that the multiplication of ‘States’ involves the abolition of the State.”[39]

As we have seen, the editors of Jus, Personal Rights, Free Life, and Liberty had significant differences among themselves. Levy commented on this in his previously mentioned discussion on “Political Terminology.”With respect to land ownership, Levy called Herbert a conservative anarchist.”The Conservative Anarchist would retain private property in land very much as it is in England at the present day, merely abolishing the obstacles to its free sale and purchase.The Individualist Anarchist would laugh at this pretension to sell or let land and would recognize only the right of the squatter to the land in his use or productive occupation.” The communist anarchist would decline to recognize any rights of property in land.[40]Liberty’s and Tucker’s position was that of the individualist anarchist, advocating the doctrine of occupation and use as the sole basis for land-holding.[41]Levy’s position on landownership is not clearly spelled out, although Tucker claimed that he was an advocate of land nationalization in England.[42]

These differences regarding landownership were aired in the pages of Liberty many times over.In one of the earlier references in Liberty, referring to the “Solutions of the Land Problem” and the English individualists, Victor Yarros noted that although he agreed with Auberon Herbert’s conclusions as far as they went, he did not reach these conclusions by the same logic.Quoting from an 1889 symposium on the land question held by the Personal Rights Association, Yarros quoted Herbert as follows: “The free and open market is the one system that does most justice among individuals, being the only impartial institution that exists, and at the same time is the only system that gives the evolutionary forces free play. . . . I scarcely need add that at present we have not a truly free and open market for land.All artificial impediments should be removed, and no new ones invented.”[43] Related issues were raised in Liberty about a year later, when Tucker reprinted correspondence which had appeared in Free Life.Albert Tarn, whom Tucker describes as an “Anarchistic correspondent,” had addressed a letter to Free Life in which he tried to combat Herbert’s assertion that anarchism would throw property titles, especially land titles, into hopeless confusion. Herbert’s contention was that “under the law of the free market, everybody knows, first, who owns a particular piece of property, and, secondly, the conditions under which property can be acquired.” Herbert attacked the doctrine of occupancy and use for being vague and indefinite in terms of establishing how ownership would be established and transferred in an anarchist society.Editorializing, Tucker rejoined that it would be up to “municipalities” (based on voluntary associations) to “formulate and enforce this view” of occupancy and use.According to Tucker, “under Anarchism all rules and laws will be little more than suggestions for the guidance of juries, and that all disputes, whether about land or anything else, will be submitted to juries which will judge not only the facts but the law.”[44]

Several months later, under the headline “Private Property and Freedom,” Victor Yarros picked up the argument again.According to Yarros, the difference between the viewpoints of Liberty and Mr. Herbert was: “he believes in allowing people to retain all their possessions, no matter how unjustly and basely acquired, while getting them, so to speak, to swear off stealing and usurping and to promise to behave well in the future.We, on the other hand, while insisting on the principle of private property, in wealth honestly obtained under the reign of liberty, do not think it either unjust or unwise to dispossess the landlords who have monopolized natural wealth by force and fraud.We hold that the poor and disinherited toilers would be justified in expropriating, not alone the landlords, who notoriously have no equitable titles to their lands, but all the financial lords and rulers, all the millionaires and very wealthy individuals.”Yarros recognized that “almost all possessors of great wealth enjoy neither what they nor their ancestors rightfully acquired (and if Mr. Herbert wishes to challenge the correctness of this statement, we are ready to go with him into full discussion of the subject).If he holds that the landlords are justly entitled to their lands, let him make a defence of the landlords or an attack on our unjust proposal.”[45]Unfortunately, Herbert never defended his position in Liberty. In the following issue, however, Tucker printed another letter from Herbert in which he continued his attack on occupancy and use. Tucker commented on it as follows:

The trouble with Mr. Herbert is that he begs the question of property altogether, and insists on treating the land problem as if it were simply a question of buying and selling and lending and borrowing, to be settled simply by the open market.Here I meet him with the words of his more conservative brother in Individualism, Mr. J. H. Levy, editor of the “Personal Rights Journal,” who is trying to show Mr. Herbert that he ought to call himself an Anarchist instead of an Individualist. Mr. Levy says, and I say after him: “When we come to the ethical basis of property, Mr. Herbert refers us to the open market.But this is an evasion. The question is not whether we should he able to sell or acquire in the open market anything which we rightfully possess, but how we come into rightful possession.And if men differ on this, as they do most emphatically, how is this to be settled?”[46]

Auberon Herbert was a hybrid, fully acceptable neither to Levy, the individualist, nor to Tucker, the anarchist.Even Wordsworth Donisthorpe rejected Herbert’s notions of self-ownership and rights: “Mr. Auberon Herbert insists on the right of self-ownership.He claims the right to own himself.I dispute it.I cannot see upon what the right is based. . . . I saw the force of their [the abolitionists’] arguments, and agreed; not because the niggers had any right to their liberty, but because I thought that in my interest that right should be conferred upon them.I deny the right then claimed for them, and I am delighted that they enjoy it now.”[47]Yet, Herbert was not without his supporters (except perhaps on the property or self-ownership question). John Badcock, in a letter to the Personal Rights Journal, wrote: “The most valuable part of Auberon Herbert’s teaching, to my mind, is the destruction which he gives to the artificial distinctions that have been set up between the acts of government and the acts of individuals, and the placing on par of all aggressions, whether individually or collectively perpetrated, whether sanctified by statute law or not so sanctified.”[48]

Herbert’s differences with Tucker and Liberty were not limited to property matters alone.Within a year after he had serialized and reprinted Herbert’s A Politician in Sight of Haven, Tucker chastised Herbert for not realizing the importance of economic equity to anarchist thinking. “Mr. Herbert proves beyond question that the government of man by man is utterly without justification, but is quite ignorant of the fact that interest, rent, and profits will find no place in the perfect economic order.”Tucker’s comments not only illustrate his own economic thinking, but criticize Herbert at the same time. Tucker complained that Herbert had never called attention to the importance of free trade in banking: “If he would only dwell upon the evils of the money-issuing monopoly and emphasize with his great power the fact that competition, in this as in other matters, would give us all that is needed of the best possible article at the lowest possible price, thereby steadily reducing interest and rent to zero, putting capital within the comfortable reach of all deserving and enterprising people, and causing the greatest liberation on record of heretofore restricted energies.”[49]

In turn, Herbert eventually asked in his Free Life how Tucker could justify a campaign against the right of men to lend and borrow.Tucker, of course, denied that he had ever campaigned on such an issue, but pointed out that he hoped that lending and borrowing might one day disappear in an anarchist society, where there would be no restrictions on people monetizing their own credit.Tucker asserted that “interest, however it may have originated, exists today only by virtue of the legal monopoly of the use of credit for currency purposes.” Anarchists “trace the process by which an abolition of that monopoly would reduce the rate of interest to zero. Mr. Herbert never stops to analyze this process that he may find the weak spot in it and point it out; he simply declares that interest, instead of resting on monopoly, is the natural, inevitable outcome of human convenience and the open market. . . . If it be true that interest will exist in the absence of monopoly, then there is some flaw in the reasoning by which the Anarchists argue from the abolition of monopoly to the disappearance of interest.”[50]

The pages of Liberty were peppered with arguments over economic issues, especially those issues concerned with money, banking, and interest. There were disputations in all directions: American anarchists arguing with other Americans; Americans arguing with the English individualists; and even the English individualists using the pages of the American Liberty to dispute among themselves.Of the English individualists, J. Greevz Fisher was probably the most prolific writer on these topics. Fisher was embroiled in at least three sets of debates appearing in Liberty.Beginning in 1891, Fisher and Tucker engaged in a spirited exchange concerning the power of government over values and free trade in banking.This exchange was included in Instead of a Book.Then in 1894 Hugo Bilgram and Fisher had it out in a lengthy series of letters regarding the justification of interest. Finally, in late 1896 and early 1897, John Badcock and Fisher went at one another over the alleged money famine and the value and volume of money.In most of these debates, Fisher criticized the anarchists from the point of view of sound economics.[51]

In the first of these series of debates, Tucker and Fisher discussed the merits of mutual banking.Fisher maintained that there was no legal obstacle to the introduction and circulation of promises of all types (such as promises to deliver wheat, cotton, or oil) which might then take the place of the Bank of England promises which circulated as money.Since there was no restriction on the types of money that might circulate, along with gold and promises to pay gold, Fisher claimed that government, in general, had little power to affect the purchasing power of gold.Tucker, on the other hand, alleged that the laws of England did not allow the workingmen to form mutual banks; that is, banks designed to issue paper money against any property that it may see fit to accept as security and such money not being redeemable in gold or silver.If mutual banks were not outlawed, then Tucker suggested that his English compatriots had nothing to complain of in the way of finance and had only to go out and start up their own banks in order to monetize their own credit.Tucker was convinced that such banking institutions were illegal in England “and in that case I tell him again that the present value of gold is a monopoly value sustained by the exclusive monetary privilege given it by the government.”[52]

In his rebuttal, Fisher asserted: “Schemes to bring about the abolition of interest, especially when the authors promulgate this as a necessary consequence of free trade in banking are pernicious. . . . What is called free trade in banking actually means only unlimited liberty to create debt.It is the erroneous labelling of debt as money which begets most of the fallacies of the currency-fadists.”[53]Tucker responded by quoting from Colonial William Greene’s Mutual Banking, claiming that mutual banking would reduce the value of gold because “it would thereby be stripped of that exclusive monetary utility conferred upon it by the State.”Tucker added that “the percentage of this reduction no one can tell in advance, any more than he can tell how much whiskey would fall in price if there were unrestricted competition in the sale of it.”[54]In his third letter in this series of exchanges, Fisher restated his contention that Tucker was wrong in thinking that the law of England did not permit mutual banks. In Fisher’s opinion, the concern of Tucker and the American anarchists was misplaced because they greatly overestimated the evils of the State banking system.[55]

In 1893 Tucker reprinted an address delivered by Hugo Bilgram on the subject of interest: “Is Interest Just?”In turn, J. Greevz Fisher wrote the Manchester Times criticizing Bilgram’s presentation. The following year Liberty carried a letter from Bilgram answering Fisher’s attack.[56]This was the beginning of a lengthy exchange between these two correspondents. Tucker would publish a letter by Fisher and in the same issue Bilgram’s “rejoinder” would appear. Fisher claimed that “the hire of tools, materials, and maintenance would yield a revenue in the absence of money” and that it was not the existence of government and its restrictive monetary policies that were responsible for interest.”What is necessary in order to establish the justice of interest is to show that in the absence of any restriction upon the issue of instruments of credit, and in the utter absence of laws of legal tender, interest would still be paid.” Mr. Bilgram, on his part, contended that government policies, such as “legal regulation of the volume of currency,” are “the cause of crises and business stagnation, of the existence of squalid poverty among those unable to find employment.”[57]In Fisher’s next letter to Liberty he outlined the core of his arguments against Bilgram:

Free and wholly unrestricted issue of all sorts of paper by all sorts of people to the utmost extent to which they could get it into circulation would certainly have as one of its results the development of a greater caution in accepting promises from those calling themselves bankers, and the elaboration of a system of voluntary audits and mutual guarantee of each other’s notes by many of these bankers. . . . Mr. Bilgram appears to take no notice of the argument that the rate of interest upon loans. . .[would still exist] under a system of barter. . . . Interest is the hire of commodities separated from their owner and entrusted to another person.The time of separation is a privation to one party (in marginal cases, which rule all cases) and a benefit to the other party.[58]

In later letters, Fisher stressed the importance of understanding the purchasing power of money.As he phrased it, “As money becomes scarce, it becomes more potent in exact proportion to its rise in value.”[59] Bilgram admitted that to the extent that interest “is a payment for risk. . .interest is just,” but he continued to assail “as unjust that part of interest which is said to be paid for being ‘deprived of a day’s pleasure’.”[60]In Bilgram’s view, interest was a monopoly privilege created by the laws forbidding the circulation of banknotes other than those by legally recognized banks.Thus interest was paid to holders of these notes only because of this exclusive monopoly privilege, which in effect restricted the amount of currency in circulation and on loan.Although Tucker was sympathetic to Bilgram’s arguments, he left it to his readers “to judge between the arguments that have been advanced,” when this debate closed in 1895.[61]

While these arguments were appearing in Liberty, several of the English individualists in London organized a new movement which they termed “The Free Currency Propaganda.”The society was formed for the purpose of assaulting the monopoly of money-issue.Their prospectus set forth the following views:

We affirm that the equitable payment of labor. . .is its entire product. . .and that the prevailing monstrous departure from this self-evident principle of justice, the sole and sufficient cause of social discontent and oppression, is due to the monopolies of land and capital. . . . We furthermore affirm that the monopoly of capital is solely due to the monopoly of monetary credit, which necessarily and essentially results from the arbitrary and exclusive adoption of gold–or specie–value as the basis of the circulating medium. . . . The tyranny of the money monopoly thus operates not only positively by exacting the tribute of interest and monopoly profits, but also negatively by barring the working classes from self-help and association.[62]

Among the names appearing at the end of this prospectus were those of Henry Seymour, John Armsden, Alfred E. Porter and John Badcock, Jr. Although J. Greevz Fisher could not support The Free Currency Propaganda movement, he realized that there was an element of truth in its assertions. He could support the idea of “free banking” based on property rights as summed up by G. O. Warren, writing under the name of T. L. M’Cready, one of the founding members of the movement: “the right to private property necessarily includes the right to exchange that property, and the right to exchange it includes the right to determine what it shall be exchanged for, be it any article or commodity, or a piece of paper with an inscription on it, be that inscription written or printed, and from whatever source. And, therefore, that any restriction upon, or interference with, exchange is a denial of the right of private property, and should be resisted.”[63]

In 1896 John Badcock, Jr. wrote an article appearing in Liberty on “The Money Famine” in which he supported these ideas. The main thrust of his argument was to oppose State monopolization of money issuance: “Let us have free trade in the issue of money. Only under freedom can the merits or demerits of any particular monies and instruments of credit have a chance to be demonstrated, and the fittest survive.Good money may be left to drive out bad money unaided.Let it be unhindered.”[64]However, his argument was not limited to this point.Badcock considered that there was a true “money famine” caused by restrictive banking laws and legal tender laws and, much like Bilgram, claimed that if the supply of money were increased interests, profits, and rent would disappear. In his first of a series of attacks on these ideas, which Tucker printed soon after the appearance of Badcock’s original article, Fisher maintained that the “money famine” was allegation rather than fact. He termed the expectation that interest, profits, and rent would disappear under a regime of free banking as “positively puerile.” “Under complete monetary freedom the delusion that debts are money would vanish.The benefits to be expected [from complete monetary freedom] lie in the direction of increased activity, competition, and stability of bankers, money-lenders, and borrowers.”[65] He also stressed the importance of understanding that the quantity of money in circulation was not of paramount concern because the purchasing power of money was not fixed and was changeable in accord with the supply of money on the market.The discussions and rejoinders between Badcock and Fisher continued in several later issues of Libertyand revolved around the formation of mutual banks in England and the exact form which the notes of such banks might take.This exchange ended finally in April 1897.[66]

None of these arguments was ever settled once and for all in Liberty. More than two years after the Badcock-Fisher debate, in September 1899, Wordsworth Donisthorpe sent a letter to Tucker on “Currency; Money and Credit; Coinage.”[67]Not to be outdone, Fisher addressed a letter to Liberty on “Mr. Donisthorpe on Currency.” This was his last contribution to Liberty on the subject of money.In it he made two very interesting observations. First, he supported the arguments of those advocating perfect freedom to issue money.”Liberty would enable the markets and force the issuers [of money] automatically and continuously to correct and improve the money or tokens.Gresham’s law as to the superior potency of inferior money applies only to fiat made money.”[68] Secondly, he summarized his views on the significance of monetary freedom in England, should it be instituted sometime in the future:

What then would be the advantages of liberty in relation to the currency? They would be great, but not at all overwhelming.They could only remedy evils which exist in consequence of State action.These, from an economic point of view, are not all so great as many Socialists, Anarchists, and Individualists imagine, at least in England.The main advantage would be in disabusing the public mind of the opposite superstition that State interference is very good and absolutely necessary. The fact is that it is no good at all.[69]

Tucker’s reaction to all of Fisher’s economic writings is to be found in his remarks in a column headlined “Anarchism and Children” written in 1895: “Pat Collins, the witty Democratic politician, once said of the late Prohibitionist leader Robert C. Pitman, that he would be a first-class man if he could only let rum alone.And I always think to myself, when I read the writings of Mr. J. Greevz Fisher in behalf of liberty, that he would be a first-class philosopher if he would only let money alone.”[70]Tucker then went on to quote approvingly from an article by Fisher which appeared in Personal Rights in April 1895 dealing with the question of parental responsibility for the support of children.Mr. Fisher wrote in part:

it would be highly dangerous to attempt to make legal responsibilities generally and universally embrace all moral responsibilities, because, if it were attempted, the enforcement of every virtue and the suppression of every vice would become objects of legal coercion. . . .

Neglect is not attack. . . . If a person, male or female, alleging parentage beats, enslaves, or defrauds a child, the Individualist has a perfect right to interfere.He can voluntarily associate himself with the child in a mutual defence organization. . . . No title to guardianship by a claimant parent ought to be admitted when the alleged guardianship is inimical to the minor.Beyond this point if it is unsafe to take one step.Neglect can be better remedied by upholding liberty for anyone directly to supply the wants of the neglected.It cannot be safely dealt with by attempts of a third party to force someone, supposed to be responsible, to undertake the duty.[71]

Tucker then quoted from the lament of the Personal Rights editor, J. H. Levy, who noted that Fisher’s argument was not, in fact, individualistic but rather anarchistic.Tucker, himself, had earlier written in favor of “The assumption is that we must not interfere to prevent neglect, but only to repress positive invasion.”[72] Tucker still maintained that “no person, parent or not, may be rightfully compelled to support any helpless being, of whatever age or circumstance, unless he had made that being helpless by some invasive act.”[73]

Subsequently, Tucker revised his position and logic on the question of parental responsibility and eventually concluded that the mother must own her children until the day that they reach maturity and self-emancipation.”[74]His final statement of his position was found in his editorial “L’Enfant Terrible”:

I can see no clearer property title in the world than that of the mother to the fruit of her womb, unless she has otherwise disposed of it by contract. . . . The change, then, which my opinion has undergone consists simply in the substitution of certainty for doubt as to the non-invasive character of parental cruelty–a substitution which involves the conclusion that parental cruelty is not to he prohibited, since third parties have not to consider the danger of disaster to organisms [children] that are outside the limits of social protection.[75]

In the same issue of Liberty, J. Greevz Fisher had a letter published in which he expressed his opposition to Tucker’s conception of “children as chattels.”Fisher pointed out that “the supposition of the chatteldom of the child, if based upon the utility, excellence and propriety of parental control, surely implies, among its benefits an advantage to the child.”Thus during the whole period of parental control, the parent is not an owner at all, but rather a “trustee”, in the legal jargon Fisher used.Fisher and other critics of Tucker’s position pointed out that if the mother were owner of the child, she could kill her child, “as a man may kill a horse,” or even throw her baby into the fire.[76]

Fisher was only one of several English individualists who claimed that the child was a self-owner who during its early years fell under the guardianship of its mother or parents.William Gilmour, the Scottish individualist, thought “guardianship, not ownership, is the real question at issue.”[77]John Badcock, in his letter “On the Status of the Child,” maintained that parents are the natural guardians of their children.”But,” he claimed, “guardian is not synonymous with owner, and, while guardianship is necessary for the child,–varying in quantity with the child’s development,–ownership is quite an intrusion, as it is in all slavery.”[78]Tucker expressed his opposition to the concept of guardianship or trusteeship. “I disclaim, however, any share in the belief which Mr. Badcock supposes me to hold in common with him that parents are the natural guardians of their offspring.I do not see why he supposes me to believe this, for not only is guardianship, as he says, not synonymous with ownership, but it is flatly contradictory of it. . . . Guardianship implies responsibility.In ownership there is no such responsibility. As I maintain that the mother is the owner of her child, of course I deny that she is guardian of her child.”[79]

John Badcock, Jr. was the author of Slaves to Duty, a lecture which he delivered in London in 1894.Although he and Tucker disagreed on the children issue, they held nearly identical ethical theories resting on egoism as illustrated by Tucker’s report of Badcock’s lecture.

In this lecture Mr. Badcock lays the spook of duty most effectively. He takes up, one by one, the various kinds of duties–political, social, marital, filial, etc.–discusses them as to their merits and demerits, and demonstrates that the subordination of self on the part of the individual to their requirements prevents him from appreciating the full value of existence and realizing the promises it originally holds out. In the place of duty Mr. Badcock puts–nothing, “as superstitions never want replacing,” but simply counsels people to study where their true and lasting interests lie and to turn all their energies to the furtherance of these regardless of codes, moral and political.[80]

Badcock and his English individualist friends displayed their contempt for society when they founded the Legitimation League in 1892 or 1893.J. H. Levy, J. Greevz Fisher, Donisthorpe, Badcock, along with Gladys and Oswald Dawson were all originally involved with the League.Its stated purpose was “to create machinery for acknowledging offspring born out of wedlock, and to secure for them equal rights with legitimate children.”[81]In 1893, Fisher published a pamphlet entitled “Illegitimate Children: An Inquiry into their Personal Rights and a Plea for the Abolition of Illegitimacy.”Wordsworth Donisthorpe published a review of this pamphlet in Liberty in 1894.[82] In 1897, according to Liberty, the League took on “A New Departure” as described by William Gilmour: “The Legitimation League, of London, which has had a somewhat passive existence since its formation four years ago, has now entered upon a ‘new crusade’. . .viz., the advocacy of the principle of sexual freedom, or freedom in sexual relationships.”Gilmour reported that Fisher and Donisthorpe had left the league, but that “Oswald Dawson, George Bedorough, Louie Bedorough, Seymour, Badcock, Rockell, and Wastall are still within its ranks.”[83]Henry Seymour became editor of its journal, The Adult: A Journal for the Advancement of Freedom in Sexual Relationships, which had a short-lived existence during the late 1890’s.[84]

Seymour had an interesting career as an anarchist, and fortunately a record of his early years in the movement has been preserved.His introduction to Tucker and Liberty was partly coincidental:

I chanced to meet Dr. Willard Knowleton Dyer and Sarah E. Holmes, who were travelling through Europe and temporarily staying at this resort [where Seymour had opened a “Science Library of advanced literature”]. They were enthusiastic in introducing the Boston Liberty, edited by Benj. R. Tucker, to my notice.Here was solid stuff, I thought, and not long elapsed before 1 was one of Liberty’s agents, and some time after published an English edition of Tucker’s translation of Bakunin’s God and the State.I remember, also, at this time, I happened across an old copy of Edmund Burke’s Vindication of Natural Society, which I sent to Tucker who promptly reprinted this gem as a classic introduction to the study of Anarchism.[85]

Seymour then recounts how he began publishing The Anarchist in March 1885.”It set forth my own profession of faith,–almost identical with that of Liberty–and contained original contributions by such notable writers as Henry Appleton, George Bernard Shaw, and Elisee Reclus, with whom I had made contacts.”[86]Eventually an English Anarchist Circle was formed among the many native and foreign anarchists in London, the most prominent of them being Peter Kropotkin. “The circle could not be squared,” wrote Seymour, and due to the differing temperaments and philosophic outlooks, the group disbanded. Seymour continued to publish The Anarchist and then The Revolutionary Review, until he went bankrupt.Seymour had wide connections in English anarchist circles and “had good relations with Malatesta, Tochatti (editor of the London Liberty), A. Tarn (editor of the Herald of Anarchy), Robert Harding, the passive-resistance Anarchist; and also met Lucy Parsons, Emma Goldman, Josephine Tilton, Lillian Harman, Sebastian Faure, Louise Michel, Bernard Lazare, Benj. R. Tucker and Mrs. Tucker with their bright little daughter, Oriole, when they severally came to London on various occasions.”[87]

Another aspect of the individualist anarchist movement in London during the last decades of the nineteenth century and the first decade of the twentieth was the Personal Rights Association.The extensive discussions between its secretary, J. H. Levy, and Auberon Herbert over compulsory taxation have already been examined.The Personal Rights Association has an interesting background and stems almost directly from the activities of a late Victorian reformer, Josephine Butler.A critic has described her as “the single individual most responsible for the spread of syphilis in Europe and perhaps the Josephine Butler was largely responsible for sparking the campaigns in England which led to the repeal of the Contagious Disease Acts.In 1864, the first of three Contagious Disease laws was passed by Parliament which made provisions for the surgical examination of prostitutes and for their confinement in “lock” hospitals if found diseased.The Act was limited to areas around eleven military garrisons and naval stations.The second Act of 1866 required prostitutes in these army towns to submit to medical examinations at least once every twelve months.A consolidating act was passed in 1868.In short the Contagious Disease Acts attempted to introduce in England the continental methods of regulating prostitution.[89]

Two distinct schools existed within the movement opposed to the Contagious Disease Acts. “For the policy, condemned by both alike, of regulating vice primarily in the interest of the physical health of vicious men, one desired to substitute the measures of vigorous suppression directed against men and women alike, while the other was chiefly concerned to protect poor and friendless women from being blackmailed and harassed by the police in the name of public decency, and was for leaving all forms of vice which did not involve force or fraud to be combatted by voluntary and non-coercive agencies.”[90]Josephine Butler’s organized activities against the Contagious Disease Acts began in 1869 or 1870, with the formation of the Ladies National Association for Repeal of the Contagious Disease Acts.Mrs. Butler was not a suppressionist, but rather believed in voluntary efforts to deal with the problem. In March 1871, she was on the organizing committee of The Vigilance Association for the Defence of Personal Rights and for the Amendment of the Law Wherein It Is Injurious to Women.[91]The membership of this latter organization reflects its origins in the Contagious Disease Acts controversy as well as in its overall anti-statist inclinations. For example, “while the radicals of the organization were caught up in the attempt to abolish state regulation of prostitution, they had also become exercised by a remarkably similar issue, compulsory vaccination.”[92]During the years 1881 to 1886, The Vigilance Association restyled itself and its purposes.J. H. Levy, who had been connected with the organization since 1878, was largely responsible for these changes.[93]

Under Levy’s leadership, the group became even more anti-statist.Beginning about 1881 such individualists as Donisthorpe, Herbert, and W. C. Crofts became involved in the organization.As the campaign for the repeal of the Contagious Disease Acts approached success (repeal was passed by Parliament in 1886), the two groups within The Vigilance Association (the coercive suppressionists and the non-coercive persuasionists) splintered. The suppressionists formed their own new organization called The National Vigilance Association for the Repression of Vice and Public Immorality. The persuasionists, claiming that the new group had “filched from us our good name,” changed the name of the original Vigilance Association to The Personal Rights Association.[94] Its organ, successively titled The Personal Rights Journal, Personal Rights, and lastly The Individualist, was published for over thirty years by Levy.[95] Through this medium, Levy “worked on the frontiers of liberal individualism in pursuit of the full application of the classical ideal of perfect equality before the law.”He “also worked in the neglected areas of personal rights, pioneering in lunacy law reform, participating in the anti-vivisection campaign and thereby extending liberal individualism. . . to its ultimate limits: the world of the helpless and the animal kingdom.”[96]

At least two supporters of the Personal Rights Association were involved in other anti-statist organizations.Wordsworth Donisthorpe was one of the two co-founders of the State Resistance Union (1880), which was the predecessor of the Liberty and Property Defence League (1882). Donisthorpe edited his own individualist journal, Jus, from January 1885 until March 1888.[97]Eventually Donisthorpe resigned from the Liberty and Property Defence League, because he was not satisfied with its limited activities.[98]Donisthorpe’s cousin, W. C. Crofts, remained administrator and secretary of the League until his death in 1894.Both he and Crofts tried to keep liberty, rather than property, to the fore, but it seemed to Donisthorpe that the League was more interested in defending the privileges of property.[99]

“Among the individualists an exotic variety of organizations” abounded.[100] Similarly there existed a wide range of opinions among those calling themselves individualists or individualist anarchists.Despite the differences between Tucker and the group of English individualists we have examined in this paper, all of them could probably subscribe to Tucker’s eloquent summation of his own creed, entitled “Woes of An Anarchist,” written in response to Wordsworth Donisthorpe’s essay of 1890: “there are some troubles from which mankind can never escape. . . . They [the anarchists] have never claimed that liberty will bring perfection; they simply say that its results are vastly preferable to those that follow from authority. . . . As a choice of blessings, liberty is the greater; as a choice of evils, liberty is the smaller. Then liberty always says the Anarchist:No use of force except against the invader.”[101]

NOTES

*This essay will also appear in Benjamin R. Tucker and the Champions of Liberty: A Centenary Anthology, ed. Michael E. Coughlin, Mark Sullivan, and Charles Hamilton (St. Paul, Minn.: Michael E. Coughlin, forthcoming, 1983). Copyright 1983 by Carl Watner.

  1. Properly speaking, J. C. Spence should not be included in this group.His name does not appear in Wendy McElroy, comp., Liberty, 1881-1908: A Comprehensive Index (St. Paul: Michael E. Coughlin, 1982). He was a follower of Herbert’s Voluntaryist movement and wrote a very libertarian analysis of the land question entitled Property in Land: A Defence of Individual Ownership (London: Liberty and Property Defence League, 1897).According to Edward Jay Bristow (“The Defense of Liberty and Property in Britain, 1880-1914,” [Ph.D. diss., Yale University, 1970], p. 180). Spence was a prominent naval architect.William Gilmour is not listed here, since he was originally a Scottish anarchist, but he did contribute to Liberty and is briefly referred to in later parts of this essay.Little is known of Porter aside from his involvement in The Free Currency Propaganda.His contributions to Liberty are listed in McElroy’s Liberty. 1881-1908.

2. Bristow, “Defense of Liberty and Property,” p. 180.

3. Ibid.

4. Murray N. Rothbard, ‘The Spooner-Tucker Doctrine: An Economist’s View,” in Egalitarianism as a Revolt Against Nature and Other Essays(Washington, D.C.: Libertarian Review Press, 1974), p. 133.

5. S. E. Parker, “Introduction,” to John Badcock, Jr., Slaves to Duty (Colorado Springs, Colo.: Ralph Myles, 1972). p. 3.

6. Bristow, “Defense of Liberty and Property,” p. 178.

7. Liberty 5 (March 10. 1988):2.

8. Taxation and Anarchism: A Discussion between the Hon. Auberon Herbert and J. H. Levy (London: The Personal Rights Association, 1912), pp. 63-64.

9. Ibid., p. 61.

10. Ibid., p. 62.This is also confirmed by Tucker’s evaluation of Herbert’s philosophy. (See Liberty 15 [December 1906]:16.)For a selective bibliography on Auberon Herbert, see Eric Mack, ed., The Right and Wrong of Compulsion by the Store and Other Essays (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Classics, 1978), pp. 27-29.

11. Taxation and Anarchism, pp. vi-vii.

12. Ibid., pp. 2-3.

13. Ibid., p. 7.

14. Liberty 13 (July 1899):2

15. Taxation and Anarchism, p. 24.

16. Ibid., p. 29.

17. Ibid., p. 32.

18. Ibid., pp. 40.41.

19. Ibid., p. 52. Although it is not absolutely clear from the quotation, the implication is that Herbert believed there would be only one (central) defense agency operating in his ideal society.

20. Ibid.

21. Ibid.

22. Ibid., p. 53.

23. Ibid.

24. Twentieth-century individualist anarchists have begun to develop such standards. For example, see George H. Smith, “Justice Entrepreneurship in a Free Market,” Journal of Libertarian Studies 3 (Winter 1979): 405-26.

25. Taxation and Anarchism, p. 44.

26. Ibid., p. 45.

27. Ibid.

28. Ibid., p. 46.

29. See Rothbard’s comments in “The Spooner-Tucker Doctrine,” pp. 127-28.

30. Rothbard, Power and Market (Menlo Park. Calif.: Institute for Humane Studies. 1970), p. 122.

31. Ibid., p. 123.

32. Ibid.

33. Quoted by Rothbard, “The Spooner-Tucker Doctrine,” p. 128, from Liberty 3 (October 24, 1885): 4.

34. Rothbard, “Will Rothbard’s Free-Market Justice Suffice?” Reason Magazine 5 (May 1973): 24-25.

35. Donisthorpe’s queries are in Liberty 7 (May 24, 1890): 6-7.Tucker’s answer is in ibid., pp. 5-6.

36. Liberty 7 (November 1, 1890):4.

37. Liberty 7 (December 27, 1890):3.

38. Liberty 7 (April 18, 1891):3.

39. Liberty 4 (July 30, 1887):4.

40. Taxation and Anarchism, pp. 64-66.

41. For a discussion of the occupation and use doctrine in Liberty, see Carl Watner, “A Question of Property,” The Dandelion, nos. 1, 2 (Spring and Summer 1977).

42. Liberty 7 (October 18, 1890):l.Also see Roland K. Wilson, The Province of the State (London: P. S. King and Son, 1911), p. 274.

43. Liberty 6 (August 10, 1889):5.

44. Liberty 7 (July 12, 1890):5.

45. Liberty 7 (November 15, 1890):4-5.

46. Liberty 7 (November 29, 1890):7.Herbert apparently did not rely an the homesteading principle.See Carl Watner, “Spooner vs. Liberty,”Libertarian Forum 7, no. 3 (March 1975): 5-7.

47. Liberty 14 (November 18, 1899):4.

48. Liberty 9 (June 24, 1893):3.

49.Liberty 3 (May 23, 1885):4.

50. Liberty 7 (October 18, 1890):4.Herbert’s only justification for interest was that it “is both moral and useful” (Liberty 7 [November 29, 1890]:4).

51. Rothbard, “The Spooner-Tucker Doctrine,” p. 133.

52. Liberty 8 (June 27, 1891):4.Also see comments, ibid., p. 3.

53. Liberty 8 (July 11, 1891):3.

54. Ibid., p. 4.

55. Far the rest of the letters in this series, see Liberty 8 (August 15, 1891):3, and 8 (August 22. 1891): 2-3.

56. For the original Fisher letter, see Liberty 9 (April 22, 1893):l.For Bilgram’s reply, see Liberty 9 (March 10, 1894):11.

57. Liberty 10 (May 19, 1894):8.

58. Liberty 10 (July 28, 1894):8.

59. Liberty 10 (November 17, 1894):4.

60. Ibid., p. 5.

61. Liberty 10 (March 9, 1895):s.Also see letters in Liberty 10 (January 12, 1895):4-5

62. Liberty 9 (May 5, 1894):ll.

63. Liberty 10 (September 8. 1894):9.

64. Liberty 12 (July 11, 1896):7.

65. Liberty 12 (October 1896):6.Note the similarity to Rothbard: “Thus, a system of free banking, such as envisioned by Spooner and Tucker, far from leading to an indefinite increase of the supply of money and a disappearance of interest, would lead to a far ‘harder’ and more restricted money supply” (“The Spooner-Tucker Doctrine,” p. 133).

66. Liberty 12 (January 1897):5-6, and 13 (April 1897):7.

67. Liberty 14 (September 1899):6-8.

68. Liberty 14 (November 1899):7.

69. Ibid., p. 9.

70. Liberty 10 (May 4, 1895):5.

71. Ibid.

72. Ibid. This is Levy’s formulation of Tucker’s attitude. See Liberty 9 (September 3,1892):l.

73. Liberty 10 (May 4. 1895):8.

74. Liberty 11 (June 29, 1895):4.

75. Liberty 11 (August 24, 1895):4.

76. Ibid., p. 6; and 11 (September 7, 1895):l.

77. Liberty 11 (August 24, 1895):7.

78. Liberty 11 (September 21. 1895):7. Badcock also stated disapprovingly that “if ownership rights are granted, . . .these rights would be salable, and a class of child-slaves and slave-markets would follow as a matter of course” (ibid.).For libertarian advocacy of the sale of guardianship rights, see Rothbard, “Kid Lib,” Egalitarianism as a Revolt, p. 93.

79. Liberty 11 (October 25, 1895):4.

80. Liberty 10 (November 17, 1894):4. Reprinted in Badcock, Slaves to Duty.

81. Liberty 9 (June 17, 1893):3.

82. Liberty 9 (May 5, 1894):8-9.

83. Liberty 13 (May 1897):7.

84. Bristow, “Defense of Liberty and Property,” p. 181. According to Bristow, “The resigning members-Donisthorpe and the Voluntaryist J. C. Spence and Greevz Fisher–held essentially the same view on the sex question as the anarchist rump: monogamous relationships easily terminated and unregulated by the state” (ibid).

85. Henry Seymour, “The Genesis of Anarchism in England,” in Joseph Ishill, ed., Free Vistas (Berkley Heights, N.J.: The Oriole Press, 1937). 2121.

86. Ibid., p. 122. Tucker did not consider Seymour a true individualist anarchist at the start of Seymour’s anarchist career. See Liberty 4 (May 1, 1886):4, and 4 (June 19, 1886):l.

87. Seymour. “The Genesis of Anarchism,” p. 128.Albert Tarn made several contributions to Liberty. See entry under “Tarn” in McElroy, Liberty,1881-1908.Some of the more interesting contributions are in Liberty 6 (March 16, 1889):l; 9 (June 24, 1893):l; and 12 (June 27, L896):7.

88. Glen Petrie, A Singular Iniquity: The Campaigns of Josephine Butler (New York: Viking Press, 1971), p. 94, quoting from Lujo Bassermann, The Oldest Profession (1967).

89. Ibid., “Prologue,” pp. 11-21.

90. Wilson, Province of the State, p. 273.

91. Bristow, “Defense of Liberty and Property,” pp. 61, 67.

92. Ibid., pp. 68-69.

93. Ibid., p. 75. Bristow adds, “As a founder of the Dialectical Society, Professor of Logic and Economics at Birkbeck College and the City of London College, colleague of Mill’s on the council of the Land Tenure Reform Association, and contributor to Bradlaugh’s National Reformer, Levy was a well-known figure in metropolitan and radical circles”(ibid.).

94. Ibid., p. 78.

95. Wilson, Province of the State, p. 273.The Individualist survived under the editorship of Henry Meulen.It was published continuously until his death in 1978.

96. Bristow, “Defense of Liberty and Property,” p. 61. Two of Levy’s pamphlets were titled: “Vivisection and Moral Evolution,” (no date) and “Our Duty to the Animal World.” (1913). In Vivisection and Personal Rights (London: P. S. King, 1902), Levy equates animal rights and personal rights: “This question of animals rights cannot be evaded by the Personal Rights Association; for they are inseparable from personal rights.If animals have no rights which it is our duty, as a political body, to defend, then every prosecution for cruelty to animals is an aggression on personal rights.We must, therefore, either condemn every effort of the State to prevent torture of any sentient being outside of the human race, or we must acknowledge that rights to not belong exclusively to our own sweet selves” (p. 15).Also see the concern of John Badcock in suppressing cruelty to animals inLiberty 11 (August 10, 1895):7-8.

97. Norbert C. Soldon, “Laissez-Faire on the Defensive: The Story of the Liberty and Property Defence League, 1882-1914,” (Ph.D. diss., University of Delaware, 19691, p. 253. Also see idem, “Laissez-Faire as Dogma: The Liberty and Property Defence League, 1882-1914,” in Kenneth D. Brown, ed., Essays in Anti-Labour History (Hamden, Conn.: Archon Books, 1974). pp. 208-21.

98. See Donisthorpe’s comments in Liberty 6 (November 23, 1889):l; and Bristow, “The Liberty and Property Defence League and Individualism,” Historical Journal 18 (1 975):773.

99. See Donisthorpe’s obituary of William Carr Crofts in Personal Rights, reprinted in Liberty 10 (March 9, 1895):7.

100. Bristow, “Defense of Liberty and Property,” p. 179.

101. Liberty 6 (January 25, 1890):4.

BENJAMIN TUCKER AND HIS PERIODICAL: LIBERTY


CARL WATNER

Baltimore, Maryland

In a letter to the New York Tribune on December 4, 1898, Benjamin Tucker (1854-1939) described himself as an Anarchist. “I was the first American–I may say the first Anglo-Saxon–to start (in 1881) an avowedly Anarchistic newspaper printed in the English language. I am still the editor, publisher, and proprietor of that paper. It is everywhere regarded as the pioneer and principal organ of modern individualist Anarchism. I either am, or have been, the publisher of the chief Anarchistic works in the English language. I am the author of the most widely-accepted English text-book of Anarchism. I have enjoyed the friendship, had the benefit of the instruction, and. have carefully studied the works, of those Americans from whom the Anarchists have largely derived their beliefs–Josiah Warren, Stephen Pearl Andrews, Lysander Spooner, and Colonel William B. Greene. I am the translator into English of some of the principal works of P. J. Proudhon, who was the first writer in any language to declare himself an Anarchist. I am acquainted, perhaps better than any other man, with the English-speaking Anarchists of the United States. It will be admitted then, I hope, that I speak by the card.” (359-3)*

Tucker’s Anarchist credentials were impeccable as he plainly stated. In August 1881, he started a “little fortnightly journal called Liberty. Its purpose was to contribute to the solution of the social problems by carrying to a logical conclusion the battle against authority . . . “[1]. This journal appeared more or less continuously under the guidance of Tucker, first in Boston, and then in New York, until 1908 when Tucker’s bookstore and composing room were destroyed by fire. In the words of Paul Avrich, Liberty was simply “the best Anarchist paper in the English language”.

The 403 issues of Liberty which appeared have been reprinted and made available by the Greenwood Reprint Corporation. They are a great source of information both to the historian and the philosopher. Here we can analyze the history of the individualist Anarchist movement, its reaction to contemporary events of the late 19th and early 20th Centuries, as well as view the actual ideological content and doctrinal changes occurring in the movement. To study Liberty is to touch practically every social question. (132-5) “. . . Liberty carried translations and articles from many of the most seminal thinkers of both Europe and America.”[2] While its subscription list probably never exceeded 1000, it had a world-wide circulation and impact, considering that it sparked individualist Anarchist movements in Russia and Australia, among other places.

Tucker made it clear in his first issue that his “journal will be edited to suit its editor, not its readers. He hopes that what suits him will suit them; but, if not, it will make no difference. No subscriber, or body of subscribers, will be allowed to govern his course, dictate his policy, or prescribe his methods. Liberty is published for the very definite purpose of spreading certain ideas, and no claim will be admitted, on any pretext of freedom of speech, to waste its limited space in hindering the attainment of that object. We are not afraid of discussion, and shall do what we can to make room for short, serious, and well-considered objection to our views.” (1-1) “The purpose of Liberty, boiled down to its ultimate essence, is the abolition of authority . . . . Liberty denies the authority of anybody’s god to bind those who do not accept it through persuasion and natural selection. Liberty denies the authority of anybody’s State to bind those who do not lend voluntary allegiance to it. Liberty denies the authority of anybody’s ‘public opinion’, ‘social custom’, ‘consensus of the competent’, and every other fashionable or scholarly despot, to step between the individual and his free option in all things.” (2-2)

As the proprietor and editor of Liberty, Tucker was responsible for its opinions and editorial content. While realizing that he was never the sole owner of Anarchism, Tucker did dominate his paper, and accordingly came to influence the Anarchist movement. However, he well realized that anarchism existed before he did and would continue to exist after he passed away. “I can interpret it only for myself”, he wrote. (327-3) Although gentlemanly and shy in his personal relations, Tucker was the “plumb line of plumb liners” in his editorial role. He tolerated no deviation from the straight and true path of Anarchy as he understood it. His intention as editor was to “win first the attention, and then the admiration and assent, of the most thoughtful thousand people in the world, though at the same time it may for the moment shock, horrify, prejudice, madden, and alienate all others . . . . ” (367-1) E. 0.Brown elaborated this point: “I have seen much in Liberty that I agreed with, and much that 1 disagreed with, but 1 never saw any cant, hypocrisy, or insincerity in it, which makes it an almost unique publication.” (370-7)

Tucker’s outlook and optimism are illustrated by relating one item which he saw fit to include in his first issue. Headlined, “The Penalty of Treason to Liberty,” it related the story told by Ariosto, in which a fairy, by some mysterious law of her nature, was condemned to appear at certain seasons in the form of a foul and poisonous snake. Those who injured her in the period of her disguise were forever excluded from the blessings which she bestowed when in her power. To those who befriended her, in spite of her loathsome aspect, she afterwards granted all their wishes and made them happy in every way. “Such a spirit is liberty”, concluded Tucker. “At times, she takes the form of a hateful reptile. She ‘grovels’, she hisses, she stings. But woe to those who in disgust shall venture to crush her. And happy are those who, having dared to receive her in her degraded and frightful shape, shall at length be rewarded by her in the time of her beauty and glory.” (1-4)

In order to fully appreciate Tucker and Liberty, one must have an understanding of how he and his readers understood the word Anarchism. “Anarchism means no government, but it does not mean no laws and no coercion. This may seem paradoxical, but the paradox vanishes when the Anarchist definition of government is kept in view. Anarchists oppose government, not because they disbelieve in punishment of crime and resistance to aggression, but because they disbelieve in compulsory protection. Protection and taxation without consent is itself invasion; hence Anarchism favors a system of voluntary taxation and protection.” (212-2) Tucker was one of the very first individuals in the world to advocate the idea “that defense is a service, like any other service”, and that such a service could and should be provided by private agencies supported by voluntary patronage. (104-4)

This advocacy was in turn based on a certain definition of government, namely “government has been defined . . . as the subjection of the ‘non-invasive’ individual to a will not his own.” (156-4) The State (or government) is in its very nature a compulsory institution to which all are forced to belong to and which all are compelled to support. (26-2) Liberty’s supporters were the sternest enemies of invasion of person and property. “We make war upon the State as the chief invader of person and property, as the cause of substantially all the crime and misery that exist, as itself the most gigantic criminal extant.” (25-2)

The starting point of the entire Anarchistic philosophy was the absolute sovereignty of every individual. (28-2) The only way to respect the sovereignty of the individual would be to refrain from invasion of every person’s body and justly acquired property. Tucker realized that criminals and invaders of person and property would remain, even in the absence of formal governments, but “Liberty’s position [was] that, of the really serious and important acts of invasion of individual sovereignty, at least nine-tenths are committed by organized State governments or through privileges granted by them, and that the governmental idea, with the State as its principal embodiment, is the efficient cause of almost all of our social evils.” (86-4) Thus Anarchism was not only a protest against every form of human invasion (94-5), but in particular against the aggression of organized government.

Liberty’s advocacy of Anarchism had both a positive and negative side. The negative side was simply the call for the abolition of politics. (25-2) Liberty proposed to abolish government and substitute in its place voluntary arrangements. “We offer every possible method of voluntary social union by which men and women may act together for the furtherance of well-being.” (27-2) Tucker carried this doctrine to its fullest extent, as he was not hound by political or cultural or social mores. Tucker and his supporters differed from all other 19th Century radicals in their conception of cooperation. These Anarchists distinguished themselves even from the Individualists, who believed that “cooperation for defense and protection should be compulsory, whereas the Anarchist believed] that cooperation should never be compulsory, and that no compulsion should ever be exercised upon the non-invasive individual.” (260-2) Although Tucker was likely at times to call himself a socialist, he always emphasized the voluntary aspect of socialism. His disagreement with the communists and socialists of other schools revolved around their economics as well as their conception of cooperation. ” . . . [T]heir Communism is another State, while my voluntary cooperation is not a State at all. It is a very easy matter to tell who is an Anarchist and who is not. Do you believe in any form of imposition upon the human will by force?” (94-4)

From the beginning of Liberty, Tucker placed emphasis on the rights of the individual and individual sovereignty. This natural rights approach may have been influenced by Lysander Spooner who at the commencement of Liberty was still living and contributing articles to it. Reminiscent of Spooner’s outlook, was the statement in an 1882 issue that “there is but one single kind of ‘legal’ freedom; and that is simply the ‘natural’ freedom of each individual to do whatever he will with himself and his property, for his body here, and his soul hereafter, so long as he does not trespass upon the equal freedom of any other person.” (24-2) In still an earlier issue was enunciated the cardinal right of all individuals to do anything and everything which they may chose voluntarily to do so long as it is done at their own cost. (7-2)

“Th[e] question of rights and obligations was thoroughly threshed out in Liberty in the year 1887.” (198-2) Although Tucker maintained that he had not changed his fundamental pinions since he had begun Liberty, it is obvious that by the late 1880s his defense of Anarchism had changed from one asserting a natural rights justification to one asserting the Stirnerite version of egoism. (201-4) By early 1888, Tucker was no longer defending property as a right, but rather claimed it to be only a social convention. (117-5) Having abandoned natural right as the basis of Anarchism, Tucker replaced it with the concept of equal liberty as the touchstone of his Anarchism. “It is true . . . that Anarchism does not recognize the principle of human rights. But it recognizes human equality as a necessity of stable society.” (126-4) ” . . . [T]he only compulsion of individuals the propriety of which Anarchism recognizes is that which compels invasive individuals to refrain from overstepping the principle of equal liberty. Now, equal liberty itself being a social convention (for there are no natural rights), it is obvious that Anarchism recognizes the propriety of compelling individuals to regard ‘one’ social convention. . . . Anarchism protects equal liberty . . . , not because it is a social convention, but because it is equal liberty, -that is, because it is Anarchism itself.” (123-5)

Tucker expressed his changed attitude as follows: “From the start [of Liberty] I have known that self-interest is the mainspring of conduct and that the ego is supreme. I had not, however, carefully thought out or even considered the bearing of this philosophy upon the question of obligation. I took society for granted and assumed the desire of man for society, and it was from this standpoint that I had loosely talked of natural rights. But Stirner’s book [The Ego and His Own] caused me to ask myself: If the individual does not wish society, is he under any obligation to act socially? And I no sooner asked it than I answered it in the negative. At no time have I answered it in the affirmative. . . . I have since [I8861 seen that my use of the word right in those days was entirely improper, and this, coupled with a steadily-clearing perception of the logic of egoism, is the only change my ethical opinions have undergone since I started Liberty.” (201-4)

In later years, Tucker exemplified his position by questioning the moralists (those asserting the natural rights philosophy and opposing his egoistical justification of Anarchism): “Why is one man bound to refrain from injuring another? That is the question which the moralists must answer. I know plenty of reasons why it is expedient for one man to refrain from injuring another. Therefore I advise him to refrain. But if my reasons do not commend themselves to his judgement; if my view of expediency does not coincide with his,–what obligation is there upon him to refrain? . . . I see no reason, as far as moral obligation is concerned, why one [man] should not subordinate or destroy the other. But if each of these men can be made to see that the other’s free life is helpful to him, then they will agree not to invade each other; in other words, they will equalize their existences, or rights to existence by contract. . . Before contract is the right of might. Contract is the voluntary suspension of the right to might. The power secured by such suspension we may call the right of contract. These two rights–the right of might and the right of contract–are the only rights that ever have been or ever can be. So-called moral rights have no existence.” (261-3) Tucker demanded to know what obligation, apart from expediency, there is upon man to refrain from aggressing against mother. (265-1) His point was that the obligation to refrain from aggression was universal, without exception, or it was nothing. The problem as he saw it was to justify the imposition of this obligation upon the man who chose to forsake human society or enjoyed social unrest and insecurity. Thus Tucker concluded that there are no rights except mights. (194-1) “Rights begin only with convention. They are not the liberties that exist through natural power, but the liberties that are created by mutual guarantee.” (328-4)

Fearless logician that he was, Tucker was never afraid to endorse his reasoning, regardless of where it led him. It was only on egoistic and utilitarian grounds–i.e. grounds of expediency–that he believed in equal liberty. (3204) On several occasions during the later years of Liberty Tucker was forced to concur in certain deviations from his earlier Anarchistic position based on non-invasion and respect for individual sovereignty. Thus he claimed that a woman who threw her baby into the fire was acting non-invasively, (321-1) and that in certain instances coercion of the non-invader was justified. Reasoning from his egoistic framework, Tucker denied that the thing fundamentally desirable was the minimum of invasion. For him, “the ultimate end of human endeavor [was] the minimum of pain. We aim to decrease invasion only because, as a rule, invasion increases the total of pain (meaning, of course, pain suffered by the ego, whether directly or through sympathy with others). But it is precisely my contention that this rule, despite the immense importance which I place upon it, is not absolute; that, on the contrary, there are exceptional cases where invasion–that is, coercion of the non-invasive lessens the aggregate pain. Therefore coercion of the non-invasive, when justifiable at all, is to be justified on the ground that it secures, not a minimum of invasion, but a minimum of pain. . . . [T]o me [it is] axiomatic–that the ultimate end is the minimum of pain.” (324-4) Thus Tucker asserted that coercion and invasion were justifiable in the case of a burning city, which can only be saved by blowing up the houses on a strip of territory inhabited by non-invasive persons who refuse to consent to such disposition of their property. (324-4) (310-5) According to Tucker, necessity and only necessity may excuse the coercion of the innocent, (308-4) and he readily admitted that there were relations between men and the land and of men to each other, where he would for the moment trample ruthlessly upon all the principles by which successful society must as a general rule be guided. (304-3)

Tucker held “that emergencies are liable to arise in the lives of men and of societies when all principles except that of self-preservation must be thrown to the winds; that there are moments when the continuance of individual life and social relations depends on the promptness with which we violate the very rules of conduct that in ordinary and normal times contribute most vitally to our well-being.” (339-4) In defending his position, Tucker declared that a critic’s answer amounted “in its conclusion to a statement that no evil can be as disastrous as an act of invasion; that justice should be done though the heavens fall, for a precedent of injustice would lead to a worse disaster than the falling of the heavens; . . . ” and that further discussion was hopeless. (341-4)

One final example will suffice to show that for Tucker, there were occasions when justice was not the supreme consideration. (341-4) Another of his critics propounded the situation of a drowning man agreeing to forego all his worldly goods in return for being saved from drowning. The critic demanded to know if under Anarchistic ethics such an agreement was enforceable. Tucker’s position was that such a contract was not enforceable, even though its non-enforcement was a violation of Anarchistic principle. Tucker’s conclusion was that “there is no obligation upon outsiders to enforce any contract, even though it be just, and that, when individuals associate themselves for defensive purposes, they will decide at the start what classes of just contracts it is advisable to enforce.” (341-4) Such men will decline to enforce the just contract of a drowning man.

Turning from Tucker’s ethics and philosophy of Anarchism, which were always and obviously a central part of Liberty, let us examine a few other themes which were taken up in his journal. During his early editorial years, Tucker expressed great interest in the activities of the social revolutionaries, both abroad and in the United States. The Russian and European Anarchist movement received both support and publicity from Liberty [3] Tucker wrote at the time of the Anarchist trial in Lyons, France in early 1883, “Anarchy knows no frontiers; it is a gospel of human brotherhood that spans oceans.” (33-2) During the first three years of Liberty, Tucker was a follower of many Anarchists of inter-national fame, such as Elisee Reclus, Peter Kropotkin, Michael Bakunin, and others of lesser note. As time wore on, particularly after the Haymarket affair in 1886, Tucker came to restrict his support of these revolutionaries who practiced “propaganda by deed.” His objection was not only to their violent methods but also to their support of authoritarianism.

Tucker illustrated this discrimination in his eulogy on Karl Marx which appeared in 1883, after Marx’s death: “For Karl Marx, the ‘egalitaire’, we feel the profoundest respect; as for Karl Marx, the ‘authoritaire’, we must consider him an enemy. . . . Proudhon was years before Marx [in discussing the struggle of the classes and the privileges and monopolies of capital]. . . . The vital difference between Proudhon and Marx [was] to be found in their respective remedies which they proposed. Man would nationalize the productive and distributive forces; Proudhon would individualize and associate them. Marx would make the laborers political masters; Proudhon would abolish political mastership entirely. . . . Man believed in compulsory majority rule; Proudhon believed in the voluntary principle. In short, Marx was an ‘authoritaire’; Proudhon was a champion of Liberty.” (35-2)

Tucker displayed basically the same attitude towards the Haymarket martyrs. Nearly all the contemporary violence of the Anarchists was commented on in Liberty. This included the assassination of President Garfield by Guiteau, the attempted killing of Carnegie’s associate, Frick, by Alexander Berkman, as well as the deeds of the revolutionaries abroad, especially in France and Russia. Tucker was not opposed to the use of force, but it was foolish in his opinion to “resort to it before necessity compels, . . . as a general thing, when force becomes necessary, the wiser way is to use as much as possible as promptly as possible; and, until it becomes necessary, there cannot be too little force.” (85-1) He generally considered violence to be inexpedient and an inappropriate way of achieving his goals. He realized that the downfall of one government, unless accompanied by a corresponding change in the ideas among the populace, would only result in the substitution of another government in its place. His goal was the destruction of the governmental idea, which could only be accomplished through the use of persuasion and reason. In the opinion of Victor Yarros, another writer for Liberty, “The practical abolition of the State would be a very easy matter, if the State ‘idea’ were once abolished in the ‘minds’ of a considerable number of people.” (113-8)

Regardless of the poor publicity generated by the revolutionaries, Tucker refused to compromise on his use of the word Anarchism or on his overall philosophy. He wrote, that “we believe that the most manly and effectual method of dealing with the State is to demand its immediate and unconditional surrender as a usurper, and to flatly and openly challenge its assumed right to forestall and crush out the voluntary associative government and regulation of individuals by themselves in all things.” (16-2) Tucker believed that the Land League Movement in Ireland had been a glorious and significant social force, arising from the fact that it developed as the result of spontaneous, voluntary actions. (20-2) Furthermore, the “No Rent Manifesto” could have been a stepping stone towards to “No Tax Manifesto.” Had the mass of Irishmen not swallowed the idea that society is impossible without a State, they might have been successful. Passive resistance (ignoring the laws without causing direct harm to anyone) and resistance to taxation were Tucker’s two main methods of achieving Liberty in his own time. Although the distance (the eventual triumph of Liberty) might be great, the point for Tucker was that the journey had begun. (51-7)

Tucker could not be considered a utopian, even though he envisioned a stateless, non-monopolistic society. He clearly understood that Anarchism would not solve all of mankind’s troubles. “[T]here are some troubles from which mankind can never escape. . . . [The Anarchists] never have claimed that liberty will bring perfection; they simply say that its results are vastly preferable to those that follow authority. . . .As a choice of blessings, liberty is the greater; as a choice of evils, liberty is the smaller. Then liberty always, say the Anarchists. No use of force except against the invader; . . . . ” (154-4)

Children are probably always a problem in any society, and that was no less true of Liberty’s time and audience than for ours. The subject of children under Anarchy, and of parental-child responsibility aroused no serious controversy in Liberty until 1895. In 1890, Tucker had chosen to reprint a short, pithy article taken from Freethought, which apparently echoed his own sentiments at the time: that parents have a certain lien upon their children, at least as long as the children lean on them. (160-3) Later pronouncements emphasized that the child, like the adult, has no right to life at all, only the immunity from assault or invasion which all human beings are due. (235-2) In May 1895, Tucker reprinted the letter of an English Individualist, J. Greevz Fisher, which dealt with the question of parental responsibility for the support of the children. The conclusion of both Fisher and Tucker was that, “we must not interfere to prevent neglect, but only to repress positive invasion,” and that “no person, parent or not, may be rightfully compelled to support any helpless being, of whatever age or circumstance, unless he has made that being helpless by some invasive act.” (312-5&8)

Some months later, Tucker reconsidered his position and came to the conclusion that since the mother owns her children, parental invasion is not to be prohibited. Thus, as we have seen, a mother who throws her baby into the fire is not committing an aggression, since she is only handling her property in a way that she sees fit. Tucker maintained that the change which his opinion underwent consisted “simply in the substitution of certainty for doubt as to the non-invasive character of parental cruelty,–a substitution which involves the conclusion that parental cruelty is not to be prohibited, since third parties have not to consider the danger to organisms that are outside the limits of social protection.” (320-5)

The debate about this issue continued for many numbers of Liberty and ended ultimately by Tucker converting all of his critics but one. J. William Lloyd broke with Tucker and Liberty over this issue and refused to associate any longer with those calling themselves Anarchists. Lloyd disputed Tucker’s contention that children were property, while he (Lloyd) maintained that “Each human being owns himself” and that “no human being owns another”. (325-7) According to Tucker, the mother who uses force upon her child invades no body at all. Tucker’s editorial point of view was not clouded by any preconceived notions or any sentimentality. He was quite willing to follow the consequence of his reasoning so long as he could find no flaws in his chain of logic. (322-5) As harsh or heartless as his doctrine may seem, he cautioned that he had the best interest of babies and children at heart as he believed that the observance of his principles would secure to children on the whole greater happiness than they can ever enjoy in any society neglectful of these principles. (320-5)

Another lively topic of interest, which resulted in lengthy discussion, concerned the Anarchistic acceptance of copyright and patents. In the early years of Liberty, when Tucker reviewed Spooner’s “A Letter to Scientists and Inventors, on the Science of Justice, and their Right of Perpetual Property in their Discoveries and Inventions,” Tucker had expressed his disapproval of Spooner’s thesis. He could conceive of nothing more unreasonable than granting to any one the right to monopolize a fact of nature. (47-1) Four years later, in 1888, Tucker commented on the position that Henry George had taken regarding patents and copy-right. The two agreed that patents had no validity but parted company over the legitimacy of copyright; George defending them and Tucker denying them on the basis that discovery can give no right of ownership. (128-4) Later when international copyright agreements became prominent political discussion, Liberty picked up this theme again. Tucker’s opinion was that copyright, in any form and under any limitation, was an injustice. According to Tucker, “there [was] no more justification for the claim of the discoverer of an idea to exclusive use of it than there would have been for a claim on the part of the man who first ‘struck oil’ to ownership of the entire oil region or petroleum product. . . . The central injustice of copyright and patent law is that it compels the race to pay an individual through a long term of years a monopoly price for knowledge that he has discovered today, although some other man or men might, and in many cases very probably would, have discovered it tomorrow.” (173-4) “[F]rom the justice and social necessity of property in concrete things we have erroneously assumed the justice and social necessity of property in abstract things,–that is,–of property in ideas,–with the result of nullifying to a large and lamentable extent that fortunate element in the nature of things, in this case not hypothetical, but real,–namely, the immeasurably fruitful possibility of the use of abstract things by any number of individuals in any number of places at precisely the same time, without in the slightest degree impairing the use thereof by any single individual.” (366-3) “The ‘raison d’être’ of property is found in the very fact that there is no such possibility,–in the fact that it is impossible in the nature of things for concrete objects to be used in different places at the same time.” (366-3)

Perhaps the most interesting part of this copyright-patent controversy was that one of Liberty’s subscribers offered a quotation from Spooner’s Law of Intellectual Property, which resulted in a great outburst from Tucker. The correspondent, A. H. Simpson, rightfully claimed that Spooner had linked together the argument for property in ideas to the justification for property in material objects and land. Tucker called Spooner’s work on Intellectual Property “positively foolish because it is fundamentally foolish,–because, that is to say, its discussion of the acquisition of the right of property starts with a basic proposition that must be looked upon by all consistent Anarchists as obvious nonsense. I quote this basic proposition. ‘The natural wealth of the world belongs to those who first take possession of it. . . . So much natural wealth, remaining unpossessed, as any one can take possession of first, becomes absolutely his property.’ In interpretation of this, Mr. Spooner defines taking possession of a thing as the bestowing of valuable labor upon it, such, for instance, in the case of land, as cutting down the trees or building a fence around it. What follows from this? Evidently that a man may go to a piece of vacant land and fence it off; that he may then go to a second piece and fence that off; then to a third, and fence that off; then to a fourth, a fifth, a hundredth, a thousandth, fencing them all off; that, unable to fence off himself as many as he wishes, he may hire other men to do the fencing for him; and that then he may stand back and bar all other men from using these lands, or admit them as tenants at such rental as he may choose to extract.Now, if this be true, what becomes of the Anarchistic doctrine of occupancy and use as the basis and limit of land ownership?” (180-4)

Tucker was alert enough to understand the implications of Spooner’s argument, and was quite independent enough to reject them. In fact, Tucker claimed that he had taken issue with Spooner on this very point, after he had read Spooner’s pamphlet on the Irish and English landlord question. “In that pamphlet [Revolution, a Reply to Lord Dunraven] Mr. Spooner bases his opposition to Irish and English landlords on the ‘sole’ ground that they or their ancestors took their lands ‘by the sword’ from the original holders. This is plainly stated,–so plainly that I took issue with Mr. Spooner on this point when he had asked me to read the manuscript before its publication. I then asked him whether if Dunraven or his ancestors had found unoccupied the very lands that he now holds, and had fenced them off, he would have any objection to raise against Dunraven’s title to and leasing of these lands. He declared emphatically that he would not. Whereupon I protested that his pamphlet, powerful as it was within its scope, did not go to the bottom of the land question.” (182-6)

As the foregoing comments indicate, Tucker solved the ‘land question’ with the doctrine of occupancy and use as the sole basis and limit of land ownership. This doctrine was based upon the teachings of Josiah Warren who advocated that natural wealth is not property at all and that neither the State nor the individual can set a price upon it without violating the first principle of commercial justice, that cost is the equitable limit of price. (28-2) The Anarchists of this school were definitely against the payment of rent by tenants (the actual occupiers of a given piece of land) to a landlord. Their case was intertwined with their advocacy of removing the restrictions from the business of banking as well as depriving property in land of legal sanction and title. (39-1) The doctrine of occupancy and use evolved from the mid-19th Century theories of land reformer George Henry Evans, who enunciated the principle that each man shall possess the ground he can use and no more. (126-5)

The basis of all the controversy among the Anarchists (and with other social reformers of their time, especially Henry George and the Single-Taxers) was essentially about determining the justness of land holding. Auberon Herbert, the English voluntary taxationist and a contributor to Liberty, insisted on treating the land question as if it were simply a problem of buying and selling, and loaning and borrowing. Tucker cited another English critic of Herbert, who noted, “When we come to the question of the ethical basis of property, Mr. Herbert refers us to ‘the open market’. But this is an evasion. The question is not whether we should be able to sell or acquire ‘in the open market’ anything which we rightfully possess, but how we come into rightful possession.” (172-7)

Mr. Tucker’s most relentless critic (although eventually a convert to the cause) of the occupancy and use doctrine was Stephen Byington. The Anarchistic doctrine of occupancy and use was always expounded in a general sort of way and never really dealt with serious details. The Anarchist doctrine consisted basically of the following provisions as outlined by Tucker: “Occupancy and use is the only title to land in which we will protect you; if you attempt to use land which another is occupying and using, we will protect him against you; if another attempts to use land to which you lay claim, but which you are not occupying and using, we will not interfere with him; but of such land as you occupy and use you are the sole master, and we will not ourselves take from you, or allow anyone else to take from you, whatever you may get out of such land.” (252-3) Tucker further informed Byington that “A man cannot be allowed, merely by putting labor, to the limit of his capacity and beyond the limit of his personal use, into material of which there is a limited supply and the use of which is essential to the existence of other men, to withhold that material from other men’s use; and any contract based upon or involving such withholding is lacking in sanctity or legitimacy as a contract to deliver stolen goods.” (32’1-4) Byington pushed Tucker to answer what would happen to people desirous of renting a room or a building for only a short time, or what would happen to the ownership of buildings when occupiers and users of the land upon which they were built changed, or how vacationers would secure their premises while away? Tucker considered these questions matters of administrative detail, unworthy of discussion unless the attempt be to show that the theory of occupancy and use was unworkable. (331-4)

According to Tucker, the last user and occupier of a given piece of land would have to remove all of his personal property (unless specifically sold to the next occupier-user), otherwise he would lose control of it. “The man who persists in storing his property on another’s premises is an invader, and it ‘is’ his ‘crime’ that alienates control of his property. He is ‘fined one house,’ not ‘for building a house and then letting another man live in it,’ but for invading the premises of another.” (331-4)

For Tucker and his band of 19th Century Anarchists there were four fundamental monopolies, i.e. four modes by which governments granted legal privileges to the few at the great expense to the many. These four monopolies were the land monopoly, the tariff monopoly, the banking monopoly, and the patent and copyright monopoly. All but the tariff question received prominent coverage in Liberty. The tariff question was very clear cut and there was little controversy among Anarchists on this point. They all believed in free trade without restriction. The question of the banking monopoly was not so simple, as the Anarchists differed among themselves, as well as with their opponents, on economic theory. Discussions were carried on about economic problems relating to money and banking, namely, the nature of capital and interest, the basis of the standard of value for money, and the significance of free banking theory to Anarchist doctrine.

In order to understand the Anarchist objection to government money, it is first necessary to distinguish between their political objections and their economic objections. Politically, they were against government compulsion and therefore were against governmental prohibition of any voluntary currency or arrangements that the people might make for and among themselves. The Anarchists rejected the Greenback movement primarily for this reason: “It is greenbackism that Libertyobjects to, for its first and fundamental principle . . . is that it shall be a criminal offense for any individual or association to issue currency for circulation, and that there shall be no money except that issued by the government. . . . Greenbackism is money monopoly in its most extreme form. Free money, on the other hand, means free trade carried into finance, unlimited competition in the business of ‘making money’, and as a result, the utter rout of inferior and usurious currencies by the virtues of the cheapest and the best.” (37-1) Again, politically speaking, the Anarchists objected to laws relating to interest or usury legislation. They continuously opposed “the claim that one has a moral right to take usury, but advocate no method of abolishing it save the removal of all restrictions preventing the free action of natural principles. To attempt to suppress usury by statute is outrageous because tyrannical, and foolish because ineffectual.” (6-1)

Most of Liberty’s adherents believed that the governmental limitations placed on the amount of currency issued and on the choice of media of exchange (generally being restricted to gold and silver) were the cause of financial depressions as well as the cause that interest was charged on loans of money. In a criticism of William Graham Sumner, a Liberty correspondent put forth the proposition that “Interest has no existence in Nature, but is solely due to monopoly, whose parent the State alone is.” (78-4) There were many other discussions in Liberty relating to the value of money and the nature of capital and interest, which generally reduced themselves to the claim that any increase in the supply of money (which would be the result of a regime of free banking) would confer a social benefit and would lead to the disappearance of interest.[4]

Although their economic arguments have not stood the test of time, the political objections to government money were and still are quite valid. Free banking and free money meant the utter absence of restriction upon the issue of all money not fraudulent (80-4) and this was considered to be a cardinal doctrine of Anarchism. (314-5) Tucker was a supporter of the concept of mutual banking, as outlined both by P. J. Proudhon, and his own friend and mentor, Colonel William B. Greene (author of Mutual Banking), by which the monetization of all marketable wealth was made possible. Tucker’s position was that free banking would lead to mutual banking, and that this could only come about through absolute free competition in banking. (314-5 and 69-4) It was Tucker’s belief that mutual banking would be the single greatest step that could possibly be taken in the direction of emancipating labor from poverty. No single liberty was as necessary as the liberty of banking. (314-5)

Liberty’s concern with social unrest and labor was evinced by its discussion of boycotts, unions and the strike. As early as 1886,Tucker elaborated that “any individual may place any condition he chooses, provided the condition be not in itself invasive, upon the doing or not doing of anything which he has a right to do or not do; but no individual can rightfully be a party to any bargain which makes a necessarily invasive condition incumbent upon any of the contracting parties. From which it follows that an individual may rightfully ‘extort’ money from another by ‘threatening’ him with certain consequences, provided those consequences are of such a nature that he can cause them without infringing upon anybody’s rights.” (85-1) On December 3, 1887, Liberty declared; “A man has a right to threaten what he has a right to execute. The boundary-line of justifiable boycott is fixed by the nature of the threat used.” (113-4) Tucker boasted that “prior to these declarations, so far as [he knew], the true foundation and limitation of the right to boycott had never been laid down.” (369-2) In this connection it is also interesting to note that Liberty not only questioned the law against blackmail, but also the laws against libel and slander. Victor Yarros, a close Tucker associate during many of the Liberty years, was “inclined to take the position that all speech ought to be free, and that there can be no invasive quality in mere speech.” (312-2) As a person does not own his own reputation, it merely being a measure of the view held of him by others, then, regardless of the truth or falsity of an alleged libel or slander, no speech, in and of itself, can be invasive. Therefore all libel and slander laws ought to be abolished. (312-2)

Continue Article….

BENJAMIN TUCKER AND HIS PERIODICAL: LIBERTY Part II


CARL WATNER

Baltimore, Maryland

Liberty truly touched on nearly all of the pressing social questions of its era. Space was devoted to articles about free love, marriage and divorce, and sexual relations among men and women. Even the woman suffrage movement came under attack: “Women are human beings, and-consequently have all the natural rights that any human beings can have. They have just as good a right to ‘make laws’ as men have, and no better; AND THAT IS JUST NO RIGHT AT ALL.” (22-4) Mormon polygamy, pornography and postal censorship were also discussed. The Chinese immigration issue was mentioned at times. Freethought was always advocated and the tyranny and cultism of religion nearly always denounced. Tucker proudly reprinted in Liberty and his private press the English Anarchist classics, such as Spooner’s Natural Law, Letter to Thomas Bayard, and A Letter to Grover Cleveland, Auberon Herbert’s A Politician in Sight of Haven, Edmund Burke’s Vindication of Natural Society, Stephen Pearl Andrews’ Science of Society and his discussion of Love, Marriage, and Divorce, as well as quoting excerpts from such writers as Nietzsche, Proudhon, and Stirner. Tucker also made Liberty serve as a forum for publishing and publicizing what he called “advanced literature”, by which he meant “the literature which, in religion and morals, leads away from superstition, which, in politics, leads away from government, and which, in art, leads away from tradition”. (391-4)

Tucker was ambitious and promoted many literary ventures alongside his Anarchist journalism. He had agents in different parts of the world selling Liberty and his other literary wares. He had occasional foreign correspondents, such as Vilfredo Pareto, George Bernard Shaw, and John Henry Mackay, submit their evaluations of Anarchist developments to Liberty’sreaders. He maintained especially close contact with the English Individualist-Anarchist movement and carried on extensive correspondence with the main English figures, such as Auberon Herbert, Wordsworth Donisthorpe, John Badcock, J. H. Levy, and J. Greevz Fisher Other American associates and correspondents of Liberty, such as Henry Appleton, James L. Walker, Joseph Labadie, Victor Yarros, Stephen Byington, Alan and Florence Kelly, John Kelly, Gertrude Kelly, George and Emma Schumm, Francis Tandy, Henry Cohen, and J. Wm. Lloyd formed the often changing nuclei of Tucker’s circle.

Among Tucker’s other notable projects were the publication of Instead of a Book in 1893 and the publication of Liberty in German for a short time. He promoted the formation of an Anarchist Letter Writing Corps under the auspices of Byington and sold and printed sheets filled with Anarchist slogans. He published such books as Zola’s Modern Marriage, Eltzbacher’s Anarchism, and not coincidentally Stirner’s The Ego and His Own. The appearance of this later book was, in Tucker’s opinion, the most notable contribution on behalf of Anarchism that he had made in his 30-year career. (397-1) Stirner was one of the three great Anarchists in 19th century literature, according to Tucker; the other two being Proudhon and Ibsen. He constantly strived to call attention to all three both in Liberty and wider literary circles. (393-11) His New York bookstore eventually came to house a large collection of literature that made for “Egoism in Philosophy, Anarchism in Politics, and Iconoclasm in Art.” (399-2)

Yet for all his boldness and greatness, Tucker and Liberty still leave something to be desired. Did Tucker and his editorial columns in Liberty present a true and consistent version of Anarchy? Of course it is easy to criticize doctrine nearly a century old, but there is much in Tucker that is still valid, as well as much that is still as wrong as the day it was published. In spite of Tucker’s eventual deviations, his life-long emphasis on individual sovereignty and the non-invasive individual is well-founded.

As Libertarians and Anarchists today we might accept the philosophy of egoism that Tucker came to espouse (namely, that might makes right in the absence of mutual agreement). Tucker, himself, recognized the law of equal liberty as being the essence of Anarchism; but his own defense of this social convention seems circular, for it amounts to the statement that we are Anarchists because we are Anarchists. (123-5) Or else we might adopt an alternative defense of Anarchism, such as one which has been outlined by Murray Rothbard in his writings and which hinges on the twin axioms of self-ownership (the absolute right of each person to own his or her own mind and body) and homesteading (the absolute right of each person to own previously unused natural resources which they have in some way occupied or transformed). Tucker’s main challenge to the moralists was to demand to know why one is bound not to injure or invade another. What obligation exists, in the absence of any mutual agreement, to refrain from initiating violence? I think the answer is primarily logical and epistemological in nature. Invasion violates the axioms of self-ownership and homesteading. The invader clearly acts on the axiom that he controls his own life, yet in coercing others he plainly denies it. The resort to violence is a confession of imbecility. Invasion is anti-life and the invader, under the moralist’s theory, loses his own rights (to life and property) to the extent that he has committed an aggression. Thus to answer Tucker, the obligation to refrain from initiating violence is found in the real world around us. Anyone who acts so as to deny the validity of these axioms must sooner or later fail and suffer disaster. As Tucker himself wrote, early in his career, “It is better to suffer great inconveniences than the evils engendered by the violation of individual rights.” (37-4)

Of course, Tucker came to disagree with this position. He called that person who would enforce the drowning man’s contract a person “with justice on the brain, a man who would do justice though the heavens fall.” (344-4) We can only speculate as to whether his rule of expediency would succeed or not, but as applied to individual lives we can make a comparison, which however may be an unfair one. Tucker retired to Europe soon after the fire of 1908 and spent the next 30 years of his life mostly apart from the Anarchist movement. In fact we might say that while Liberty existed Anarchism blazed in glory, but when Tucker retired the flames soon returned to embers. By contrast, Lysander Spooner, definitely a moralist and natural right defender of Anarchism and therefore an opponent of Tucker’s, became steadily more radical and libertarian as he grew older. Each person must be left to judge the effect of historical circumstances on these two individuals, hut their differing philosophies of Anarchism must also be taken into consideration when viewing the outcome of their lives.

To evaluate Tucker in terms of current day libertarian thinking, we would have to say this: We concur with Tucker that no living person owes any other living person any thing in the absence of voluntary agreement; hut tile obligation to refrain from initiating violence is not a positive duty. It is a negative one. It is something which we should not do, not something we should do. We can stand by and see a man murdered or a woman raped (170-4); but we cannot claim that there are times when it is necessary for the Anarchist to become Archist, and to abandon the guiding rule of his life and to coerce the noninvasive individual. (307-3)

NOTES

*All parenthetical footnotes refer to Liberty by Whole Number (issue number) and then page number.

I. Benjamin R. Tucker, Instead of a Book (New York: Haskell House, 1969), p. ix.

2. William 0. Reichert, Partisans of Freedom (Bowling Green, OH: Bowling Green University Popular Press, 1976), p.146.

3. James J. Martin, Men Against the State (Colorado Springs, CO: Ralph Myles, 1970), p.220.

4. Murray N. Rothbard, “The Spooner-Tucker Doctrine: An Economist’s View,” in Egalitarianism as a Revolt Against Nature, and Other Essays(Washington, DC: Libertarian Review Press, 1974), pp.129-33.

The “Criminal” Metaphor in the Libertarian Tradition


 

by Carl Watner

 

   During the last 350 years of constitutional and political struggle in England and the United States, perhaps the most libertarian image to be invoked by political theorists has been the comparison of existing, so-called “legitimate” governments to “organized gangs of banditti, pirates, highwaymen, and robbers.”  Such metaphors have been a constantly recurring theme because the central thrust of libertarian thinking is to oppose any and all forms of invasion against property rights of individuals, in their own persons and in the material objects they have voluntarily acquired.[1]  The Levellers and other opponents of King Charles I and Oliver Cromwell were among the first to challenge the legitimacy of governments as being tyrannical and unjust. The rebels in the American colonies based their revolt against the English Crown on similar grounds of natural law, as outlined in the Declaration of Independence.  Early antislavery radicals in both countries extended their libertarian arguments against slavery and challenged any government that sanctioned a violation of man’s natural rights. Propelled by the logic of the natural law tradition and the events of the American Civil War, Lysander Spooner relied heavily on the “criminal” metaphor to buttress his arguments for individualist anarchism.

   The doctrine of natural liberty is ultimately grounded on two premises which are necessary to the understanding of why governments are “criminal.” By the self-ownership axiom, every individual has an absolute right to his or her own mind and body and the labor thereof; i.e., each person has the right to control that mind and body free of coercive interference. By the homesteading axiom, the first user, the first person who transforms and uses previously unclaimed and unused resources, becomes their absolute owner.[2]  Since people must live in a particular place and their labor must be applied to the material objects around them, they rightfully become the owners of hitherto unclaimed and untransformed natural resources. As defined by libertarianism, freedom is a condition in which a person’s ownership rights of his own body and of his legitimately (according to libertarian principles) acquired material property are neither invaded nor aggressed against.  Crime, in the same context, is an act of aggression against these property rights, either in an individual’s own person or in his materially owned objects.[3]

   Most people would probably support the libertarian rejection of crime in their personal dealings.  They would reject the use of violence, such a murder, theft, kidnapping and extortion. The uniqueness of libertarianism consists in the manner in which this principle of non-aggression is developed.[4]  To the libertarian, it matters neither who commits a crime, nor how many are involved in sanctioning its commission. As one early libertarian said:

Whatever constitutes despotism or cruelty will be continually the same. Considerations of rank and power can never alter the genuine character of human action; if the scymeter is stained with innocent blood, it matters nothing whether the fatal blow was struck by a monarch or a robber.  Oppression and crime are the same in every corner of the globe; the experience of mankind with respect to their characteristics will be constant and uniform; upon those subjects, therefore, the sentence of human understanding will be ever steady and correspondent.[5]

   In other words, for the libertarian, “Crime is crime, aggression against rights is aggression, no matter how many citizens agree to the oppression.” “Even if 90 percent of the people decided to murder or enslave the other 10 percent, this would still be murder and slavery.”[6]  Libertarians unanimously endorse respect for individual rights and they conclude that the only possible crime among men is the violation of individual rights.  The important consideration for libertarians is that individuals are always responsible for a violation of rights. Groups never act; it is always and necessarily individual members of the group who commit crimes in the name of the larger organization.  “Men never lose their individuality. Though in authority, they are still men and act as men. . . . The acts of a government are acts of individuals – of individual men, whose accountability is in no respect changed by their official character.”[7]

   The natural law tradition affirms the libertarian attitude towards crime and aggression.  The philosophy of natural law defends the rational dignity of the human individual.  It provides the only basis on which the individual may rightfully criticize, in word and deed, every institution and social structure which is incompatible with the universally held moral principles of natural law.[8]  In his discourse on “The People’s Ancient and Just Liberties,” William Penn outlined the contents of the natural law, which he considered fundamental and immutable:

By [these] we understand such laws as enjoin men to be just, honest, virtuous, to do no wrong, to kill, rob, deceive, prejudice none; but to do as one would be done unto; to cherish good and to terrify wicked men; in short, Universal Reason, which are not subject to any revolution, because no emergency, time or occasion, can ever justify a suspension of their execution, much less their utter abrogation.[9]

   Under this interpretation, no man-made law which conflicts with the natural law of honest dealing and non-aggression is considered binding. An unjust law binds no one, according to the libertarian, since a law higher than that of government holds the individual responsible for his actions.  One of the Leveller leaders in the struggle against Charles I thought that:

the Law taken from its original reason and end is made a shell without a kernel, a shadow without a substance, a carcass without life; for the equity and reason thereof is that which gives it a legal being and life, and makes it authoritative and binding.  If this be not granted, injustice may be a Law, tyranny may be a Law, lust, will, pride, covetousness and what not? may be Laws.

In his opinion:

Had there been the letter of the Law directly against me, yea if it were contradicted by the equity of the Law, I had not been at all bound thereto, except to oppose it: for the Letter if it control and overthrow the Equity, it is to be so controlled and overthrown itself, upon peril of treason to the Equity, and the Equity to be preserved is the only thing legally obligatory and binding.[10]

   An eighteenth-century libertarian summed up this point of view when he declared that ” ‘the Powers that be’ cannot bind the conscience when they exceed just limits, any more than the threats of lawless Banditti” can succeed in demanding obedience.[11]

   One of the basic corollaries of libertarian thinking is that it is wrong to engage in aggression against non-aggressors. According to libertarian doctrine, an aggressor, to the extent he invades another’s person or property, loses his own individual rights.  The person so invaded may resort to violence in self-defense.  In nearly all times and places, this defensive principle has been recognized as the right of the individual against the criminal.  It has also been used as the only true basis for revolution against unjust and tyrannical governments. Richard Overton, who was arbitrarily arrested and imprisoned by the House of Lords in 1647, argued that:

in pursuance of the just and necessary defensive opposition we may lawfully, and are in Conscience bound to destroy, kill and slay the otherwise irresistible enemy for our own preservation and safety, whether they attack us in our lives, our Laws, or our liberties: And against. the justice of this defensive principle,, no degrees, Orders, or titles among men can or may prevail. [12]

   In his struggle with the government, Overton claimed that government laws which were consistent with natural law could be turned against the government itself.  Having been arrested without a valid, legal warrant, he argued:

For if assaulting men’s persons, invading and entering their houses, and taking what of their goods such men please [as had happened in his own case] and that all by a force of Arms, be simply a Magisterial Act, then all thieves and murderers are justified thereby; for their violence is without any Magisterial Authority appearing; but by the Law it is therefore adjudged theft and murder, etc.[13]

Under such circumstances, “the persons invaded and assaulted by such open force of Arms may lawfully arm themselves, fortify their houses (which are their Castles in the judgment of the Law) against them, yea, disarm, beat, wound, repress, and kill them in their just necessary defense of their own persons, houses, goods, wives and families, and not be guilty of the least offense.”[14]

   One hundred years later, Granville Sharp used similar reasoning to denounce the unlawfulness of the press gang.  Those who resisted the impressment officers, Sharp maintained, were acting legally in defense of their own rightful freedom and against unjust violence. Such resisters were

not deemed guilty of murder, even if they kill the assailants, provided the killing be inevitable in their defense; and that they cannot otherwise maintain their rights.  Nay men are not only justified in defending themselves with force of arms, but may also legally defend and rescue any other persons whatever that are attacked or oppressed by unlawful violence.[15]

   William Allen, a critic of Cromwell, in his written attack on the Protectorate, beautifully summed up the complementarity of the libertarian principles of self-defense and non-aggression. He pointed out that the “law of Nature gives every man to oppose Force with Force, and to make Justice where he finds none.”[16]  In this pamphlet, Killing No Murder, the author advocated the assassination of the tyrant Cromwell and made these highly libertarian pronouncements:

For what can be more absurd in Nature and contrary to all common sense, than to call him Thief and kill him that comes alone or with a few to rob me; and to call him Lord Protector and obey him that robs me with regiments and troops? As if to rove with 2 or 3 ships were to be a Pirate, but with 50 an Admiral?  But if it be the number of Adherents only, not the cause, that makes the difference between a Robber and a Protector: I will that number were defined, that we might know where the Thief ends and the Prince begins.  And be able to distinguish between a Robbery and a Tax.  But sure no Englishman can be ignorant that it is his Birthright to be Master of his own estate; and that none can command any part of it but by his own grant and consent, either made expressly by himself, or Virtually by a Parliament.  All other names are mere Robberies in other names. . . .To rob, to extort, to murder Tyrants falsely called to govern, and to make a desolation, they call to settle peace: in every assessment we are robbed, the excise is robbery. the customs is robbery, and without doubt, whenever tis prudent, tis always lawful to kill the Thieves whom we can bring to no other justice.  And not only lawful, and to do ourselves right, but Glorious and to deliver mankind, to free the world of that common Robber, that universal Pirate under whom and for whom these lesser beasts prey. [17]

   Two hundred years later these same sentiments were expressed by a radical abolitionist in a slightly different context.  Henry Clarke Wright, an associate of Garrison in the abolition struggle, had exactly the same attitude towards government:

States and Nations are to be regarded as we regard combinations of men to pick pockets, to steal sheep, to rob on the road, to steal men, to range over the sea as pirates – only on a larger and more imposing scale. When men steal, rob and murder as states and nations, it gives respectability to crime – the enormity of their crimes is lost sight of, amid the imposing number that commit them, and amid the glitter and pomp of equipage. The little band of thieves is scorned and hunted down as a felon; the great, or governmental band of thieves, is made respectable by numbers, and their crimes cease to be criminal and hateful in proportion to the number combined to do them.  If a community of ten commit piracy, they are all hung, and a man is made infamous if he joins this little band of pirates; but if a community of 25,000,000, called Great Britain or Austria, do the same deed, it is all right, and Christian, and heaven-ordained, and a man is made infamous if he refuses to join this great band of pirates.  Such reasoning is most false.  I cast it from me.  I can no more join a community of 25,000,000, that exists by plunder and murder, than I can join one composed of ten. [18]

   Almost all of the antislavery radicals of the late-eighteenth and nineteenth centuries were repelled by the idea that the local law of slave communities could establish a condition which infringed upon basic human rights. If there were no eternal laws which applied equally to all men, then any kind of banditry might be cloaked in legal forms.[19]  If governments were allowed to justify slavery and the slave trade, then they could justify any form of crime.  In order to reject government sanction of slavery, these radical libertarians had to establish a theory of proprietary justice independent of government law and not subject to re-definition by government.  They did this by referring back to the natural law tradition and by accepting the self-ownership axiom.

   Thomas Paine, an early supporter of the American Revolution, was a critic of slavery and the slave trade.  Paine equated slavery with man-stealing and kidnapping.  For him, the buying and selling of slaves was not an ordinary commercial transaction. The equation of slaves with stolen property had radical implications for Paine:

Such men [the purchasers of slaves] may as well join with a known band of robbers, buy their ill-gotten goods, and help on the trade; ignorance is no more pleadable in one case than in the other; the sellers plainly own how they obtain them [the slaves].  But none can lawfully buy without evidence that they are not concurring with men-stealers; and as the true owner has a right to reclaim his goods that were stolen, and sold; so the slave, who is the proper owner of his freedom, has a right to reclaim it, however often sold.[20]

 

   Since slaves were “stolen” men, it was a simple step to equate slave traders with pirates and robbers.  Paine enunciated a dual libertarian argument.  Each slave, being a person, was entitled to self-ownership rights.  Moreover, since every owner could rightfully recover stolen property that belonged to him, regardless of how many times over it had been sold, a slave could legitimately reclaim his freedom at any time.  A thief could never divest the rightful owner of property of his title, even if an innocent purchaser bought the stolen property in good faith.  In this fashion, the early radicals made a telling case for justice in property titles.

   Also, as Paine pointed out, when “innocent” purchasers were “buying” men, it was impossible that they claim ignorance as an excuse. That the claim of a slave to his freedom was necessarily stronger than the claim of an owner whose chattels were stolen was pointed out by Samuel Hopkins in 1776:

If your neighbor buys a horse . . . of any thief who stole it from you, while he had no thought it was stolen, would you not think you had a right to demand your horse of your neighbor, and pronounce him very unjust if he should refuse to deliver him to you. . . ?  And have not your (African] servants as great a right to themselves, to their liberty, as you have to your stolen horse?  They have been stolen and sold, and when you bought them, in your own wrong, you had much more reason to think they were stolen than he who bought your horse.[21]

Hopkins also compared slave traders to pirate’s, much to their discomfort:

It is granted by all, that common pirates may be punished by the laws of any state, when apprehended, wherever or in whatever part of the world their crimes were committed. . . .The slave trader who buys and sells his fellow men, by which traffic he is the death of many, and of reducing others to the most miserable bondage during life, is as really an enemy to mankind as the pirate, and violates common law, which is, or ought to be, the law of all nations, and is guilty of crimes of greater magnitude, exercises more inhumanity and cruelty, sheds more blood and plunders more, and commits greater outrages against his fellow men than most of those who are called pirates.  In short, if any men deserve the name of pirates, these [slave traders] ought to be considered in the first and highest class of them.[22]

   Perhaps the most vigorous of the antislavery radicals was Henry Clarke Wright. He was one of the few who extended his argument for abolition of slavery to include abolition of the state that sanctioned slavery. Wright saw that if he were successful in using natural law to nullify state-sanctioned slavery, then he could, on similar grounds, attack other forms of state tyranny, such as conscription and taxation. No government that upheld such injustices could be legitimate in his eyes.  In his most radical pamphlet, No Rights, No Duties, he consistently used the “criminal” metaphor to make his points against governments and slavery.  “The thesis he presented was simple. Slaves have no obligation at all to their masters, who good or bad, deserve no more respect or consideration than a gang of pirates or kidnappers.  Freedom must be won by the slaves themselves in alliance with their sympathizers among white freemen – by all and every means that the latter would feel justified in using against ‘burglars, incendiaries, and highway robbers’, who might threaten them.”[23] Wright argued that:

   The individual pirate, as a pirate, has no rights.  No laws nor constitutions of human device can create for and secure to him any rights; and if they attempt to do so, it is the duty of all to ignore such rights, and trample such enactments beneath their feet.  This is true of all who hold and use human beings as chattels.[24]

   A corporate body of pirates, though called a State or nation, can have no rights.  It is an organized, systematized banditti, and any individual or State is authorized to destroy it.  So, a corporate body of slave-holders, though called Virginia, Maryland, Kentucky, or Missouri, is a self-incorporated body of marauders, and as such, any man, or set of men is authorized to destroy it.[25]

   All efforts to compromise with slavery and those who embody it, for any cause, is to compound with rape, robbery, and piracy: is to complot with “the sum of all villany.”. . . It is the sacred duty of the people and States of the North to side with the slaves. As in a conflict between a band of highway robbers or pirates, and those whom they would plunder and murder, it is their duty to side with the wronged and the outraged.[26]

.

   Wright claimed that the basis of every governmental organization in America was the right of every person to defend his life, liberty, and property. This was the essence of the American Revolution and was embodied in the Declaration of Independence.  The supporters of the Constitution were inconsistent if they refused to allow slaves to exercise this right of self – defense.  “If all highway robbers, midnight assassins, or pirates, or all organized bands of such marauders and desperadoes, have forfeited all rights, and if any man or set of men has a right to exterminate them, then . . . slaveholders and slaveholding States [have] forfeited all their rights, and the people and States of the North have a right to exterminate them on their own territory, or wherever they may exist.”[27]  The motto that Wright chose for his title, No Rights, No Duties, meant that “no slaveholder, as such, has any rights, and that no man owes him any duties, except to compel him to cease to steal and enslave men, and to let the oppressed go free.”[28]

   All of Wright’s reasoning was in accord with natural law thinking about the subject.  A hundred years earlier, another natural law lawyer, Thomas Rutherforth, had written in his Institutes of Natural Law that:

A band of robbers or a company of pirates may be in fact united to one another by compact; and may have stipulated with one another in this compact to be directed by the common understanding and to act by the common force for their general benefit.  But they are still by the law of nature only a number of unconnected individuals; and consequently in the view of the law of nations, they are not considered as one co1lective body or public person.  For the compact. by which they united themselves, is void: because the matter of it is unlawful.  The individuals, that form themselves into a civil society, are bound by their social compact to pursue and maintain a common benefit: but this common benefit is such an one, as is intended to be consistent with the obligations which they are naturally under to the rest of mankind.  Whereas the common benefit, which a band of robbers or a company of pirates propose to themselves, consists in doing harm to the rest of mankind.[29]

   Although some natural law thinkers have placed credence in a so-called social contract theory, others have delved behind the origins of government. The very fact that all governments are coercive is prima facie evidence that they originated in and perpetuate themselves by violence. Thomas Paine pointed out that

it is more than probable, could we take off the dark covering of antiquity and trace them [kings and their government] to their first rise, we should find the first of them nothing better than the principal ruffian of some restless gang, whose savage manners or preeminence in subtility obtained him the title of chief among plunderers; and who by increasing in power, and extending his depredations, overawed the quiet and defenceless, to purchase their safety by frequent contributions.[30]

   Lysander Spooner, another great nineteenth-century radical who was probably the only constitutional lawyer to evolve into an individualist anarchist, confirmed Paine’s suspicions about the origins of government. In his pamphlet. Natural Law or the Science of Justice, which was subtitled, “A Treatise on Natural Law, Natural Justice, Natural Rights. Natural Liberty, and Natural Society; Showing That All Legislation Whatsoever is an Absurdity, A Usurpation, and a Crime,” Spooner wrote:

   All the great governments of the world – those now existing as well as those that have passed away – have been of this character.  They have been mere bands of robbers, who have associated for purposes of plunder, conquest, and the enslavement of their fellow men.  And their laws, as they have ca1led them, have only been such agreements as they have found it necessary to enter into, in order to maintain their organizations, and act together in plundering and enslaving others, and in securing to each his agreed share of the spoils.

   All these laws have had no more real obligation than have the agreements which brigands, bandits, and pirates find it necessary to enter into with each other, for the more successful accomplishment of their crimes, and the more peaceable division of their spoils.[31]

   According to the libertarian view, all governments exhibit at least two fundamentally aggressive, and therefore criminal, attributes.  First, governments obtain their revenue by means of taxation; that is, by compulsory levy. Taxation is contrary to the basic principles of libertarianism because it involves aggression against non-aggressive citizens who refuse to pay their taxes.  It makes no difference that the government offers goods and services in return for the tax money.  What matters is that taxation is not voluntary.  Secondly, all governments presume to establish compulsory monopolies of defense services (police, courts, and law code) over certain geographical areas.  Even if governments were financed by “voluntary” contributions, their second aggressive feature would remain.  Individual property owners who prefer not to subscribe at all or to subscribe to another defense company within that area are not permitted to do so.  Government, apart from individual outlaws, is the only organization in society that can use its funds to commit violence against its subjects.  Only the government is empowered to aggress against the property rights of its citizens, whether to extract revenue or to impose its own moral code.[32]  This analysis leads directly to the two most important questions of political philosophy: What distinguishes the edicts of the State from the commands of a bandit gang? and Can taxation be defined in such a way as to make it different from robbery?[33]  In his appendix on “Taxation” which appeared in his book Trial by Jury, Spooner answered these questions thus:

To take a man’s property without his consent is robbery; and to assume his consent where no consent is given, makes the taking none the less robbery.  If it did not, the highwayman has the same right to assume a man’s consent to part with his purse, that any other man, or body of men, can have.  And his assumption would afford as much moral justification for his robbery as does a like assumption, on the part of the government, for taking a man’s property without his consent. The government’s pretense of protecting him, as an equivalent for the taxation, affords no justification.  It is for himself to decide whether he desires such protection as the government offers him. If he does not desire it, or does not bargain for it, the government has no more right, than any other insurance company to impose it upon him, or make him pay for it.[34]

 

   Until the American Civil War proved him wrong, Spooner had believed that the American government and Constitution were based on the “consent of the governed.”  Although slaveholders were themselves in violation of natural law doctrine, Spooner maintained that they still had the right to secede from the Union.  To be taxed against their will and to be held to membership in an association to which they did not wish to belong was contrary to the principles of a voluntary government. In 1867, in the second part of his pamphlet series, No Treason, Spooner wrote that there is no middle ground between taxation and consent:

Either “taxation without consent is robbery,” or it is not. If it is not, then any number of men, who choose, may at any time associate; call themselves a government; assume absolute authority over all weaker than themselves; plunder them at will, and kill them if they resist it.  If, on the other hand, “taxation without consent is robbery,” it necessarily follows that every man who has not consented to be taxed, has the same natural right to defend his property against a tax gatherer, that he has to defend it against a highwayman.[35]

   In Part VI of No Treason we find Spooner’s analysis of the State as a robber group, which “is perhaps the most devastating ever written”[36]:

   It is true that the theory of our Constitution is, that all taxes are paid voluntarily; that our government is a mutual insurance company, voluntarily entered into by the people with each other; that each man makes a free and purely voluntary contract with all others who are parties to the Constitution, to pay so much money for so much protection, the same as he does with any other insurance company; and that he is just as free not to be protected, and not to pay any tax, as he is to pay a tax, and be protected.

   But this theory of our government is wholly different from the practical fact.  The fact is that the government, like a highwayman, says to a man: “Your money, or your life.”  And many, if not most, taxes are paid under the compulsion of that threat.

   The government does not, indeed, waylay a man in a lonely place, spring upon him from the roadside, and holding a pistol to his head, proceed to rifle his pockets.  But the robbery is none the less a robbery on that account; and it is far more dastardly and shameful.

   The highwayman takes solely upon himself the responsibility, danger, and crime of his own act.  He does not pretend that he has any rightful claim to your money, or that he intends to use it for your own benefit. He does not pretend to be anything but a robber.  He has not acquired impudence enough to profess to be merely a “protector,” and that he takes men’s money against their will, merely to enable him to “protect” those infatuated travellers, who feel perfectly able to protect themselves, or do not appreciate his peculiar system of protection.  He is too sensible a man to make such professions as these.  Furthermore, having taken your money, he leaves you, as you wish him to do.  He does not persist in following you on the road, against your will; assuming to be your rightful “sovereign,” on account of the “protection” he affords you.  He does not keep “protecting” you, by commanding you to bow down and serve him; by requiring you to do this, and forbidding you to do that; by robbing you of more money as often as he finds it for his interest or pleasure to do so; and by branding you as a rebel, a traitor, an enemy to your country, and shooting you down without mercy, if you dispute his authority, or resist his demands.  He is too much of a gentleman to be guilty of such impostures, and insults, and villainies as these. In short, he does not, in addition to robbing you, attempt to make you either his dupe or his slave.

   The proceedings of those robbers and murderers, who call themselves “the government,” are directly the opposite of these of the single highwayman.

   In the first place, they do not, like him, make themselves individually known; or, consequently, take upon themselves personally the responsibility of their acts.  On the contrary, they secretly (by secret ballot) designate some one of their number to commit the robbery in their behalf, while they keep themselves practically concealed.[37]

Spooner claimed that the secret ballot makes a secret government, “and a secret government is a secret band of robbers and murderers.”[38] The secret ballot was in effect, “a tacit understanding between A, B, and C, that they will, by ballot, depute D as their agent, to deprive” men of their property.  Such a tacit understanding in no way empowers D to act for them and “he is none the less a robber, tyrant, murderer, because he claims to act as their agent, than he would if he avowedly acted on his own responsibility.”[39]

   It was Spooner’s contention that no government could excuse itself from a violation of the individual’s right to property and person. He was appalled by the government’s resort to conscription during the Civil War, and by its issuance of legal tender notes.  The legal tender decisions of the Supreme Court especially upset Spooner because they were entirely contrary to his theory of justice and property. In his own satirical way, he recommended the practices of the Supreme Court to all bandit gangs:

   If a company of bandits were to seize a man’s property for their own uses, and give him their note, promising to pay him out of their future robberies, the transaction would not be considered a very legitimate one. But it would be intrinsically just as legitimate as is the one which the Supreme Court sanctions on the part of Congress [in regard to the legal tender decisions].

   . . . Banditti have not usually kept supreme courts of their own, to legalize either their robberies, or their promises to pay for past robberies, out of the proceeds of their future ones. Perhaps they may now take a lesson from our Supreme Court.[40]

   The Lincoln administration also sought loans from abroad to bolster its sagging finances. Spooner was upset to discover that people would entrust their savings to such a government for such purposes as subduing the Southerners.

This business of lending blood-money is one of the most thoroughly sordid, cold-blooded and criminal that was ever carried on, to any considerable extent, amongst human beings.  It is like lending money to slave-traders, or common robbers and pirates, to be repaid out of their plunder. And the men who loan money to governments, so-called, for the purpose of enabling the latter to rob, enslave, and murder their people, are among the greatest villains that the world has ever seen. And they as much deserve to be hunted and killed (if they cannot be otherwise got rid of) as any slave-traders, robbers, or pirates that ever lived.[41]

   Thus ends this survey of the “criminal” metaphor in libertarian thinking.  Anyone who accepts the libertarian principles of self-ownership and homesteading and seriously reasons out their implications will eventually realize that the State is criminal.  As has been pointed out, the mere fact that the State must exist by violence is sufficient evidence to brand it invasive.  We need always fear and defend ourselves from the random violence of the lone criminal; but more importantly, we must never forget that the institutionalized violence committed upon us by the State is actually our greatest threat.

NOTES

 

1. See, for example, Murray Rothbard, For a New Liberty (New York: Macmillan Co., 1973), p.47.

2. Ibid., pp. 26, 35.

3. Ibid., p. 43. 

4. See Walter Block, “Introduction,” Defending the Undefendable  (New York: Fleet Press, 1976).

5. Tunis Wortman, A Treatise Concerning Political Enquiry and the Liberty of the Press (n.p., printed by George Forman, 1800), p. 60.

6. Rothbard, For a New Liberty, p. 53.

7. William Hosmer, The Higher Law, in Its Relation to Civil Government (1852; reprint ed., New York: Negro University Press, 1969), p. 53.

8. John Wild, Plato’s Modern Enemies and the Theory of Natural Law (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1953), p. 176.

9. William Penn, Selected Works (London: James Philips. 1670), 1:112-13.

10. Richard Overton, The Commoner’s Complaint (1646), pp. 6, 12. Copy obtained from the Henry E. Huntington Library, San Marino, California.

11. Granville Sharp, A Declaration of the People’s Natural Right to a Share in the Legislature, Which Is the Fundamental Principle of the British Constitution of State (1774; reprint ed., New York: Da Capo Press, 1971), p. 240.

12. Overton, An Appeale from the Degenerate Representative Body (1647), in Don M. Wolfe, ed., Leveller Manifestoes of the Puritan Revolution(New York: Thomas Nelson and Sons, 1944), pp. 177-78.

13. Overton, A Defiance Against All Arbitrary Usurpations (1646), p. 10. Copy from the Huntington Library.

14. Overton, An Arrow Against All Tyrants (1646), p. 9. Copy from the Huntington Library. It was also reprinted by the Rota Press, University of Exeter, England, 1976.

15. Sharp, An Address to the People of England: Being the Protest of a Private Person Against Every Suspension of Law That Is Liable to Injure and Endanger Personal Security (London, 1778), p. 71. Copy from Duke University Library.

16. William Allen, Killing No Murder (London, 1659), p. 9. Copy from Huntington Library.

17. Ibid., p.8.

18. Letter from Henry Clarke Wright to The Liberator (c. March 1844), in Truman Nelson, , ed., Documents of Upheaval (New York: Hill and Wang, 1966), p. 196.

19. David Brion Davis, The Problem of Slavery in Western Culture (lthaca, N. Y .: Cornell University Press, 1966), pp. 416-17.

20. Thomas Paine, “African Slavery in America,” in The Works of Thomas Paine, ed. William Vander Weyde, Patriot’s Edition (New Rochelle, N. Y .: Thomas Paine Historical Association, 1925), 2:5. See also Davis, The Problem of Slavery in the Age of Revolution (lthaca, N. Y .: Cornell University Press. 1975), p. 269.

21. Samuel Hopkins, Timely Articles on Slavery (reprint ed., Miami, Fla.: Mnemosyne Publishing, 1%9), p. 575.

22. Ibid. , p. 622.

23. Peter Brock, Pacifism in the U.S. (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1968), p. 684.

24. Henry C. Wright, No Rights, No Duties (Boston: printed for the author, 1860), p. 3. Copy from Library of Congress,

25. Ibid.. P. 4.

26. Ibid., p. 15.

27. Ibid., p. 18.

28. Ibid., p. 25.

29. Thomas Rutherforth, Institutes of Natural Law (1744), 3rd ed. (Whitehall: printed for William Young, bookseller, Philadelphia, 1799), 2;481-82.

30. Thomas Paine, Common Sense, pt. 2, “Of Monarchy and Hereditary Succession.”

31. Lysander Spooner, Natural Law; or the Science of Justice (Boston; A. Williams, 1882), chap. 3, sec. 2, p. 18. Spooner’s works have been collected by Charles Shively, ed., The Collected Works of Lysander Spooner (Weston, Mass.; M & S Press, 1971).

32. Rothbard, For a New Liberty, pp. 49-50.

33. Ibid., p. 55.

34. Spooner, An Essay on Trial by Jury (Boston: J. P. Jewett & Co., 1852), app., “Taxation,” p.223.

35. Spooner, No Treason, pt. 2 (Boston; by the author, 1867), sec. 7, p. 13.

36. Rothbard, For a New Liberty, p. 55.

37. Spooner, No Treason, pt. 6 (Boston; by the author, 1870), sec. 3, pp. 12-14.

38. lbid., sec. 8, p. 29.

39. lbid. , sec. 8, pp. 27-28.

40. Spooner, A Letter to Grover Cleveland, on His False Inaugural Address, the Usurpations and Crimes of Lawmakers and Judges, and the Consequent Poverty, Ignorance, and Servitude of the People (Boston: Benj. R. Tucker, 1886), sec. 20, p. 70. 41. Spooner, No Treason. pt. 6, sec. 18, p. 50.

Aggression is Wrong


By Robert LeFevre — (1911 – 1986)


A principle is an unvarying rule of action which has always been true and which permits of no exception.If one conjectures about the early days of the human race, one is impressed at once by the early brutality of homo sapiens.

There are few now who care to dissent when it is pointed out that man’s origins were coarse and cruel and that the movement toward civilization assisted in de-brutalizing and making more human and more tractable the peculiar entity we call brother.

One is left to marvel, in view of the nature of early men, that any progress was made at all. Force was almost the universal rule. And as every gentle modern knows, when force is directed against you, the easiest thing in the world is to reply in kind.

It can be suggested that the use of force and aggression was so common at one time among our species, that had every act of violence, inflicted by one against another of the race, been repaid in kind, it is doubtful if a single specimen would still be alive.

Somehow, somewhere, deep within our unknown past, someone got the idea of not retaliating in kind. Our survival to this date unquestionably rests upon that idea.

Nor is it necessary to explore human prehistory to establish this. It is only necessary to explore our history for the past several thousand years to note that war, murder, torture, beating, cruelties and the like, were inflicted so generally over so wide an area, that had each act of this kind been considered a debt to be paid, the blood feud would have wiped out the human race.

So, sometime a very long time ago, there were those of our species who, already partly civilized, set an example by striving to mind their own business and being unwilling to descend to the brutal level of those who engaged in aggression as a means to an end.

In the 20th century it appears that this lesson is going to have to be learned all over again. It appears that a new wave of brutality is poised, ready to sweep the globe. And in the main, normal human reaction is such that we prepare for aggression in an aggressive manner. We counsel one another that if “the other fellow” becomes brutal, he may yet learn brutality from us. Our retaliation will out-brutalize his brutality. And let that give him pause! This is the logic of the cave-man.

We are not suggesting that we should become supine and docile and the ready prey of the aggressor who is prepared to proceed in a cruel and inhuman manner. But we are suggesting that it is time we made use of our intellectual facilities rather than relying wholly on our ability to descend into the gutter to match a degraded opponent at that level.

In logic we have long understood that two wrongs do not make a right. And thus, if one individual inflicts a wrong upon another, the response is scarcely in keeping with logic if the victim of attack turns about and victimizes his attacker. What we must be willing to do, it would appear, is to act in such a way that the first act of aggression is forestalled. Aggression is always wrong. There can be no justification for it in any circumstances.

But our problem is not to control the other fellow so that he does as we wish. The “other fellow” controls himself and we cannot. We may not approve of the way he does it, but we cannot substitute our control for his.

Our problem is to control ourselves so that we become masters of the situation. We must concern ourselves with the moral recognition that we must not join the ranks of the aggressors, even for what may appear to be cause.

Governments, by their nature, are invariably agencies of aggression. This is our excuse for having them; they can be employed against the “other fellow” to compel him to provide the money for our schemes, to compel him to do or not to do in accordance with our wishes.

But to the degree that we rely on government, which is our agency of aggression, to this degree do we reject civilization. If we can learn to recognize the merit of non-aggression, and hence of voluntary action, we will begin to employ the market place to a fuller degree and ultimately we may be able to abandon government reliance totally.

The dawn of future ages depends upon man’s ability to rely on moral principles and to reject aggression.
Customs and Morals

Some people experience confusion over the differences between moral law and custom. In many a college classroom and elsewhere there is a tacit agreement that these are merely two words to express a single idea. It is conceived that customs and morals are the same thing and that what a given people do is, in fact, what that people believe is the correct and moral thing to do.

It will be argued, for example, that cannibals are every bit as moral as non-cannibals. The only thing which differentiates cannibals from non-eaters of human flesh is custom. Cannibals have a morality, we are told, which permits them to practice dietary habits which are repulsive to us. But this does not make them immoral, it merely serves to indicate that there are no moral laws as such. Custom controls all and morality (a widely shared opinion) sets the pattern for whatever the custom will be.

We are in sharp disagreement. We believe there are moral laws as absolute and final as the laws of physics or chemistry. In the latter case, the laws have always existed but until very recent years men knew little or nothing about them. Man’s ignorance in these fields did not eliminate these laws. They existed always. Through science and study, through experiment, exchange of thought and deep concentration, man has managed to learn some of the laws in nature’s handbook.

We believe the same is true of moral law. Such law has always existed. It rests upon the nature of things as they are. Man may not know what moral laws actually exist. But if he will study and observe and remember, he can learn that because things are the way they are, certain behavior patterns are correct and proper and others are not.

Cannibals are merely human beings who have not studied their lessons. Were they capable of abstract or deductive reasoning they would quickly discover that the practice of cannibalism is destructive of their own self-interest.

Morals and customs are not the same thing. Throughout the world most human beings have a sense of moral rightness which exists at a higher level than the customs they have adopted. In fact, one can discern the progress of the species in an upward direction as one follows the history of man from earliest times and observes his improved customs. Rarely, if ever, has any group of men been able to make their customs and their moral ideals coalesce at all points.

Consider the United States today. Morally, we inveigh against theft. We have laws to punish the thief or the robber. We try to teach our children the validity of property rights and constantly remind them they must not take for themselves things which belong to someone else. Customarily, we will punish the person who steals, either when he is a child and parental responsibility is invoked, or when he is an adult, and the state authority is called upon.

In these two instances we have tried to make morality and custom the same. But this in no way establishes that custom and morality are identical. For in the United States, to a very real degree, nearly everyone practices theft of a different kind. Morally, we don’t approve of it. Customarily, we practice it.

We are referring here to legalized theft, committed through the offices of an agency of plunder and looting called government.

Although legalized stealing and illegal stealing can be defined in precisely the same terms, and hence would be contrary to our moral sensibilities, the fact is that, like the cannibals, we have not studied our lessons.

The family which subsists on a government dole is subsisting on stolen money. Yet this family will have no qualms in the matter. The persons receiving a monthly cut in public loot accept this as their due. Yet, such a family will possibly have very strong opposition to an act of illegal theft, even as they share in the immorality of general and public theft. At this point, custom and morality do not agree. The former trails behind the latter.

Yet we can learn, if we do our homework, that like cannibalism, the practice of public theft works to our undoing. In spite of the arguments of fear, it is always wrong to steal and legal justification does not make right that which is morally wrong.
Ends and Means are Different

Consistency, ah, consistency! This is the cornerstone of logic.

All knowledge rests upon our ability to match things which are alike and to disassociate things which are not alike.

Here we have four major elements. Things that are identical; things that are similar; things that are dissimilar; things that are opposites. Our ability to analyze things correctly and to match them correctly or reject the matching is the cornerstone of reason.

Let us take the philosophy of freedom.

We hold that the concept of freedom rests upon the means and the methods to be employed to attain that which we wish to attain. Freedom is not so much a goal as it is a direction to be taken in an effort to reach our various and divergent goals.

Thus, any study of freedom must concern itself primarily with a methodology rather than an objective.

Here are six desirable things we would like to see everyone have.

  1. Good education.
  2. A large income.
  3. The best medical care.
  4. A comfortable home.
  5. Ample food and clothing.
  6. Protection of life and property.

Every one of these things is good. Surely, no one will dispute that. But if we believe in freedom it isn’t the ends alone that concern us. We must also be concerned with the means taken to secure these ends. For if, in our blindness, we do not count the cost of the things we want, we will, perhaps, achieve something for ourselves while making it impossible for someone else to have the same tangible goods that we want.

This is the folly of turning to the government to provide us with the ends we seek.

For instance, if we call upon the government to provide good education for everyone, we are actually asking that everyone be assessed in some way to pay for that education.

Let us see if this is justified. Whereas we have assumed that all six of the ends named are desirable ends, they are not desired in equal intensity by everyone. Some persons may not be particularly interested in education, but may be far more interested in the best possible medical care obtainable.

Surely, this is legitimate. We do not expect everyone to want everything in precisely the same way at the same time, do we?

But we are beginning with education. So we institute a general tax on everyone so that schools will be provided and everyone will have education. Or at least everyone will have a tax-paid opportunity to spend a certain amount of time in school. These are not the same things.

But what have we done in the process?

We have impaired the ability of those persons who put medical care first in their own scale of values, to get the medical care they want and could otherwise afford. We have substituted our scale of values for theirs.

Not only is this not justified, we have actually injured everyone to some degree who doesn’t happen to agree with us about the primacy of education.

This is what happens when we confuse ends with means. Because we hold that formal education is good, we have decided that a coercive and corruptive means of obtaining that end is good.

Precisely the same rules can be applied with the other five ends we listed. And after that, we could list the thousands upon thousands of desirable ends all of us would like to achieve.

Every time we use the wrong means to obtain a good end, we impair the ability of others to get the things they want out of life. Is this consistency? Is it wise? Is it even feasible?

Somewhere the end must be reached in the employment of wrong means.
Take Time for Truth

There is always enough time for truth.

Many men do not think so. They fancy that they will make greater gains if they assume there is no time for truth and, therefore, that something else must be believed. There isn’t time to think things through to the right answer; we must act and act now.

If one can dispassionately view the progress of the human race, he can see men hurrying and scurrying about, down through the ages, muddling and bungling along and making what progress they make, not so much by dint of careful individual planning of their own lives, but by trial and error. Man has advanced from the simple brute to what largely could be called the political brute because, in spite of all, he has kept trying.
Life persists and human beings persevere.

Many scholars today are in agreement that one of the reasons we have advanced no further than we have relates to the dearth of a generally accepted philosophy of realism which would both properly and ideally orient man to his environment and his fellow man. But most of us are not willing to move quietly through our lives in pursuit of truth and then in alignment to that truth.

We have noticed recently a number of traffic warnings in various parts of the country which express this thought: “Slow down and live.” In a sense, this slogan could be adapted to our national unrest and applied with some merit to our propensity for action. Perhaps a more accurate slogan would be: “Slow down for truth.”

A certain degree of trial and error, in our more primitive days, was doubtless inevitable and perhaps desirable. With virtually no history to rely on and little in the way of actual knowledge to guide us, trial and error is about all we had.

But today, with man’s enormously advanced technology, unless trial and error can be confined to the laboratory, we may make a shambles out of society by one unnecessary trial and by one unforgivable error.

And the place so few are willing to give up massive experimentation is in society, where the lives of other people are to be tampered with.

It should be clear by now that in our American civilization, as an example, we have made great progress and there is yet great progress to be made. There must be a complete willingness on the part of all of us to examine this progress, or this lack of it, discover that which is true and right, and then to discard that which is not true or right and replace it with something which comes closer to the realism our times demand.

There is, unfortunately, both a tendency to discard the whole thing, which would reduce us to savagery, and an equally noticeable tendency to cling tenaciously to every facet of it, which would seal us into a living tomb of error.

We know of no way out of the dilemma except by the processes of rational thought, logic, scientific inquiry and individual freedom in which self-discipline can be practiced. Obviously, these things are not much to the liking of most of us. But it is becoming more and more apparent that to the degree we neglect them and instead look to our government to show us the way, to that degree do we compound our problems and fail utterly either to solve them or to stop creating them.

If there is one lesson which the times cry out for us to learn, it is this: Stop trusting government.

Government, when it is examined, turns out to be nothing more nor less than a group of fallible men with the political force to act as though they were infallible. Remove the political force and these same men would be as ordinary and as reasonable as any of us. And in order for us to take time for the truth we are going to have to someway help to create the kind of climate in which government cannot and will not keep rushing us frantically into the next round of folly. Reason and political force are deadly enemies.

For thousands of years we have relied upon political force. We cannot rely on it a moment longer. The greater and the more reliable agency of our time is individual reason.

Abstain From Beans


By Robert LeFevre — (1911 – 1986)

In ancient Athens, those who admired the Stoic philosophy of individualism took as their motto: “Abstain from Beans.” The phrase had a precise reference. It meant: don’t vote. Balloting in Athens occurred by dropping various colored beans into a receptacle.

To vote is to express a preference. There is nothing implicitly evil in choosing. All of us in the ordinary course of our daily lives vote for or against dozens of products and services. When we vote for (buy) any good or service, it follows that by salutary neglect we vote against the goods or services we do not choose to buy. The great merit of market place choosing is that no one is bound by any other persons selection. I may choose Brand X. But this cannot prevent you from choosing Brand Y.

When we place voting into the framework of politics, however, a major change occurs. When we express a preference politically, we do so precisely because we intend to bind others to our will. Political voting is the legal method we have adopted and extolled for obtaining monopolies of power. Political voting is nothing more than the assumption that might makes right. There is a presumption that any decision wanted by the majority of those expressing a preference must be desirable, and the inference even goes so far as to presume that anyone who differs from a majority view is wrong or possibly immoral.

But history shows repeatedly the madness of crowds and the irrationality of majorities. The only conceivable merit relating to majority rule lies in the fact that if we obtain monopoly decisions by this process, we will coerce fewer persons than if we permit the minority to coerce the majority. But implicit in all political voting is the necessity to coerce some so that all are controlled. The direction taken by the control is academic. Control as a monopoly in the hands of the state is basic.

In times such as these, it is incumbent upon free men to reexamine their most cherished, long-established beliefs. There is only one truly moral position for an honest person to take. He must refrain from coercing his fellows. This means that he should refuse to participate in the process by means of which some men obtain power over others. If you value your right to life, liberty, and property, then clearly there is every reason to refrain from participating in a process that is calculated to remove the life, liberty, or property from any other person. Voting is the method for obtaining legal power to coerce others.

Nature of Man and His Government


By Robert LeFevre — (1911 – 1986)
with an Introduction by Rose Wilder Lane


   1. Man and His Government
2. A Reasonable Viewpoint
3. Aggressive Power
4. The Law Factory
5. Government as Competitor
6. National Defense
7. A Government’s Government
8. The Product of Fear
9. The Guillotine
   10. Two-Party System
11. Superstitious Awe
12. Varying Forms of Government
13. The American Experiment
14. Sic Transit Gloria Mundi
15. Anti-Individual Device
16. Is There A Way Out?
17. The Voluntary Way
18. What Can We Do?

 

Introduction

This little book is important because it is revolutionary thinking. To appreciate its value correctly, we should remember the World Revolution’s career so far.

Not two centuries ago, refugees and castoffs on a wild coast between an empty ocean and an unknown wilderness, farther from the world’s affairs than Samoa is now, made an epochal discovery of man’s real nature. “We hold these truths to be self-evident,” they said, “that all men are created equal, that they are endowed by their Creator with certain unalienable Rights, that among these are Life, Liberty —”

A declaration that liberty, as real as life, is the nature of “all men,” challenged the basic belief and the practical arrangements of the whole world. And to defend it these low-class underlings rose, “a rabble in arms,” and defied the world’s Great Powers.

They came from frontier cabins along the James, the Delaware, the Connecticut, the Mohawk, walking in moccasins and fringed deerskin up the trails of Virginia, the Carolinas, York State, the Hampshire Grants, to meet the solid fire of the British Regulars with musket shots and their revolutionary war cry, “Liberty and Property!” And a poor refugee printer spoke for them all: “These are the times that try men’s souls. . . . There hath not been such an opportunity since the time of Adam. We have it in our power to make a new world.”

They fought and lost, fought and lost, fought again — and lost, for eight years, to a contemptuously broken treaty and a pause. The Great Powers stood around them, ignoring them, preparing to fight each other for the new continent: Spain south and southwest of them, France in the west, Great Britain northwest, north, and using their eastern ports. These enemies’ secret agents were among them, bribing, conspiring, plotting. The commander of their little army was in the pay of the king of Spain. The Republic of Vermont was a wavering ally. Many New Englanders were ready to return their States to Great Britain. In that precarious time their President, John Quincy Adams, discussing their policy, remarked in passing:

“When the day shall come for your representatives to determine whether the territories of Ceylon and Madagascar, of Corsica and Cuba, shall be governed by rules and regulations emanating from your Congress . . . and whether their people shall ultimately be constituted into States represented upon the floor of your national legislative assemblies . . . .”

For their discovery of the natural liberty of “all men” was world-revolutionary. The world of God-Kings, of Ruling Classes and wretched peasants, serfs, slaves enduring brutality, hunger, misery, could not survive that discovery.

They fought for it again — losing on land, their Capitol looted and burned, but winning on the Great Lakes, boldly winning in Britain’s own coastal waters — to the Treaty of Ghent, a real peace; and at last, after forty years, real recognition of the existence of their Republic — their revolutionary “republican” federation of thirteen little, poor, but “free and sovereign States.”

Again and again, through the long past, leagues of nations had failed. This was a league of “all men,” based on the nature of man; so in time, as its makers thought it must, it could be a federation of all mankind, a new world of free men. Including Eskimos.

The refugee printer wrote: “An army of principles will march on the horizon of the world, and it will conquer.”

Now a strange thing occurred. In the source and center of this real World Revolution, the men who were making it — forgot it.

Three generations of free men, while overcoming the fierce resistance of a wild continent, actually created here a wholly new way of human life, never before imaginable. Men engaged in this stupendous task put their whole minds into it. And the minds of American intellectuals remained in the Old World, with the thinkers who were reacting against the Revolution.

In 1789, George Washington was President, and Jefferson and Lafayette were taking the Revolution to France. In 1792, the Jacobin socialists ousted the French republicans. The Jacobins decreed “unity,” dictated and, wrecked the economy, tried to enforce unity and obedience by massacres and the Terror, collapsed, and made way for Napoleon, the first Hitler. Then appeared in American text books the European view: “The French Revolution began the spread of liberal ideas.”

In the 1830’s and 1840’s, active Americans were annexing the Republic of California. Americans in northern Mexico, at San Antonio and San Jacinto, were fighting and dying for freedom and their dream of the Lone-Star Republic of Texas. At Yale, an honored guest, the French socialist Fourier, was enthralling his learned audiences with his visions of a Socialist World, and New England’s intellectuals were fondly trusting that their Brook Farm commune was a beginning of the future Communist World Commonwealth. It wasn’t.

The Revolution was arousing reaction against it, everywhere in the Old World, from Mexico in 1820 through all South America, to Italy in the 1860’s, Germany in the 1880’s, China in 1911, Russia in 1917. The whole Old World was wrecked. That ancient world of rulers and ruled, tyranny and slavery, poverty, misery, famine, torture, human degradation, was smashed by its violent reaction against the discovery that “all men” are endowed by their Creator with liberty, as real, as inalienable from a living person as life itself.

Since 1860 the Jacobin reaction has been organized. The first Communist International failed in France in 1870, and its disheartened members disbanded it in Philadelphia in 1876. The Second Communist International collapsed in 1914; its former members became Fascists in Italy, National Socialists in Germany. The Third Communist International is now an armed Power, and the issue at last is clear; in the ruins of the Old World, the Reaction faces the New World with bared teeth and claws, snarling, “We will bury you.”

A century of heedless builders and reactionary thinkers has had reactionary effects even within this Republic. Too many Old World fallacies have been believed here, too many Old World measures imitated. Apparently only one lone newspaperman, Mr. Haskell, of the Kansas City Star recognized the “New” Deal as a stale imitation of ancient Rome in its decline. But the source and center of the World Revolution is still in this revolutionary Republic, this only successful league of States, the first ever made to defend every person’s human rights: life, liberty, property.

A real World Revolution is not to be won in two centuries. The reaction against it has wrecked the whole Old World. It wrecked France and retreated to Germany; wrecked Germany and retreated to darkest Russia and stagnant China. It can retreat no farther; now is the showdown. Now the struggle between the old, barbarous past and the new, possible future involves the whole human world and every one of us alive.

The basic question, on which the answers to all other questions depend, is: What is the nature of man? The only political question is: What is the nature of the institution named “Government”? It is a simple fact that all men’s future for centuries is being determined by the answers that Americans give to these fundamental questions. We have it in our power to make a new world. There has not been such a responsibility since the time of Adam.

So I would ask you to sharpen your own thinking on Mr. LeFevre’s genuine thought about these questions. The value of this little book is its contribution and its stimulus to true revolutionary thinking. I think you have not read its like before. If it jolts you, that’s good; these are the times when minds need waking up. Let nothing keep you from it any longer.

Rose Wilder Lane — (1886 – 1968)


   Chapter 1

 

Man and His Government

Know then thyself, presume not God to scan;
The proper study of mankind is Man.

Man is a conglomerate of many things. His distinctive characteristic, above all others, is his ability to create tools. In this department he is unique. No other animated entity of all creation, so far as we can tell, has this ability, at least to the extent that man has it.

Man has learned, because of his remarkable tool-making facility, to extend himself into all kinds of worlds and situations which would be beyond him except for his tools. It is the use of tools which gives man mastery over this planet. If man plunges beyond this planet, it will be his tools which take him there.

One of the principal characteristics of the toolmaker is his ability not only to devise the original tool but to improve upon that tool which he has devised. It could be argued that a failure to improve a given tool, while other tools were being improved, might seriously handicap man’s progress. In other words, if man found himself addicted to the use of, let us say, the hand ax as the only tool for cutting wood, to such a degree that he would not consider a better method, the development of power saws would have been meaningless and impossible. If man wants to use an ax, and if his desires in this connection are buttressed by superstitious fear, by religious conviction, by stubborn willfulness or mental inertia, so that he believes the use of the ax is right whereas any tool other than the ax would be wrong, then man would never be able to go beyond the use of the ax. To convince him that the use of the ax in the midst of far more effective tools in other categories is no longer desirable, would require a virtual revolution of thought. Mankind would have to examine its habits, its thought patterns, its moral convictions, the very mores of the race itself before it would consider anything else.

Therefore, man’s use of a particular tool beyond the date of its obsolescence, though it admittedly had served a purpose at one time, might actually become a harmful usage. An insistence upon the use of an archaic instrument could hold back man’s progress, perhaps indefinitely. Further, if the tool were basic, a dedication to its employment could become actually destructive. For it might be that this one tool was of such a nature that it could and would interfere with the development or the improvement of virtually all other tools. Man could be bound and limited by the very device which once was, perhaps, one of his chief aids.

If we can begin to understand the tools men make, we may begin to understand more about man’s true nature. The nature of the creator is discernible in his works.

One of the most curious and one of the most useful tool-making facilities which man has is his ability to organize. Any organization made by man can be classed as a tool.

Man begins his organizational efforts by classifying things in groupings according to his understanding of those things. He learns to make associations on the basis of identity and similarity. He then learns to make disassociations on the basis of differences and, finally, opposites. Man organizes his thoughts, his time, his physical possessions. Finally, he organizes his neighbors and politics is born.

Men have made hundreds of thousands of organizations. Each one has a purpose. Men have learned to combine their energies around a specific objective; harness the energies of diverse and sometimes even conflicting personalities; and concentrate upon a program, project, or product, to the exclusion of all other things. If you look at this process objectively, you cannot help but be amazed.

During the long and bloody history of human progress, the most prolific and fertile efforts have been put forth by men to create an organization which is called “government.” Government has been deemed by primitive and semi-civilized men as the single most important tool ever to be devised.

Government is important because it is a tool designed to multiply the strength and power of individuals. If one man is strong, two men would be stronger. From earliest times man has desired strength. If government, the invention of man, could be so formed that it multiplied man’s strength, then man would have an important device of power to use against his enemies. This is the reason for government. It was the answer to the search made by primitive men for collective strength in place of individual lack of strength.

For us to understand the nature of man, a good beginning could be made by attempting to understand the nature of this tremendous tool of man’s devising.

What is government?

Clearly, all governments are simply groups of men or women which are put together for the purpose of finding strength, of providing protection. Every possible combination of rules, codes, laws, charters, constitutions, regencies, protectorates, treaties, contracts, specifications, and customs has gone into the tens of thousands of governments which have been devised during history’s meteoric course. But however the framework is made, however the structure is built, the fact remains that government is a tool of man’s devising, neither better nor worse than the men who devise and use it, and calculated to make man stronger and better able to protect himself in his weaknesses, by the use of force, exerted by some over others. That is all.

The understanding of what government is, and what government is not, is of paramount importance. The importance of understanding government lies not in the importance of government itself, but in the importance men place upon their beliefs respecting government. The importance of understanding government lies in the importance of the security and protection which governments have been devised to provide. Thus, while men may believe that a government is important in itself, beneath this belief is the fact that government is a means to an end, not an end in itself. So we must not only examine this means, this tool of protection, but we must also explore protection, and the necessity for it if it exists.


  Chapter 2

 

A Reasonable Viewpoint

Men have many viewpoints respecting the functions and the purposes of government. Let us explore some of them in turn.

It has been noted that men are weak and that government is a device aimed at helping men to overcome their weakness.

Physically, mentally, and even morally, men appear to be weak. As we look at man’s physical nature, we recognize immediately that he is no match for many other living things. Lacking tools, modern man would survive with difficulty if at all. Tools multiply his energies, making him more than a match for other living things. In a hand-to-claw combat man could be bested by almost any other living creature relatively near his own size.

Man cannot outrun the four-footed animals, but his tools can. Man cannot outfight the wild beasts, but his tools can. Man cannot tame the domesticable animals, but his tools of fences, ropes, cages, special foods, and knowledge can.

Looking at man’s mental stature, again we are prone to discover his weakness. Men have lived in error. What progress man has made has been made haltingly, as he rubbed superstition and fear from his eyes, studied the true nature of matter and learned to rise, by means of the tools of books, research, test tube and model, into a better world.

Compared to what man does not know, even all modern mental achievement is but a single candle flame flickering in darkness. Yet by means of his tools, man is overcoming this darkness. Where would man be without, let us say, the alphabet; the numerals 1 to 10; the printing press; paper, ink, and glue? Eliminate the tools and within a few generations man would be engulfed once more by superstition, fear, and ignorance.

And what of morality? Here is, perhaps, the greatest frontier yet to be crossed by humankind. What does man know and understand about morals? Very little. In centuries, he has learned that the Golden Rule is good, and has less than a dozen basic rules of conduct embodied in the Decalogue.

Here, the church and religion itself have been man’s most useful tools. But today, even as man’s technology improves, as his mechanical genius unfolds and his knowledge of matter increases by leaps and bounds, his ability to govern himself and to master the precepts of morality approaches a yawning chasm. It could be said that the area of man’s basic goodness has been too little shored up by effective tools. While man’s material tools improve, man’s moral tools are neglected and remain largely static. It would not be too harsh to say that man’s morality has gone into a decline.

Here, then, is man — a moral, mental, and physical entity having life. And here, also, are man’s weaknesses, embodied in his very nature.

But as we have shown, man has, from his earliest beginnings, turned to government to bolster his weaknesses. Government is man’s chief organizational tool to be employed against his weaknesses.

Thus, when men turn to government in an effort to overcome weakness and to obtain protection, the strength desired is found in compulsive unity. Government, inherently, places individualism at a low point on any scale of values. Individuals are the enemies of government. Government is inescapably concerned with unity. Individuals are the necessary victims.

It is true that some governments have proclaimed a contrary doctrine. Some have said that the individual is important and the government is merely the servant of the individual. But let the evidence be presented and we discover that this assertion is only a pleasant fiction. The servant has the power and the strength. The individual bows before the might of the servant, who is, despite the platitudes, a master, not a slave to men. Governments rule. Individuals are ruled.

Any individual must give way to the violent cohesion of government.

If the individual is physically, mentally, or morally in error, that is to say, if the individual is physically a criminal, mentally unbalanced, or morally degenerated, the combined and powerful action of a government may provide an amelioration. And it is in this area where actions taken by government are deemed to be not only proper in a moral sense, but highly practical and desirable. Since it is true that an individual who refuses to practice self-discipline and practices theft, for example, can be opposed, apprehended, and even punished by government, the employment of this tool by human beings has long been upheld as a prime necessity.

This would seem to be, then, a reasonable function for the government to have. What we must explore are some of the other functions which government has assumed. Also, we must look into this same function — that of apprehending and punishing criminals — to determine the actual necessity of the function and also to discover whether the function could be performed more practically, more morally, more economically and more certainly by some tool other than government.

Man’s progress has come largely of his ability not only to discover tools, but to improve tools. Can the thief-taking ability of government be improved upon by providing a better tool?


Chapter 3

 

Aggressive Power

 

As we look at government we find that men have organized for the purpose of protecting themselves and their property. Government is the tool of this protection.

Also, since government is always an agency which plans to use and, indeed, must use force, we have noted that government derives its power from a compulsory unification. All persons under the jurisdiction of a particular government are compelled to agree with whatever that government does. The agreement can be enthusiastic, tacit, or reluctant. But the agreement must be there. Government’s power to protect is based upon that agreement, however secured. Power, to be effective, cannot permit exceptions.

Thus, the government is inevitably opposed to individuals. The individual is the natural prey of the organizational tool. And we have shown that when the individual is immoral, mentally retarded, or physically aggressive against others, the government can employ its cohesive power in a manner which is pleasing to people in general.

In short, it can act defensively, taking a position against the one on behalf of the many.

So long as the matter is simple, the case clear-cut, the individual obviously out of order, and the protection of the people generally the paramount issue, government is fulfilling what people generally expect of it.

But matters are rarely simple and cases have a way of being complicated and fogged over with a combination of motives, behavior patterns, backgrounds, and prejudice. Thus, more times than not, an individual will object to some particular government action only to find himself, by reason of his objection, the object and the victim of governmentalism.

A peaceful and law-abiding citizen, for example, may have perfectly sound and moral reasons why he does not wish to share his money with the government or the politicians of Yugoslavia. His conviction can be logically derived, morally certain, and sincerely maintained. In holding to his conviction, the individual is harming no one. His belief is not inimical to the welfare of other people. Actions which might spring from his belief are not aggressive. In other words, physically, mentally, and morally, such a citizen can be above reproach.

Yet, when the government adopts a policy which prescribes the sharing of his earnings with a foreign government, the man who objects to this can be treated in precisely the same manner as a bank robber could be treated and for the same reason. The government cannot brook a deviationist.

If the government decrees against bank robbing, it can permit of no exception. It will use its full force of unified power to prevent bank robbing, or, at worst, to apprehend and punish the robber should one appear. And if the government decrees a universal sharing of its citizens’ wealth with the politicians of another country, it can permit of no exception here. It can and it will use its full force of unified power to collect whatever sums it deems advisable and will punish any person refusing to provide those sums, with arrest, fine, or imprisonment, and in the event of resistance, with death.

Thus, in practice, the tool of protection, which men have devised out of their weaknesses, can be employed and is employed with equal vigor and ferocity against both the criminal and the good and harmless citizen. Here the bank robber and the patriot who loves his country are equated.

Government has but a single standard, obedience. Its decrees, good, bad, or indifferent, are enforceable. And the men in government cannot recognize a law which need not be enforced. If the government has adopted a policy, the policy must be carried out, even though one policy may be aimed at social stability and the other at social injustice.

This is one of the characteristics of weakness contained in man’s nearly universal tool of strength. The device of protection can be employed as a weapon both defensively and aggressively.


 Chapter 4

 

The Law Factory

 

Having granted that a government can perform a defensive function by apprehending and punishing the criminal, we must look at government on a broader scale.

It is immediately apparent that there is no government in all the world, saving only extremely small and local constabularies, which reserves for itself solely this simple and at least partially constructive function. The prevention of crime and the punishment of the criminal have become, in most instances, subsidiary departments of government. In the main, governments have gone far beyond this field of activity.

Today governments concern themselves in general not with criminals, but with law-abiding citizens. Every citizen is a victim of the aggressive tactics of government. Government begins by seizing the arbitrary and total power of deciding how much money it wants. Then it collects the money without a care or concern for the plight of the individual who must pay or be punished like a criminal.

Next, the government establishes hundreds and thousands of regulations which prescribe particular practices and proscribe others. Almost every action of every citizen has its legal “do” and “don’t.”

The list of prohibitions and compulsions is too lengthy for cataloguing here. But it pertains to business operations, licenses, building regulations, zoning, hours of employment, prices, trade, quotas, embargoes, subsidies, grants-in-aid, traffic, assembly, slander, libel, trespass, health, cleanliness, quality, quantity, method, education, indoctrination, propaganda, news, pictures, morals, food, drink, clothing, housing, sanitation, roads, farm products, transportation, search, seizure, mental outlook, exchange of parcels by post, and so on.

It can truthfully be said that there is almost no activity in which human beings engage which is free of legality. Think what you will, do what you will, there is a law somewhere which either compels, limits, or prohibits.

Try to think of something that people do. With the possible exception of breathing, laws bristle from the activity like quills from a porcupine. And the result of all these laws is to make any individual who does not conform in every respect, a lawbreaker.

Thus, the average person today, buttressed in by government, surrounded and overshadowed by government, finds himself a lawbreaker several times during an average day. And this fact turns him from being a law-abiding citizen into a lawbreaking citizen and equates him with any criminal who, in fact, breaks a law with aggressive intent.

But the government, as has been shown, cannot concern itself with anything but the universal obedience it must enforce. Thus, any violation of law becomes in essence a punishable offense. And whereas the government does maintain certain classifications — civil, criminal, and the like — the fact remains that even in civil matters government can and will punish and apprehend with vigor. This is not the fault of government. This is the nature of government.

This is the major point which must be understood eventually. Government which passes and enforces endless rules and codes is not out of character when it does so. It is in character. That is the way any government operates. And the longer a given government endures, the more numerous will be the laws it enacts. It is the business of government to pass laws and to enforce them. These laws are the productive sum of all governmental effort. Therefore it is not to be wondered at when thousands and thousands of new laws come into existence every year. It would rather be a marvel if this did not happen.

Government is a law factory. It passes laws in the same manner that another type of factory extrudes metal molding. Government is a lawmaking tool.

But, whereas a factory which extrudes metal molding is providing a product which is useful to the citizens generally, and which certain citizens will purchase voluntarily; the government factory extrudes compulsion which is useful principally to the government, itself, but is purchased in advance by the people, who are never in a position to refuse to buy.


 Chapter 5

 

Government as Competitor

 

We have now shown that government has a single, possibly legitimate, function, that of apprehending and punishing the criminal. We have also shown that government has, in its manifold legal actions, gone far beyond its possible legitimacy by passing thousands upon thousands of laws and rules which tend to equate the average individual, who is peaceful and orderly, with the criminal who commits acts of aggression with willful intent.

Now, we must continue to look at government as it goes even beyond this limit. For within our own lifetimes, our own governments — national, state, and local — have gone beyond even the excessiveness of multiple legal prohibitions and compulsions.

One of the most serious incursions performed by the governments against their citizenry has occurred in those instances where the government has abandoned its position as arbiter and compulsionist, and has embarked in the role of entrepreneur. Today, not content with compelling and preventing citizens as they go about their daily routines, government has developed for itself an independent status as a business or industrial entity.

Our federal government has taken on this chore in more than nine hundred separate fields, ranging from corset making, rope manufacture, and candy-bar purveying to the distilling of low-grade rum. It has become a provider of electric power, gas, and water; it runs golf courses, zoos, and tourist attractions; it manages bus and railroad lines, radio and television stations, newspapers and periodicals. It manufactures nuts and bolts and copper wire, and engineers immense building projects. It builds roads and ships, runs hospitals and, even in the end, handles graveyards.

Yet all of these things also are done by private persons, managing their own affairs under government supervision and by permission — after taxes; whereas the government cannot supervise itself, pays no taxes, and consistently competes with the very persons who are compelled to provide the wherewithal for government enterprise. Nor have state or local governments been free of the general federal trespass. In point of fact, in many areas local governments are the principal offenders.

This is a very far cry, indeed, from the simple expedient of catching and punishing thieves and murderers. Nor is this the end of government’s straying from its prescribed course.

In our own case, anew departure in governmentalism has arisen to plague every American. For in this country chiefly, although the offense also exists in other countries to a minor degree, our own taxpayers are compelled to pay taxes for the support of foreign governments. And this is tyranny of the worst order.

Yet it is not unknown in history. Weaker states have, from time immemorial, been compelled to pay tribute to stronger and more vigorous neighbors. The innovation, circa the 1930’s, was that the United States of America, the then strongest and most vigorous nation in the world, began to pay tribute from a position of strength. And this was the great advance towards barbarism, made exclusively by American politicians.

Stripped of its humanitarian language and reduced to fundamentals, the payment of American tax money to foreign powers constituted international bribery of an order a degree worse than the payment of ransom money to the Barbary pirates. Fear was obviously at the bottom of the move.

With America the greatest and most productive nation on earth, her politicians became fearful of both the envy of others and the war making potentials of others. It was as though we lived in a glass house in a neighborhood of stone throwers. And to prevent the stones from being thrown, our government adopted a policy of rewarding our neighbors for the negative passivity of not throwing stones.

The claim was made that this would win us friends. The most simple and least informed psychologist could have revealed that this practice would only win us the contempt and hostility of others. For America was no glass house. It was a rich and productive reservoir of a high percentage of all the production on earth, including the production of the means to defend ourselves. And this our neighbors knew.


Chapter 6

 

National Defense

 

We come at once to government’s classic usage, that of making war upon government’s enemies. Whether we begin our examination of government as a warmaker in clan, tribe, city, state, or nation, or even as a body of nations joined together, we find this the single most costly and terrible function that government can ever attempt.

Aggressive warfare is always the exclusive prerogative of government. Mobs, groups, families, or individuals may fight. They may riot, destroy, pillage, and perform in any wanton way. But it takes a government to conduct a war. Only government has the capacity, extended through both time and space, to organize sufficient force and violence to sustain a war. And only government, in our age, can effectively amass sufficient wealth for such a nonproductive and destructive purpose.

Aggressive warfare can never be justified on any moral ground. The use of initiated violence is abhorrent to all persons. But what does fall under our gaze is the apparent occasional necessity for a government to perform in war as a defendant. It is true, governments being what they are, that certain governments will plot and plan an aggressive campaign of combat, however immoral or foolish such a campaign might be. And it must follow that if any government undertakes so violent a course, other governments, lying in the pathway of the deliberate predator, may with some justification inform their citizens of the danger.

What should be the nature of this information? Since government is merely a tool, and since it is always the citizens who face the hazards occasioned by a physical clash in battle, the alert should always be couched in terms acceptable to volunteers. Further, the call to arms should come from the people and not from their government.

If there is a real danger, the danger is one which the citizens will recognize. Having recognized it, they will do what they can to defend themselves. They are the actors of the drama.

On the other hand, it is entirely possible, and in many instances a proven fact, that the announced danger is fancied rather than real. Governments tend to make trouble, in a great hubbub of concern for their own prerogatives. The citizens are capable of discerning the difference between a scare drummed up by power-hungry politicians and a real threat to their safety and security. In truth, the citizens are always in a better position to make this discernment than is their government. Governments, as instruments of force and power, are far too prone to operate in an atmosphere of fear. They tend to engender fear. They end by believing their own engenderings.

One of the most serious mistakes the citizens can ever make is to grant to their government the power of a draft. Governments which can forcefully enlist the citizens under them, can shoulder their way truculently among all foreign powers, confident that they can compel a final showdown to their liking. Lacking this power, a government is constantly in review before its citizens. The citizens may, in such a case, refuse to accept their government’s foreign policies and the errors perpetrated thereby. This would leave such a government in an untenable position. It must move warily and peacefully or risk an ultimate exposure before a hostile force.

From a practical point of view the volunteer in any war is a better soldier than the conscript. The nature of man being what it is, men will always seek to be in the place they wish to be, and they will attempt to get away from the place they do not wish to be. If a man chooses to oppose an actual enemy in the field, it is because he would rather be in such a position than in any other. But if a man is compelled to take the field, and is uncertain as to the actual hostility in the breast 0f his supposed enemy, he must be driven and forced at every turn of the road. Such a man will only stay to fight because he fears his own government more than he fears the guns of his opponents. Under such compulsions he does not do his best. Nor is his love of country encouraged by such outrage.

Our problem is not to find a way to compel men to defend themselves. This they will always do. Our problem is to prevent the evils of conscription which hamper true defense, create armed forces which contain aggressive potential, and create a drain of economic wealth beyond all other actions. We must be vigilant that we are not lured into hostile poses by a fearful or belligerent government.

But here we run into a whole series of dilemmas. The dilemmas are occasioned by the fact that historically the citizens have turned over to their government all power of decision respecting the preparing for and the waging of war.

How can a government, armed and capable of conducting an effective defensive campaign, be successfully prevented from the slightest act of aggressive war? To this question, history gives us a discouraging answer. Any government fully armed and ready for defense is all too prone to prove the point upon the field.

Alas, the human record proves another point. Who is the aggressor in any war? With absolute unanimity the answer is, the other fellow. The bristling engines of war build up along each national boundary. The pressures mount behind the barricades. A rising tide, like a great wave, towers menacingly until sometime, somewhere, the laws of gravity take hold and the great wave topples, spilling out across the barriers like an onrushing flood. This is aggression. Who caused the spilling? The science of tactics and of strategy gives us the official ruling. “Each act of war is retaliatory.” Even the first act of any conflict is in reprisal for some prior condition.

The prior condition in itself need not be hostile. Differences between nations and people abound. Wars have been waged for the flimsiest of reasons. Yet, when a government decides that warfare is “the only course,” the slightest pretext, relating to color of skin, religious differences, tariffs, immigration laws, language differences, differences in philosophies, or even hostile words, has established at one time or another a cause for war.

Thus, even when one government hurls its legions across a boundary in an obvious attempt to amass land and plunder, the excuse is always given that the aggression occurred because the government on the other side of the boundary drove the government on the near side to this final deadly act of politics.

How can the ultimate in human foolishness be prevented? Clearly, it is preposterous to assume that the tool capable of such a holocaust can also be relied upon to prevent the very thing it is uniquely designed to do. This would be like supposing that fire will not burn, or that a fire once started can be extinguished by a larger fuel supply. One does not call upon one’s government to prevent war. One calls upon one’s government to wage it. And it is here that the necessity for understanding man’s own nature as well as the nature of his tool de main, becomes, in modern times, acute.

If we are to believe the tacticians, war is always a reaction against some prior act. But this is only saying what has been said all along, that war is the natural extension of politics. War is organized force employed by government against some other government which is under no constraint to give obedience to alien politicians. Governments wage wars against their individual citizens and it is called policing. But when a government wages war against another government, it is called by its right name.

But let us ask, in what way is a war against an opposing government different from government’s eternal war against the individual? The answer is that in principle it is the same; only the battle- fields and the size and scope of the arena provide a distinction. But it is a distinction without a difference in principle. Governments back up their decrees by force of arms. In the event the decree is leveled against a citizen, the force of arms required is moderate. In the event the decree is aimed at a foreign power, an army must be employed to compel obedience.

In the end we will see that only governments make war. The people in all nations do the fighting and the dying. But our quarrel is never truly with them. Our quarrel is always with their government, which sets them upon us.

We are not suggesting a dismantling of the tool of our possible protection.

But we are suggesting that we examine this tool, recognizing that while it is capable of defensive action, it is a1so capable of so conducting itself at home or abroad that defensive action, in the end, becomes the only course open to us.

Here, as in every other case, that which was formed for our protection becomes, finally, the very reason we need to be protected. This tool of defensive potential inevitably contains the seeds of aggressive force and violence. The larger and more powerful it becomes defensively, the more it is apt to use its vast ability in some aggressive manner.


 Chapter 7

 

A Government’s Government

 

If we would understand why our government has so invaded private rights; if we would learn why our government has expanded so greatly during the past two and a half decades; if we would comprehend the thinking which has caused our government to resort to bribery in an effort to maintain friendly relations, and is even now considering the advisability of launching a war to prevent a war from breaking out — we must look to the nature of man, and not to the nature of government.

Government, as we have attempted to show, is merely a tool. Man, the maker of government, is, in the final analysis, the master of government. Yet man has made government to perform the opposite function and to master man. And while all governments begin with the premise that they will protect the many peaceful from the few who are belligerent, it is in the nature of governments that the rules will be extended and expanded until the state itself becomes man’s mortal permanently damages a priceless relic.

The tool is blameless. And thus, the government, within itself, is blameless. It is simply a ravening monster, naturally, and will continue to grow, to expand, to pounce upon its victims and devour them in foe.

We cannot blame a lever if, in our exercise of it across a fulcrum, it slips from our grasp and smashes a toe. We cannot blame a shovel if, in the hands of the wielder, it plunges into an ancient tomb and the normal course of its activity. That is the kind of tool it is. Man made the tool to perform in that fashion.

It is an instrument of force and coercion. And there can never be an instrument of force and coercion which will consciously restrain itself. It must be restrained. Yet there is no tool capable of such restraint. For any type of tool, whatever its nature, which is allegedly formed to restrain and contain government, would, by its own nature, simply become a government’s government.

In other words, the restraining tool for a compulsive instrument would have to contain a greater accumulation of power than the compulsive instrument or it would be ineffective. But this, in essence, would also be a government. It would simply be a larger, more compulsive, more dangerous and more mischievous tool and less subject to restraint than the original instrument of coercion.

The United Nations falls into this category, as — does every other prior political organization aimed at universal peace. The United Nations is simply a government’s government. The members of the United Nations are, by definition, not the peoples of the world, but the nations of the world, at present eighty-two in number.

Individual people cannot belong to the United Nations. Only governments can belong. The delegates to the United Nations are simply politicians who have been appointed by the member governments. And it is in the nature of the United Nations that it will look after the governmental interests of its members. Hence, the things that the member governments desire to do will become the policies of the United Nations.

But the thing all member governments desire to do is to rule their own people and to collect money from them. This is inherent in their natures. So the United Nations, perforce, will aid and abet the member governments in their universal desire to maintain a coercive hold over their individual subjects.

Thus, the United Nations is a government of the governments, by the governments, and for the governments. And it cannot and will not restrain these governments, for the members support the giant, looking to it for backing, even as the individual citizen supports his own government and looks to it for backing.

So much for the nature of government, and even for the nature of a government’s government.

But at the root of all government stand the people. What is it in the nature of human beings which causes them to look to a government?

There is only one thing which causes man to look for and to organize a tool which is an instrument of compulsion and prohibition. That thing is fear. Men look to government to protect them because they fear. And virtually without exception, everything that human beings fear becomes a project for government.


 Chapter 8

 

The Product of Fear

 

Fear is one of the most interesting and one of the most basic of all human emotions. And, as we have attempted to show, man, recognizing his weaknesses, which are many, is fearful of many things. He fears his predatory neighbor, death, old age, poverty, loneliness, hunger, and cold.

In man’s rise from the primitive to the relatively civilized status of modern times, man has been propelled by fear probably more than by any other facet of his heterogeneous nature.

His fear of hunger has caused him to search diligently for dependable food supplies. His fear of cold has caused him to erect buildings and to fashion clothing. His fear of death has caused him to study the nature of matter, to discover the germ theory, to guard his health and to provide as long as possible against the ultimate.

His fear of the supernatural, which led him first into a belief in a plurality of deities and created a world of superstition, led him ultimately toward morality and the Golden Rule.

He discovered that it was wise to fear the immoral act of others, and hence it was a matter of simple prudence for him to forbear when it came to committing an immoral act himself.

Probably no basic emotion of man has been so fruitful in its results. If men were not chronic worriers, they would take no thought of tomorrow. As it is, they have taken great thought of tomorrow and the result is that our todays are buttressed about with forethought, even though tomorrow always brings its problems which must still be solved.

It is this all-compelling emotion, fear, that has sired governments. Man is fearful of strength in others. Therefore, he has devised an organizational gadget, containing compulsory unification, and by means of which he hopes to offset, or even to overcome, the strength of others.

Governments, then, are not agencies of right, necessarily. They are, necessarily, agencies of strength. It could be said that man, feeling certain that he was surrounded by gangsters, has devised a gangster of his own, theoretically obedient to his own will, who will act with truculence against alien gangsters, while remaining docile and tractable towards his deviser.

History teaches us with much repetition that this is an enormous fallacy. Governments begin with a soft side towards their own creators and a hard exterior exposed towards potential foes. But as time passes, the hard exterior extends until it completely encompasses the government. Then, it develops that it has no “soft” side at all. It becomes equally hard and impervious towards every human being, since the nature of the gadget is that it must be strong against human beings.

Government’s presumed selectivity, in knowing whom to favor and whom to oppose, is actually nonexistent. This is because, as we have shown, the nature of government’s strength is derived wholly from its compulsory unification. Government can permit no exceptions to its rules, whether these rules are aimed at preventing an aggressive act against a citizen under its jurisdiction by another citizen similarly situated, or whether the rules are aimed at compelling uniform attendance at a government institution of indoctrination by every junior citizen from the age of six.

In the one case the government may act defensively, to protect the rights of an individual; in the other case, the government will act aggressively, protecting no individual right but simply compelling universal obedience to its decrees.

In the one case the government acts as a friend, within the framework of its theoretical usefulness. In the other case the government is the predator, actively enacting the role of the foreign or alien gangster.

And it is apparent that men have so much fear concerning the imminence of gangsterism in their midst that they tend to bear the iniquities of government’s predatory actions without a murmur, rather than to deprive themselves temporarily of their own gangster, however powerful and unruly he has become.


Chapter 9

 

The Guillotine

 

Government’s ability to bite the hand that feeds it has long been mourned by its principal progenitors. Simple human beings for at least six thousand years have learned to put their faith in some governmental organization only to find, after the passage of a few years, that the agency they trusted has turned to rend them in their tracks.

They have long marveled at this phenomenon. And their wonder, during the unfolding of man’s story, has taken two principal avenues towards a solution.

1. They have concluded that the particular men selected to head up and run a particular government have been evil. Hence, they have reasoned, if they can find better men, they will have nothing to fear.

2. They have concluded that the particular form of government they have devised has lacked certain safeguards. They have reasoned that if the government could have been organized along different lines, they would have escaped the evil their government was busily engaged in inflicting upon them.

We will take these two avenues in turn.

First, what of the men in government? Nowhere in all the world has such feverish activity attended the process of selecting good men to governmental office than in these United States. With us, it is a passion, nay, a mania.

In the United States an enfranchised citizenry is virtually the single untouchable institution of our time. If the people are free to vote and, thus, to select the men who will become the personnel manning our own gangster device, it is deemed that we have overcome barbarism and that security is certain. The right to vote is, in the public mind, prior to and superior to the right to liberty. It is by the process of polling that we secure for ourselves the best in the way of governmental servants. But is this really true, or is it rather a large superstition generally believed?

Could we timidly inquire if the voting process has always secured for us men of superior ability? And if our answer is affirmative, or we have raised our voices against a shibboleth . . . then how does it happen that so many administrations of good men have been able to do so many evil and harmful things to their subjects?

Let us assume that voting practices embody no superstition; that, in fact, the men selected by the voting public are inescapably the best that can be found at a given moment in our history. Then, the resulting harm must come, not because of the good men but because the good men are powerless to prevent the harm.

And surely we are mature enough in our deliberations at this crucial point in our history so that we can admit that our multitudinous governments, at every level-federal, state, and local — do considerable in the way of harm. The harm is obvious. We have less freedom than we used to have. We are more coerced. We are plundered repeatedly and in growing amounts for every conceivable scheme that the human mind can invent.

Nor does one act of plunder solve the problem for which the plunder was originally legalized. Rather, each act of plunder gives birth to the necessity for additional acts of plunder. And the number of laws curtailing us, regimenting us, restricting us, and punishing us grows hourly larger and more difficult of evasion.

So the harm continues, yet the men inflicting the harm are the best that can be obtained!

If this is the case, Isabel Paterson, in her monumental work, The God of the Machine, gives us one kind of answer. She establishes that government is a tool, and she defines the nature of the tool as that of a guillotine. In effect she asks, what good does it do to have a saint of every conceivable virtue operating a guillotine? Personally, the man may be above reproach. He may have the highest of morals and ethics. He may be imbued with a passion for doing good. But the mechanism he is hired to operate cuts off heads.

He may dislike to cut off heads. He may weep with true sorrow whenever a head falls into the basket. But he was hired to pull the rope that lets the knife drop. And when it comes down, off comes the head. That is the way the tool works.

In her analysis, Miss Paterson is eminently correct. Government is an agency of force which can and must be employed against every deviationist. And this is only to say again that the government must oppose the individual. Therefore the “good” man in government is like a priest with a machine gun. The mechanism does the harm. The man who operates it merely pulls the trigger.


  Chapter 10

 

Two-Party System

 

There is no other way of explaining the phenomenon. Good men do find their way into government. But having gotten there, they must either perform their function or resign. If they perform their function, they use the government, an agency of compulsively gathered coercive force, to accomplish that function. Inevitably, they hurt someone. This is undoubtedly the reason such a furor is maintained over the necessity for a two-party system. Nothing is said in the Constitution or the Bill of Rights about the necessity of a two-party system. Yet most Americans hold that two parties are necessary.

The reason is obvious. The party in power inevitably employs its friends and well-wishers, and passes laws and enforces proceedings against others not of the same political conviction.

Over a period of time these laws and enforcements build up a body of resistance. The oppression mounts. It may become a public scandal. Finally, the “ins” are ousted and the other party assumes power.

Immediately the process repeats but with alternate emphasis. Those who are “ins” become “outs.” And the newly hired “ins” go to work to cut their friends free from oppression and to visit their vengeance upon those who subscribed to the beliefs of the former “ins.” Then the same iniquities come to pass allover again. Those persecuted change places with the persecutors. And around and around goes the political wheel of chance, with the voting public spinning the wheel.

In our own time we have seen one curious variance occurring to this otherwise monotonous and easily predictable routine. The “ins” and the “outs” have performed a merger. The party in power has now scarcely a discernible difference from the party out of power. And the reason for this merger is self-evident. The government has in itself grown so large and so formidable that it tends to absorb any and all politically interested persons, regardless of party affiliation. And since, in the main, there is no real difference in political parties, each party desiring only to rule — each party adopts an advertising program consisting of those public statements which each party leader feels will win an election — the merger is that of blood brothers and constitutes no betrayal.

Of course there are those who have felt that elections were for the purpose of establishing policies, rather than for the purpose of selecting men. These persons, always a minority, vote for the statement made by certain politicians and against the statement made by others. But since all of these statements are nothing but window trimming, constituting a verbal display, and in all probability not representing either the thinking or the intention of the person making the statement, a vote secured by virtue of a statement does not establish policy but merely enhances the position of the man who made it.

But again, this is simply the mechanics, the “advertising.” The purpose of an election is to select men, not policies. And in the end, the men are selected, after which the policies are adopted.

But the policies, whether from party one or party two, are more nearly identical than opposite. For it is the business of government to employ force and to compel obedience. And it is the business of any politician within a government, regardless of his party, to employ government as an agency of force and coercion; to compel obedience and uniformity; and to punish any individual who does not go along with those mandates imagined as necessary by the men in power.

So, now we must ask the inevitable question. We have considered the situation that must ensue if we presume that the voting process always provides us with the best possible government employees. But, what if this is not true? What if the voting process does not guarantee the selection of superior men?

In this case, then, our preoccupation with the polls is simply a false reliance upon a majority. And since a majority is nothing but the amassing of power by virtue of superior numbers, are we not extolling the alleged virtue of might, instead of right?

Either the voting process will provide for us the best men in government, or it will not. Whichever way we choose to believe, we meet the inescapable result. The result is that government has the tendency of growing large and unmanageable and in the end of turning to rend and devour even its most devoted followers.


Chapter 11

 

Superstitious Awe

 

We have now explored the first avenue. This is one of the paths taken by some men when they discover that their government has become predatory against themselves. They seek to alleviate the predation by changing the personnel within their agency of collective power.

The other avenue to be taken deals with the changing of the form of the government in an effort to prevent the predation in advance. From time immemorial, men have also concerned themselves with this process.

Let us explore this avenue.

We have shown that fear is the basic emotional drive which leads men towards the establishment of government. Primitive governments have maintained their power largely by fostering fear.

Look where you will in the governments of our forebears and you will find men, clad with power, using terror and compulsion in order to maintain a hold over their followers. Thus, fear not only drives men to form governments but it is used within the government formed for the purpose of perpetuating that government.

Probably the most ancient form of government ever to come into existence amassed power and dealt with fear by claiming that the person in the government had been selected and appointed by divinity. For centuries it was this belief which provided confidence in government and kept it there — so long as people believed that their gods had a hand in its formation.

Men do not mind being ruled by gods.

They recognize their own weaknesses but, assured that divinity is actually conducting governmental affairs for them, they subside and become docile when they confront the politician clad in such glorious disguise. The record is full of stories of men who have gladly gone to their deaths under the impression that their deaths served a divine purpose. And this, for centuries, was the ne plus ultra of every politician.

Cunning rulers went in league with priests — the one, the embodiment of force, the other the embodiment of propaganda and superstition. It was a telling combination.

In point of fact, so well did this combination work that there are traces of it still apparent in our modern world. The Russian government, as an example, today combines the function of despot and priest, by organizing army, civil offices, schools, and even churches with the same kind of dual leadership. The general is flanked by the political commissar. Military decisions are buttressed with the party line. The government, in Russia, takes the place of God. To obey the Leader is to gain total approval. No contrary voice is permitted. Thought and action are blended into a consistent whole. Every action is made to follow the statist philosophy. And the statist philosophy is turned and twisted to match whatever actions are taken. History is rewritten after the fact, so that whatever occurs can be shown to be that which was predicted and planned.

There are evidences within our own government that the same process has much appeal in this country. This is especially true in the military, where the debacle of multiple defections during the Korean war has caused the ruling hierarchy to adopt a program of indoctrination which is calculated to make everything that the military attempts, correct, and everything that is correct, an action of the military.

There is also a general superstition among the voting groups that our political leadership cannot err. Whatever the leader decides is sanctified with general approval. The most banal and trivial decisions are exaggerated into being utterances of profundity. Even questionable policies are glossed over with the statement: “Our leadership is the best in the world. That leadership could not have come into being unless God had so willed it. Therefore, it is up to us, the citizens, to give immediate, unquestioned, and undeviating loyalty and obedience to every action of our political leadership.”

This is the “God wills it” of the ancients, scarcely altered with the passage of time and the enlightenment of the people. The superstitions which plagued mankind for generations still ride upon its shoulders in the guise of a majority decision only God could sanction.

It is frightening and a discouraging spectacle.


Chapter 12

 

Varying Forms of Government

 

Governments always come into being because men recognize their weaknesses as individuals. The very first government to be formed undoubtedly was that of a strong man, stronger than his fellows, who was called upon by his weaker followers to protect them against real and fancied dangers.

It was doubtless a dictatorship. Then, because the dictator in time grew old and feeble, and because he dreamed of bequeathing his power and authority to his own offspring, the monarchial system was born. The dictator, while at the height of his power, had convinced his followers that his ascendancy over them was divinely ordained. He could have told them that he was a son of a god. Thousands of early politicians maintained this fiction. And not a few of them were deified, either during their reign or after their passing.

The next step was for the successful dictator to claim that his family, the descendants of his loins, were also divinely ordained. Royal families came into being.

Thus, God and government were intermixed in the general opinion, and theocracy, the oldest and perhaps the most frightening of all governments, held sway for more than a thousand years.

We have already described this system. It provides for the combination of despotic power in the hands of a king with the power of superstition wielded by a crafty priest. Disobedience to secular authority became at once a blasphemy as well as civil disobedience. One does not defy God, even when God is unapproachable and his only avenue is the king who rules you.

But wherever these despotic pretensions were maintained, the people suffered. And, in the end, we shall see that it is the people, and not the politician, who are supreme. For, even when people believed largely that a god or many gods had established their ruling politician in office, they revolted against his tyranny and oppression. This is the history of man.

Everywhere we see men setting up governments, submitting to them, growing tired of the mounting oppression, and finally throwing off that yoke, only to acquire another. And each successive yoke represented an effort to do away with the evils of the prior form by establishing a better form.

We can think of no better statement covering this phenomenon than that written by Rose Wilder Lane in her great book, Discovery of Freedom. Here is what she says:

They replace the priest by a king, the king by an oligarchy, the oligarchy by a despot, the despot by an aristocracy, the aristocrats by a majority, the majority by a tyrant, the tyrant by oligarchs, the oligarchs by aristocrats, the aristocrats by a king, the king by a parliament, the parliament by a dictator, the dictator by a king, the king by . . . . there’s six thousand years of it, in every language.

Every imaginable kind of living Authority has been tried, and is still being tried somewhere on earth now.

All these kinds have been tried, too, in every possible combination; the priest and the king, the king who is God, the king and a senate, the king and the senate and a majority, the senate and a tyrant, the tyrant and the aristocrats, a king and a parliament. . . . Try to think of a combination; somewhere it has been tried.

Each of these efforts has been made with the most solemn and noble purpose. Always the aim has been to set up an organized collective which can and will use force against the enemies of a particular group, class, clan, nation, or family. Always the collective has amassed power and ended by using that power to harass and tax and oppress and regiment the very persons who set it up and gave it original obedience. There is no variation to this story. Nor is it possible to find a combination which has not been tried.

Let us now consider the American experiment, which was, without a doubt, the most noble and the most solemn ever undertaken.


Chapter 13

 

The American Experiment

 

When the American pioneers found themselves the victors after a war with England, they decided they must undertake the establishment of a form of government which was to be impervious to inner tyranny.

It is probable that at no other time or place in history had so many men, so well informed, so nobly motivated, ever convened for such a purpose. Few of the founders of our Constitution were politically ambitious. With high purpose and deep sincerity, they set about the task of providing a form of government which would stand the assaults of the mean and selfish.

They labored diligently and well. And when they finished, although they were far from unanimity, they had forged a document which was at once both wonderful and a political curiosity.

For the great distinction which set the American form apart from all others was that it was probably the most inefficient, cumbersome, and unwieldy government ever devised!

How well the founders knew that men with power could not be trusted. They set up a conflicting and enigmatic mechanism which was more notable for what it could not do than for what it could do.

There was an executive branch; but its functions were limited and contained. There was a legislative branch, equally frustrating. And, finally, a judicial branch, which was to watch the fulminations of the other two.

But this was not all. Having established three equal containers for power, they proclaimed that it was a federated government, with sovereignty residing both in the separate states and in the people generally. In short, what they had devised was not a government but the antithesis of government as it was normally contrived.

European politicians chortled with glee when they first heard the news. Here was an anti-rule rulership; a powerless powerhouse; a contradiction within an enigma. They opined that it would never work. However, a few elevated mentalities glimpsed the ideal our pioneers had striven to attain and gasped at its daring and immensity.

And in large measure the European politicians who ridiculed the form were right. The American government did not perform with efficiency. It wasn’t intended to. And the American people, finding themselves for the first time without a ruling despot, were hard pressed to know what to do. Consequently, unable to call upon their government for aid or guidance, they set to work themselves. Their energy, uncontrolled by living authority, changed the world. Their achievements, in a few short years altered all of history.

For the first time, freedom was proclaimed as a national policy, individualism was given full sway, and government was reduced to puppeteering functions.

It was delightful, while it lasted. Never was so much accomplished by so few, under such adverse conditions. Freedom was the big payoff. Men who do not have to kneel come to recognize divinity within themselves as individuals. Our ancestors were a stiff-necked lot. They bowed to none but God. Government could go hang for all of them.

We had done away with theocracy by delivering it a mortal blow. And even in our Bill of Rights it was ordained that the government could make no law affecting the practice of religion. Church and state were separated.

We had a republic which used a democratic process, which provided for a temporary aristocracy, which removed the priests, which put God into heaven and off the throne, which uncrowned the dictator or the king, which eliminated succession to power, and which generally disrupted every ordinary political practice.

For years it worked, because it didn’t do too much. Our power was in the hands of the people.

But our founding fathers had seen that what they had done, even though it was a mechanism shorn of much power, still contained the seeds of tyranny. Therefore they provided that as time passed, changes could occur. And at least some of them fondly hoped that, by permitting change, still further reductions in governmental protocol would come.

An informed populace could learn the fallacy of even this much power remaining. For if the people individually learned to overcome their weakness, what need had they for an instrument of force?

The changes, provided for, came in due course. But the changes were not in the direction our most dedicated idealists had desired.


Chapter 14

 

Sic Transit Gloria Mundi

 

We honor the authors of our Constitution and Bill of Rights. We admire them and pay them homage. More than any other group of men at a particular moment of history, did they comprehend the inherent dangers which inevitably come to the fore when men are clad with the robes of power and the insolence which officeholding breeds.

The founders of our government sought to nullify these dangers. They provided what we have called our system of checks and balances which deprive an officeholder of supreme and perpetual power.

Yet our founders were humble. They knew they were fallible and, therefore, they wrote up the amendment clause and inserted it in the Constitution. They fondly hoped others coming after them would surpass them in high purpose and in penetrating wisdom. How vain those hopes have been is now demonstrated.

For, since the days of our government’s origin, we have never equaled the character and purpose of those who set pen to paper to forge that basic charter. If there was one oversight of which our founders were guilty, this is it. They had too much faith in man’s ability to understand his own motives and principles. They failed to comprehend the extent of the venality and lassitude of politicians and ordinary citizens.

Yet, even here were warnings. Franklin said: “We have given you a Republic, if you can keep it.” And Jefferson, even in his first years in office, cried out against the mounting tendency of public and private citizens alike to look to the government to solve all problems.

In the end, the Constitution was overcome. Instead of remaining a system of checks and balances, our government has become overbalanced and predatory .The executive branch of the government is very largely ruling the land by means of bureaus and executive decrees. Congress still passes laws. But the decrees put out by the executive department, including treaties, outnumber congressional laws by more than four to one.

And the Supreme Court, instead of testing the validity of laws against the Constitution, has itself, in large measure, become a lawmaking body, enlarging its own functions and approving virtually every other action which enlarges government.

The policies expressed by the Chief Executive come into force and power either through Congressional enactment or via the backdoor route of the bureaus. Yet the bureaus are filled with appointees, none of them elected to office, and hence all of them beyond responsiveness when it comes to following the wishes of the people.

What we have yet to see in these United States is the fact that, in fine, the people will command. For government is always nothing but a tool. It takes human energy to employ any tool, even with automation. Somewhere there must be human minds and human energies directing each operation. And the people will not forever support and use that tool which exploits and misuses them.

So much for the American experiment. It was magnificent. But as a safeguard for human freedom and dignity it has been found wanting. Nor can we turn back to it with confidence that it will yet protect us. A wall once breached is no longer a wall. And with mounting political pressure all about us, the dyke with the hole has become a sieve.

Now we have explored both avenues of remedy taken by people who find their government no longer protecting them as individuals. We have discovered that a change of personnel provides us with no certain guarantee of freedom. And now we learn that even the greatest form of government ever devised has also proved inadequate. The reasons in both cases are similar.

Government is a tool. The nature of the tool is that of a weapon, a gun, a sword, a guillotine. And when people, be they politicians or otherwise, call upon a gun, a sword, or a guillotine to protect them from others, the device, willy-nilly, works two ways. It can be used defensively. But it is always used aggressively.


Chapter 15

 

Anti-Individual Device

 

Let us examine this idea. Why is it that government, designed for protection, always ends up by attacking the very persons it was intended to protect?

The reason is basic. Government’s power, as we have shown, comes from a compulsive unification of all peoples. Government speaks and acts for everyone. It cannot permit nonconformity.

The individual, at variance with governmental policy in any particular, becomes the target of government action, be he saint or sinner. Individualism is always opposed to collectivism. Any government is, by its nature, a collective.

“The best government,” said Jefferson, “is the government which governs least.” And following up on that thesis Thoreau exclaimed, “Then the very best government would govern not at all.”

And here we come to the nature of human beings. For the inescapable fact of human life is that people are different. Their fear may sire governments for purposes of protection. But what they fear varies from person to person. One man may fear a thief, another the tax collector. One man may shun canines and salesmen, another zoning regulations and the foreign born. Still another will have a veritable phobia about disease germs, whereas his opposite number will shudder principally over government questionnaires.

In the end, the government, seeking only to be a useful tool, will overreach itself and seek to protect both the unprotectable and those not wanting protection.

Its character is universal. If you do not fear disease, the government can, all the same, compel you to fear it. If you love canines and perhaps are yourself a salesman, the government can rule both out of order.

And thus we see the government is at once both protector and predator. It is not that governments begin in virtue only to end in sin. Government begins by protecting some against others and ends up protecting itself against everyone. This is the course of history.

We need only to look at taxation to see the universal flaw in every government. There is no government on earth that, now or ever, sold protection only to those who would willingly pay for it. Nor is there now or ever has been a government which permitted the purchasers of its service to decide just where the protection was to begin and end.

On the contrary, all governments always have and probably always will decide:
1) who is to be protected against what, and
2) how much each is to pay for that protection, whether it is desired or not.

Taxation, by definition, is compulsory. Whether or not you approve of a particular policy, practice, or program, and even if the policy, practice, or program is personally injurious to you, the government can and will compel you to pay for it.

For example: There are few Americans today who are in love with communism. Yet every American, by means of both direct and indirect taxation, is helping to spread the teaching of communism. An exchange agreement with the Soviet Union provides that a slick magazine, published in the U.S.S.R., shall be made available to readers in this country. Your money pays the shipping charges and helps to underwrite the cost.

But, at least this particular practice is a two-way street. There is an American counterpart, another slick, shipped to Russia and made available there. And the Soviet taxpayer pays at least some of the cost for this exchange.

But the matter goes much further than this. Communism, in essence, is not a Russian program but an economic program. It calls for the elimination of private property and private ownership. Yet your money is being taken from you — try to prevent it, if you will — and is being used in most of our schools, both private and governmental, to promote the idea that capitalism is both decadent and immoral, and that a sharing of wealth is the new economic order. This is communism. And the dissemination of this doctrine is being subsidized by the free enterprisers of America who are compelled at the point of a tax gun to pay all charges.

You cannot successfully object. You cannot with hold that portion of your taxes which would be used to underwrite this practice. Thus, your own money, via the hands of the government, is being used to undermine the very device by which you earned your money in the first place.


Chapter 16

 

Is There A Way Out?

 

When we are all through examining the logical and the illogical regarding government, we inescapably come up against an, as yet, insurmountable problem. Governments may be intrinsically evil; clearly they operate on the basis of tax predation. And with equal clarity we can discern that the collection of the tax money precedes the vaunted protection thus dearly bought. But the fact remains that human nature being what it is, a certain amount of protection of our lives and property is desirable.

The world is not an ideal place. The people who go to make up our world are, in the main, neither idealists nor saints. Criminals do stalk our streets; viciousness, selfishness, inconsideration, stupidity and worse are all about us. We cannot completely forego the right to protect one’s life and property.

Would that we could. But the facts of life are bloody, and in altogether too many instances an inability to protect ourselves defensively would simply encourage the rise of organized aggression.

Therefore, we come to an impasse. When government is employed as a protective device, immorality of necessity appears. But, should we forego protection, at least at this time and place, the immorality might conceivably be expanded by even more brutality and cruelty.

And though it may be true, and there are some who will argue the point valiantly, that we actually require far less protection than we think we do, the fact remains that something must be done, some tool provided, which will offset man’s belligerency, at least in individual cases.

Let us, then, state with certainty that some tool of protection must be found. And if we can find nothing better than government, cruel, rapacious, immoral, and unjust though it has proved to be in all of history, then, we must still have government.

However, let us suppose that we are able, by virtue of our advanced knowledge and by virtue of a renewed belief in moral verities, to devise a tool of protection which is superior to government. Ah, there is a thought to conjure with.

We have shown that government is a tool. But in this respect, though it may provide a necessary service, it is no more sacred than any other tool which also provides a necessary service. Government’s distinct character comes from the peculiar manner in which it attains to force and power. It derives this power from the compulsive unification of all persons below its exalted level. No other tool occupies this strange elevation. Every other tool of man’s devising is a tool which, if man can control himself, will become docile and tractable in his hands.

Government alone, of all man’s inventions, is capable of independent life. Government alone, like Mrs. Shelley’s terrifying creation of the monster born in Frankenstein’s mind, has the power and the ability to turn upon its creators and destroy them.

The question which must one day demand our finest intellectual efforts is: Can we invent or create a tool to protect ourselves from aggression without building into it so much power that ultimately it can turn against the very persons who create it and give it strength?

We cannot yet answer this question. However, avenues of procedure already suggest themselves as offering at least a partial remedy.

Is government the only device we know of self-protection? No, it is not. Voluntary insurance is another device. So are private policemen, private organizations such as the American Legion, night watchmen, merchant police, the Triple A and perhaps a score of others.

We have found, for example, that we can protect ourselves from fire with fire insurance. This does not prevent the fire from occurring, but it can indemnify us from loss in the event the unwanted holocaust occurs. And, similarly, if we hire a private policeman, a private watchman, or a private detective, these men cannot prevent a criminal tendency in the mind of another, but they can and will prevent a crime in some cases, and in others they can and do track down the criminal.

But can government do more? Quite frankly, it cannot. We could pass a law, but fires will continue to occur. We can establish expensive and expansive police departments, yet the criminal mind will still function in its own warped way.


  Chapter 17

 

The Voluntary Way

 

We must concern ourselves with morality. We have, for centuries, struggled to understand more about matter and more about technological things. We now know where to look for a reliable food supply. For ages this knowledge was not available.

We now know how to protect ourselves against extremes of temperature, both by shelter and by clothing. Additionally, we can, within limited areas, control the weather. We have deep freezes and we have roaring furnaces. Air conditioning is not new to us.

But as we look at the progress we have made as humankind, we find that chiefly we have concerned ourselves with material things. Materially, we stand at an advanced position as we compare modern living with prior barbarism.

But we have yet to break the barrier of immorality which surrounds us. We have yet to understand ourselves sufficiently so that we can protect ourselves from aggression in a wholly moral manner. And, if we can devote ourselves to this frontier ever before us, we may yet learn how to cross this invisible boundary and move our society into a completely moral setting. And this would be a fitting climax to the drama of human progress.

If only people would govern themselves. But, alas, they do not. If only people would believe in and practice the Golden Rule and the basic prohibitions of the Decalogue. But people, basically, neither believe nor practice. And even those who devoutly assay these moral heights fall dismally by the wayside.

Yet we do hold certain clues to a better moral climate. We know that men cannot be compelled to be good. They can only be prevented from being bad — a negative condition. We know from bitter experience that men cannot be forced into doing the wise thing, for such a forcement is foolishness.

Therefore, dimly we see that men can be good, but only when they wish themselves to be good. And through the fog and smoke of friction we can make out the fact that wisdom is possible only when the individual has learned to control himself. Great wisdom comes only with great self-discipline and great self-control. And experience, we learn from experience, is the very best and surest of teachers, though the cost is high.

So the word “voluntary” becomes suddenly of inestimable importance.

Men cannot be driven up a slope. But individually, voluntarily, men can and will assay the climb. Further, if their training is proper, if their education is sound, they will long for a moral world with all their hearts. If the longing is born in their breasts, they will inevitably seek the light. And if they do, their seeking will be voluntary and their progress, so long as it is voluntarily conducted, will be certain.

Again we look at insurance and private protective agencies. Have we fully explored all that these devices can perform? We do not think so. This is an age in which both government and insurance ideas have gained great expansion. But government leads the race, twenty to one. This age will probably yet be called, not the age of reason, but the age of compulsion. What reason we have found has led us, immorally, towards compulsion.

For example, we have two kinds of insurance, voluntary and involuntary. The first is purchased willingly by the buyer, because he feels that it is a good buy for him. The second is forced upon him by his government, whatever he thinks of it. The first is moral, the second is immoral. Yet the latter is gaining ground. Still, the very essence of immorality is found in the use some persons make of force in compelling others to do what some think they should.

And we have two kinds of police protection, voluntary and involuntary. The first is paid for voluntarily because someone wants protection and is willing to pay for it. The second is forced upon us all because some people feel we must have it. The first is moral, the second is immoral. Yet the latter is gaining ground.

So there is the great question. Can we yet establish a fully voluntary government . . . or, perhaps, to phrase it best, can we devise a tool for our protection which will be paid for only by those who want it, and in whatever amounts the payers deem best?


Chapter 18

 

What Can We Do?

 

We come, finally, to you. Individually, you are in difficulties, many of them probably not of your own making.

But, of course, in some way, you are responsible for all your difficulties, even when they have been thrust upon you. You, alone, can solve your own problems.

As a member of a community and as a member of a nation, you are in difficulties. Your various governments have taken your energies in the form of frustrating regulations and in the form of mounting taxation, until you stand today almost equated with the victim of a vampire. You are being drained. Let’s face it. You have been drained.

The government, you say, has done this to you against your will. This is true. But it is only partially true. For the government is still nothing but a tool of man’s devising and you, although you may deny it, have aided and abetted the condition in which you now find yourself. In short, you have, yourself, employed the tool for your own use, only to find that with each use the tool grew stronger and you grew weaker.

Isn’t it time you discovered this fact? Isn’t it time you learned that whenever you call upon the government to do something for you, the call you make is like food and drink for the bureaucracy? On your calls and your demands, it is nourished.

Without that nourishment it would not grow. It could not.

It is an inescapable fact that what your attention is upon flourishes because of your attention. If you love your home and your family and devote yourself to these things, do they not flourish? And if you turn away and deprive them of your attention, do they not wither, and perhaps ultimately depart?

If you love your business and your work, and devote yourself here, does not your business expand and your work multiply? And if you shirk your business and your work, will they not shrivel and perhaps ultimately turn to dust to be blown away by the winds of chance?

And if you look to the government as your great love, pouring your energies out upon it, coddling it, coaxing it, wheedling it, beseeching it, will it not blossom and wax fat and strong?

But in this latter case, because of its contradictory formation, the government never has anything of its own. It can only gain by your loss.

You can grow with the growth of your family and your home. You can grow with the growth of your business or your work. But you cannot grow with the growth of your government. You must shrink, and from the shrinkage the government grows.

You are on the threshold of a new world. This is true every day of the year and every year of your life. Can you and will you discipline yourself so that you will not employ an agency of coercion and affliction to compel others to support you in your fondest hopes and dreams?

Can you be content with minding your own affairs and living your own life? Or must you inflict your views and your opinions on others by using your agency, government, to compel universal support to your ideas?

Can you and will you raise your head in pride and honor and refuse to receive the slightest governmental “aid,” knowing that whatever it may be, it has been wrung from the energies of others?

Will you become a devotee of the American capitalistic system and give your energies to producing wealth and services on a voluntary basis? Will you turn your attention away from government, either as a big brother to help you, an employer to hire you, or a mailed fist to force others into your way of doing things?

The nature of man is such that he can rise to any height if he but will. The nature of government is such that, whatever strength it has, it will be used to amass greater strength by draining away the strength of individuals.

You, alone, can decide where you will stand. If you can and will be strong, the future is yours. If you cannot and will not discipline yourself, the future belongs to the government.

Thus we are confronted with the necessity for most serious introspection. Government is a tool, made necessary by man’s weakness. But in the passage of time man, through the employment of an enormous array of other tools, is no longer weak. Yet man clings to government as the first and most important requisite of organized living.

Admittedly, the worthy functions which government can and does perform are necessary. But it must be seen that government is not an end in itself, but a means whereby those functions of security and protection are vouchsafed to humankind.

The question which must be asked is this: Can man obtain the necessary mental objectivity to devise a modern tool, other than government, which will provide for his security and his protection without the evils which are inherent in any and every government ever devised? In a word, can man improve his tool of protection so that its destructive character is eliminated?

Is man, through fear, already addicted to the use of compulsion beyond the possibility of change? Or is it possible that man may now, in this century of much retooling, set up a protective device which will remain docile to his will; his servant, never his master?

Is modern man dedicated to the ax of force? Or can he exercise his unparalleled skill in tool improvement so that the primitive and prehistoric use of coercion is no longer a necessary adjunct to his own concept of power?

 

The Nature of Man and His Government

 

By Robert LeFevre — (1911 – 1986)

Originally published by The Caxton Printers, Ltd., Caldwell, Idaho (1959)

How To Advance the Cause of Liberty


By Robert LeFevre

 

How can one individual assist in maximizing human well being by advancing the cause of liberty? His first task is to learn his true nature.1. Each of us has the ability to think and act as he pleases.2. Each of us controls his own energy. We do it wisely or foolishly, but we do it individually. We may act on the advice or the command of others. Or we may decide not to. Our own energies remain under our individual command and control.3. It follows that I cannot make you free; I can earn my own freedom by controlling myself instead of trying to control others.4. What steps do I take when I wish to be free?5. I free myself from dependency on others when that dependency is created or maintained by force. Since there is no way that I can survive without the help of others, I will always be dependent to some degree. But I can depend upon the voluntary support others provide when they willingly buy my goods or services. If I have to compel them to buy my goods or services – either directly at the point of a gun, or indirectly through governmental avenues – then I am acting in a way that is counter-productive and anti-freedom.6. Having recognized this point, I break off all relations with government.a. I will make no contributions to any political campaign or political party.b. I will endorse no issue and no candidate.c. I will not vote.d. I will de-register and refuse to participate in government-sponsored proceedings of any sort.e. I will not run for office, nor hold a political job even if asked.f. I will patronize those persons and firms that have the least to do with government. If a firm or individual is heavily subsidized by the government, I will have nothing to do with it; it is an arm of the State.h. I will not ask for government help, guidance, advice, money, or emolument of any kind.i. I will accept no government check for Social Security, welfare, injury, pension, or for any difficulty I may be in. I will solve my own problems.j. I will set my own standards in such a way that I impose on no one.k. I will injure no one for any reason.l. I will be as generous and helpful to others as my ability makes possible.m. I will live up to every contractual agreement I voluntarily enter into.n. I will, therefore, take great care to only enter into those agreements that are worthy of fulfillment.o. I will be true to the highest and best within me, committing no act of theft, dishonesty, or violence against any other human whatsoever.

The foregoing are the rules. How many will follow them? Predictably, very few. That is why human society is in such upheaval. What I have set forth isn’t popular.

But it is factual and in harmony with the reality of man. The fact that I do not participate in government at any level and in any way does not cause the government to cease to exist. Should you reason your way through the human morass and decide to emulate the non-participation procedure, government will surely continue.

That, in itself, should cause rejoicing. The recommendations I have set forth provide a method that will be as gradual as the dawn of intellectual integrity. That is as it should be. Any other procedure will contain a reaction, a backlash that can destroy any temporary gains.

By employing the method of logic and learning, no one is coerced into accepting an unwelcome or misunderstood objective. He advances toward freedom and a free society in exactly the speed and to the degree that he is prepared for it. That is the only way it can be done. It will not be popular because we have been nurtured on the hopes of panaceas and quick political solutions. But it is the only way that will never have to be repeated.

Today the world is sick with the greatest social disease of all. It isn’t herpes or syphilis. It is, in fact, a pagan faith in the State. Around the world, terrorists are operating under the noses of various governments, often aided and abetted by those same governments.

We will move toward a free society, one by one. We will never achieve a free society in the sense that we can finalize the process. The price of freedom is eternal effort aimed at achieving self-control and self-mastery. We do not achieve this by controlling others. We move toward achievement when we learn to control and govern ourselves. Freedom is self-control, not license to impose on others.

It has taken me a lifetime to learn this. I am grateful that I have lived. I am even grateful that I have made mistakes, yet continued to live so that I could learn more. Man learns by trial and error. Few of us learn much of anything by success.

I am also grateful that some across this great country of America agree with at least some of my conclusions. They are out there now, quietly minding their own business, improving their own performance, raising their own standards, and willfully imposing on none.

– A WAY TO BE FREE: THE AUTOBIOGRAPHY OF ROBERT LEFEVRE, Culver City: Pulpless.com, Inc., 1999, Vol. II, pp. 496-498. Reprinted by permission of Tom LeFevre, email dated Feb. 1, 2011.

 

DOES GOVERNMENT PROTECTION PROTECT?


By Robert LeFevre

 

Society for Libertarian Life edition

Lecture at Santa Ana College on May 19, 1978

 

Introduction by Kenneth Grubbs, Jr.

Editorial editor of The Register in Orange County, CA

Describing one of his mentors, also one of our speaker’s mentors, William Buckley once told me that Frank Chodorov was pure as the driven snow. Buckley was speaking of Chodorov’s libertarianism, a philosophy so fiercely and exuberantly jealous of individual freedom that it refuses to be corrupted by politics, period, politics left or right, a philosophic feature which at once distresses and bemuses William Buckley. Chodorov’s generation of liberta­rians, and Robert LeFevre’s generation of libertarians, was almost forced by circumstances to be so pure. The days twenty and thirty years ago were black by freedom’s standards. Statism was fashionable and ever encircling.

It is said that Bob LeFevre, our link tonight with that generation, not only enunciated pure libertarianism but lived it as best he could, even to the extent when a fly bothered his table of placing a napkin in the insect’s path, gingerly to train it off the table, thence out of the way of human aggression. BobLeFevre was anti-SWAT even before the term was taken to mean certain police squads. That, ladies and gentlemen, is principle. Indeed a merry organization called Our People’s Underworld, which homes in on these od­dities blindfolded, so wanted to pay homage to this extraordinary consistency that it included in its museum Bob LeFevre’s one and only telephone call to the sheriff, about which, if we’re lucky, he’ll reminisce.

If Frank Chodorov was, in Buckley’s words, pure as the driven snow, then Bob LeFevre must surely be a blizzard, a benign blizzard to be sure, a blizzard not of obfuscatory words and bureaucratic gobbledegook but of blinding clarity and unsurpassed illumination. Very likely you will learn more about the crucial issues of our times tonight than you would were you to spend a semester in political science, upper or lower level. We find ourselves gravitating to Bob LeFevre’s light, those of us who have had our flings and even those of us who are still tempted to have our wild nights in the current welter of politics. It must have something to do with LeFevre’s uncanny powers of synthesis, of synthesizing the worst features of left and right and the best.

Bob LeFevre is a link to a founding generation, as I have said, harking back to Chodorov and Lane and Hoiles and Nock, even as that generation harked back to Jefferson and Paine. Think of it; that generation’s libertarians com­prised a handful of dedicated and thoughtful people. Today our name is not only libertarian but legion. It is worldwide. We have not only a Carl Oglesby drifting over to our island of solid thinking but you have the so-called New Philosophers in France, erstwhile Maoists and terrors of the Sorbonne, settl­ing on a basic anti-ideological, anti-political style of thinking, first cousins to the latter day libertarians Bob LeFevre has tutored. We’ve even reached an historic point when a newspaper editorialist can refer to Bob LeFevre and Timothy Leary in the same breath. It’s astonishing. Not only is this synthesis, it is testament to Bob LeFevre’s remarkable prescience. I remember con­versations with him a decade ago, myself then caught up in the American conservative youth movement. (Bob will tell you I never escaped, bless his purist heart.)

Even then he predicted the dizzying realignment of political forces. His clairvoyance was effortless. He knows better than most that the most durable division of humankind is that which separates those who in their hearts and minds yearn to control others and live their lives as nuisances and those who will be free. Is that oversimplification? Perhaps. Robert Benchley said that there are two kinds of people in the world: those who divide the world into two kinds of people and those who don’t. I think it’s extremely important, no less for our generation than for Bob LeFevre’s, to knife through such convoluted explanations of political events as we see today. Such tortured punditry usually arises from the need to avoid uncomfortable conclusions — namely that freedom works, that liberated men and women provide the most har­monious, the most orderly, and the most well – fed society feasible. Bob LeFevre’s freedom philosophy, this exceptionally gentle man’s philosophy, holds out limitless possibilities. Therefore, it is a thinking man’s joy. Please welcome Bob LeFevre.

 

 

DOES GOVERNMENT PROTECTION PROTECT?

By Robert LeFevre

 

Thank you very much, Ken, and ladies and gentlemen. If you can spare a copy of that, Ken, I’d like it because I’d like to look up some of the words and find out what you said.

Actually, I understood what you said, but I will do two things. One, I’m going to deny the story about the fly. That’s not true. But the story about the sheriff is true and I don’t mind telling you about it.

It was when we had the campus in Colorado and the plot of land that we had was sandwiched between two other privately-owned plots. The people be­hind us had no means of access to their property except by means of a road that went through our property and for which they had an easement. After a very severe winter, more or less normal for some of the high mountains in Colorado, the runoff precipitated floods which washed away the bridge span­ning the stream over which the access road went. Thus our neighbors behind us had no means of getting in or out of their property. I noted that fact and presumed they would do something about it. It was their task to keep the road in repair, mine to let them go back and forth. Well, my son notified me one day that there was some heavy equipment that had been moved in, and I figured itwould be used to replace the bridge.

And he said, “No, Dad, they are tearing into the bank on our side of the property line.”

I hastened to look, and my son was correct. Our neighbors were, in fact, encroaching on our land not merely by parking on it, but they were engaged with steam shovel and bulldozer in putting in an entirely new road on our land. I was emotionally upset. And I paced the room trying to figure out what in the world I could do. I didn’t want to get a gun, not because I wouldn’t hurt a fly, but I simply didn’t think that was the way to handle these things.

What could I do? Well, I finally succumbed. You’re right and whoever reported it was correct. I called the sheriff. The minute I dialed the number, my secretary said, “Who are you calling?”

And I said, “I’m calling the sheriff.”

And she said, “What?”

The tone of her voice and the look on her face shocked me so that when he came on the line all I was intending to say to him vanished from my mind. Instead, I said, “Do you have the phone number of the people who live behind us? I’d like to telephone them.”

He said, “Sure,” and gave me the number. That’s all I got from the sheriff.

Here’s the rest of it. I called my neighbor, introduced myself on the phone and said, “Do you understand what you’re doing? You’re back there on my land, tearing out some of my property and you didn’t even ask for permis­sion.”

There was a silence at the other end of the line and then: “Oh, my God, Oh my, Oh, Oh, ah yes, yes. Yes, of course, you’re right.” He said, “Oh, Mister LeFevre, you’re new in this area. Where I’ve put the road now is where it once was. But that was before you moved in and you would have no way of knowing that. I’m terribly sorry. Believe me, I’ll go right back and I’ll put everything back the way it was. We’ve taken out a few trees. I’ll replace them. I’ll put it all back the way it was. I wouldn’t have done this for the world.” He was practically groveling and I began feeling better and better.

Finally, my reasoning powers took over. One of these days I’d like to buy his property and the place where he was putting the road was exactly where I’d put it if I owned the property. He was probably saving me expenses later on. So instead of hanging up, I got over my hang-up and I said, “Mister Blank, now that you’ve been so nice and apologized I think we’ll just call it a draw. Why don’t you just go ahead doing what you’re doing.” It turned out to be a vast improvement. So there it is. You see how much need we really do have for the government in situations such as this.

Anyway, Ken’s introduction got right to the point as he so frequently does. I’ve talked to many people over many years and one of the big questions that is raised is how much government do we really need. Of course, a great many, I suppose fundamentally the conservative—those who think of them­selves as the rock- ribbed property-owning productive people—will say to me, “Well, there’s just one thing for the government to do and that is protect our lives and property.” Now, if I go outside the Orange County area, or any other area dominated by conservative thinking, I will find extensions to what the government has to do… “Of course, the government has to protect our lives and property but, in addition, put in the roads. After that, we’re allright.” Or “The government has to protect our lives and property and put in the roads and schools and provide us with tariff protection from trade with those other people who aren’t as we are because they work for less money than we do, and therefore, we have to have the government protect us from them.” And so it goes. The further away you get from Orange County, the more things you find government has to do.

Well, I deny I’m as pure as Ken says I am, but I try to take a position based on reason. And I try to be a realist about it.

 

A NUMBER ONE SUCCESS STORY

My question for tonight is: Does government protection protect? I think that is really the point.

We’re right in the middle of this big debate over Proposition 13 versus Proposition 8. I’m sorry that, at the moment, I’m not getting the kind of reaction I would like to hear from either side in the debate. Because while the proponents of Proposition 13 say they’re going to win, the proponents of Proposition 8 say they’re going to get even. If you vote for 13, they’re going to reduce the size of schools or cut them out. And they’re going to reduce police protection and fire protection. And, of course, the reaction I hear from the populace is “Oh, you can’t do that. We’ve got to have those things.” Now, if we were really for Proposition 13, what we would do when we heard these opponents say “if you take away our power to tax your property, we’re goingto close the schools” would be to laugh and say, “Swell, they deserve to be closed. We’re going to set up our own.” When they say, “We’re going to reduce your fire protection,” we ought to say, “Gee, that’s marvelous; it’s going to give us some great opportunities to make some money.” And we’ll call up the fire department at Scottsdale, Arizona, which is doing nothing but make money, and model our system along those lines. It’s a private system. It has been operating for about thirty years. It’s a number one success story.

And then when the opponents say we’re going to reduce police protection, we’ll talk about private protection. We’re going to take a look at that tonight. So let me move directly to that area.

 

LAWS OF REGULATIONNOT PROTECTION

Ladies and gentlemen, the desire for protection is probably the most deeply embedded conviction respecting government that most people have. Maybe more. It is a belief that you and I are helpless in matters relating to our own protection. And so we have to let government handle the problem. Now, were we to conduct any study on the subject, we would first of all discover that governments from time immemorial have never really said they were going to protect us. If you examine, for example, the Code of Hammurabi, which was drafted about 1750 B.C., you’ll find this ancient Babylonian lawmaker suggesting what has since become categorized as lex talionis, the laws of retaliation, not the laws of protection.

So the very first thing for us to do tonight is provide a definition for certain terms so we can be in communication. We have, in fact, become confused because of our dependence on government in this area. We’ve taken four or five ideas and lumped them together and called them protection. Let me identify the ideas. One: we think of retaliation as a part of protection. Two: we think of punishment as a part of protection. Three: we think of restitution as a part of protection. Four: we think of defense as a part of protection. And five: we think of protection as protection. We think of protection as including all five concepts. If we are going to understand our subject, we will have to analyze each concept clearly and carefully.

I’m going to use the word protection to mean just one thing. I’m going to define the word and I’m deriving the meaning from the roots of the word itself to mean that when you are protected, in fact, you are safe. Nothing happens to you. Never mind whether anybody wants to hurt you or not; if you are protected, you aren’t hurt.

In your mind, think of the word protection as meaning safety. I’m going to submit, ladies and gentlemen, that safety is really what you and I want. We would like to be safe in our persons and property. We don’t want to be injured. We are sensitive creatures. We experience pain if someone thrusts a knife into us, shoots a bullet into us, or even swats us. We don’t like those things to happen. So we want to be protected because we want safety. I think we should be protected.

The word retaliation does not mean protection. Retaliation, in fact, is as far removed from protection as competition is removed from monopoly. If you have to retaliate or if you believe you do, it proves that you weren’t protected. These are mutually exclusive terms. You cannot have them both at the same time. You either are protected or you aren’t. If you aren’t, then you may have been hurt. After your injury, then maybe you could retaliate. But there is no way you can retaliate if you haven’t first been hurt. And if you didn’t get hurt, then you can’t retaliate. Is anyone having problems with that? Okay, fine.

Now what is punishment? Punishment is something inflicted on someone by an authority over him like his mother, his father, or Big Daddy State or whatever. Of course, we have masochists who inflict pain on themselves, claiming they enjoy it. So pain is not really punishment from their point of view. The word punishment itself means the infliction of unwanted injury, harm, pain, something unwelcome upon someone by someone else who has somehow managed to get into an authoritative position. This is not protec­tion.

Now restitution. Restitution means that something taken away from you is restored. That isn’t protection, either.

And defense. Defense is what happens in the heat of combat when some­body hits you and you hit him back hoping to curtail further blows. Defense means an actual combative situation with both sides engaged in essentially the same thing. Defense isn’t the same as protection. It is the first step toward retaliation when protection is inadequate. The Arabs have a proverb that “All wars begin with the second blow.” Clausewitz says, “Every act of war is an act of retaliation.” I hope to stay away from defense as much as I can although I don’t mind getting into it. Because, after all, if we’re going to talk about protection, we may have to open it up.

Now, ladies and gentlemen, I submit that you do not want to retaliate, that you really don’t want to punish anybody, that you don’t even want to defend yourself, and you don’t want to receive restitution because you’d prefer to be in a position where nobody has to make restitution to you. That all of thosethings are undesirable in terms of what you really want. What you really want is protection. And if you have protection, in fact, the rest of this becomes academic. If you’re protected, in fact, we can put the questions of defense, restitution, punishment and retaliation aside.

It all comes down to protection. The question is: Does government protec­tion protect? Through long dependence on the government, we have become guilty of lump-think. We lump all these concepts together and we call it all protection.

 

BASE FOR COMPARISON

Now I’m going to show you just how well the government protects you. (Holds up several books.) I have been making a collection of these little goodies for a number of years. These are the United States Federal Bureau of Investigation Uniform Crime Reports that are issued every year. And I have a shelf full of them. I have them going clear back into the 1940’s. I have gotten one every year for all that time. Now, I brought with me tonight just a few because I didn’t want to be excessively burdened.

I have the 1970 Uniform Crime Report, 1971, 1972, 1975, and 1976. And I’m going to show you what the FBI says their record is in handing crime or in protecting you from the bad guys. Okay, the so-called bad guys.

I still use the 1970 Report for a number of reasons. One of these is the last report that the FBI has put out that has within it a ten-year composite study. I’m hopeful that in 1980, they will come up with another ten-year report. I think the room is small enough so I can hold this up and if you have good eyes, you ought to detect the direction of these curves.

Now, that is a ten-year study of how the government has been fighting crime. From 1960 to 1970, in that period of time, crime in all categories in the United States went up 176 percent. The rate went up 144 percent as opposed to a population increase of 13 percent. Now, ladies and gentlemen, that means that according to the FBI figures, crime in all categories in that ten-year period went up better than ten times faster than the population.

Inside, if you care to read these dreary things, you will discover that actually the increase of crime at the particular time, instead of taking place in the areas where the population was expanding, was taking place in the suburbs basically and not in the so-called ghetto areas. Now, it fluctuates back and forth, but at this time, it was taking place in the suburban areas. So that clearly the rate of increase of population has no necessary connection to the crime rate. What is shown over many years is that population density and population growth had no necessary connection with the incidence of crime or crime growth. Population growth and the growth of crime fluctuate. Nothing that I know of can tie them together in any kind of cause and effect relationship. So that’s the statistical story of crime, in general.

Now, crimes of violence over the same ten-year period—up 156 percent. Crimes against property for the same ten-year period—up 180 percent. That’s the ten-year study. I’m going to refer back to that book later on.

Just to be sure that the impact of what the FBI says reaches you, let me sum it up this way. First, let me make an explanation. Nobody, including the FBI, says these figures are accurate. They are bound not to be accurate for the reason that all we have here are the crimes that have been reported. Obvi­ously, many crimes are not reported. Additionally, there is bound to be some increase in crime every year as long as the legislators stay in session. There is bound to be, because every time a new piece of legislation is enacted,somebody is bound to trip over it. And, of course, when you trip over it, you’ve violated a law. And that’s going to classify you as a lawbreaker, hence a criminal. You might be a minor criminal but that depends on how badly the legislature wanted that particular piece of legislation. The fact remains that nobody says that these figures are accurate. There is one merit that these reports have and it makes them the best information that we have that comes out regularly in the country. Or at least it did until currently. They are uniform. These are uniform crime reports. Consequently, whatever errors are made are made consistently. So we have a base for comparison if nothing else.

 

PYRAMIDS AND THE WRONG DESTINATION

To be sure that the impact of my point is not lost, let me offer an analogy. I so often find that when I’mtrying to make a point with some of my students that if I hammer away at a given idea, I sometimes hammer their minds closed. I don’t mean to do that. Sometimes when I approach something from an angle it is easier to see.

Let us suppose that all of us here in this room work for a moving and transfer company. Let us suppose also that we are good. In fact, we are so proud of our work we have emblazoned on the sides of our trucks a motto which reads “WE CAN MOVE ANYTHING MADE BY THE HAND OF MAN.” And we do a lot of business. One day we are approached by a potential client from Egypt and he says, “Is that true? Can you really move anything made by the hand of Man?”

And we say, “We think we can. What do you have for us?”

And he says, “Well, we have an idea in Egypt that were we to move the Great Pyramid of Giza from its present location to a few miles north of Cairo, it would be a better tourist attraction. Money’s no object. We’ve got money. So we’d like to move the pyramid. Now you understand, it has to be moved intact because, you know, that thing wasn’t put together with cement. Those blocks are loose. They just fit. We don’t want any vibration. Can you move it as one piece without damaging it and set it up 25 miles north of Cairo?” The entire distance, we’ll imagine, for purposes of this illustration, to be one hundred miles. “Can you move it?”

Of course, we start to laugh about this time and say, “Well, of course, we can move it but you realize that this is going to cost you.”

And our client says, “Money is no object. We really would like to get it moved. Can you give us a fixed bid?”

And we say, “Well, sure, we can do that. We’ll send a team of experts over and get you a quotation.” So we get our best team and we send them to Egypt. And they spend six months over there measuring, calculating, and doing all of the things necessary. And then the team comes back and they say, “You’re not going to sell this one. It can be done, but it’s a massive job.” And they describe all of the problems. And they say, “The cost is going to be one billion dollars; that’s a thousand millions. That is a great many dollars. So your client’s going to turn you down.” And we say we think so, too, but ho ho, we’ll try it. We give the quotation to our client.

And he says, “It’s no problem. Go ahead. Here’s your billion dollars.” We design the equipment, go to Egypt, tie onto the pyramid and tug for a year. Then we get out and measure and discover we are 125 miles from the destina­tion. Our client asks, “What went wrong?” And we say. “We underestimated the job. It’s going to take more money than we thought. We need two billion more on top of the one you gave us. Why don’t you drop it?” But our client says, “No, we want it moved. Here are the two billion. Move it.”

And we say, “Yes, sir.” And we hook on and pull for another year and we get out and measure and we are 175 miles from our destination. And we repeat the process the third year and find we are 300 miles away from where we want to go. Would you begin to think you’re doing something wrong? Well, that is what we are doing with protection.

 

LAWS OF RETALIATION

Let me show you, if I can, the system that we have. The system that we have is based on the Code of Hammurabi which didn’t work well even then and is not working well now. It’s lex talionis, the law of retaliation. I’m going to explain a little more about it, but I want you to get the picture. Here’s the way we do it.

The first act in this little drama is this. You and I are afraid that there are some kooks out there who could hurt us. And I’ll tell you something. It’s true. So we’re afraid of that. We feel completely inadequate and the government, of course, has been telling us for years that we’re inadequate about every­thing except earning a living so they can tax us. We authorize the creation of government and the very first thing the government does is to perform an act of major predation. Isn’t this nice? And by major, I mean it involves every­body in the territory over which the government holds sway. It goes out and rips off everybody so that it can get the money together so that nobody will rip you off. That’s the first act.

After that is performed, the next act is a private one. I’m going to call it minor predation. Not because the act isn’t serious; it could indeed be murder but the numbers of persons involved are necessarily few. And, therefore, it is minor as opposed to major in the sense that it involves all. So this act occurs in spite of what we’ve done to forestall or prevent it.

Now after that has happened, the third act in our little drama — also provided by the government — is an act of minor predation in which the government goes out, tries to find the person responsible for act two, once in a while succeeds, brings him in and tries him, hopefully convicts him and then punishes him. That’s the system. That’s the way we have it set up. I call the third act minor because the only people suffering here are either the crimi­nals themselves or those who were mistakenly in the wrong place at the wrong time and are taken to be criminals and those closely associated. But it’s minor in the sense it doesn’t touch all of us. Another act like act two.

Okay, and then we go to act four, this one also provided by the government. We have another act of major predation as the government goes out a second time and steals from everybody in the area to get the money to pay for the services rendered in act three. Take a look.

You and I are worried about act two. We’re worried about being privately injured. As a result of that worry, we authorize this and this and this (acts 1, 3, and 4). And private injury not only happens anyway, it happens with increas­ing frequency the more of government we authorize. The government’s own figures confirm it. Now study that a bit, concentrate on it, and see if you can come up with a worse system if you tried. You can’t win here for losing. This is a disaster. It’s worse than I’ve let on. Oh, believe me, this is incredible. I’ll give you a few further insights just to give you an idea how successful the police are.

I’m going back to the Uniform Crime Report of 1970. In 1970, ladies and gentlemen, there were 2,169,300 burglaries in the United States. That’s just burglaries. It has gone up since then. The losses total $672,000,000. Now, get these figures. Nineteen percent of the burglaries were solved by the police, 9 percent were convicted, 3 percent served out their time or are still serving time.

Now, do you see the implications? That means if you’re a burglar, you have an 81 percent chance of doing your burglarizing without being caught, a 91 percent chance of not being convicted, and a 97 percent chance of not having to serve out your time. That’s better odds than you can get in Vegas if you own the casino.

Admittedly, burglary is one of the most difficult areas for the police to deal with. I’ll explain why in a moment.

Let me give you the corresponding figures in the area where, strangely, the government has been improving fantastically. In fact, I’m going to the area where they used to be the worst and are now getting better. They’ve made great strides in apprehending murderers. Of course, they can’t catch the Hillside Strangler and lots of others.

Their records indicate there is a 21 percent likelihood of arrest; their rate of conviction and punishment is about on a par with burglary.

You can take a relatively comfortable position, put all crime together and say the police are successful 20 percent of the time, from a low of 19 percent to a high of 21 percent. Twenty is a comfortable middle which means the police are unsuccessful 80 percent of the time.

Now I want to make this point clear. I am not engaged in attacking the police. I think something could be said in that area. It is not my purpose to vilify the police officer. I have met many of them. You do find a few slant-browed, long-fanged Neanderthals but the bulk of them are actually very nice fellows. Mostly, they’re pretty honest and they’re carrying on a tough job. So we don’t have to be down on them. They simply can’t do the job they’re hired to do for reasons which will emerge as we proceed.

Let’s get back to one of the points I was originally making to show the difference between protection and retaliation.

What you want is protection. You want to be safe. What the government does is to try to retaliate after the fact. I know it’s comforting to believe that if somebody rips of your television set the cops will find it and bring it back. It’s comforting to believe that. And once in a while it happens. The police are usually not there when the theft occurs. There’s an old adage that says the police are never around when you want them. We laugh about that and conclude that the police are not very sharp. Don’t blame the police. Very few crooks perform with a police audience. And because the police wear distinc­tive clothing and carry noisemakers and have flashing lights, you can see them as far as you can see. Therefore, there’s no point in performing a criminal act when the criminal knows the police are in the vicinity. So he waits and the police will leave presently. Then he performs the crime. That is why the police have a great deal of difficulty in catching people after the crime is committed. Because—and you can ask them—they don’t know who did it.

 

POLICE ARE NOT MAGICIANS

I’ve had some experiences which illustrate the point. One time at the Gazette Telegraph in Colorado Springs, somebody threw a boulder through two of our big glass doors. In due course, the police arrived and made all the appropriate inquiries. There were two policemen with guns. They were ready. We had the rock in the lobby. The officers took notes and then they looked at me and said, “If you ever find out who done it, tell us and we’ll be glad to pick him up.”

What did you expect? Police are not magicians. They’re good people but they weren’t there when the crime took place. I wasn’t there. The only one there was the crook. This is one of the reasons the police record is not really scintillating.

Despite the difficulties the police have in acting after the fact, they once in a while have success: twenty percent, give or take a fraction either way. That’s remarkable in itself. Twenty percent. A very difficult twenty percent. Of course, we’re talking about crimes where restitution could be made. Some­body steals my TV set; there are other TV sets. I could get one back. Money could be returned, theoretically, at least. It’s possible.

But what about a really serious crime, an irreversible crime, a crime for which restitution is impossible. Don’t tell me the joys of catching the man who murders my wife. I don’t want the man who murders my wife because I don’t want my wife murdered. What do you want me to do with him? If I have to collect people, I’d like to collect nice people. I don’t want to collect murder­ers.

I don’t want my wife murdered. I want her to be safe.

Don’t tell me the joys of catching the fellow who rapes my daughter. I don’t want my daughter raped. What do you want me to do with him, rape him? I don’t want him.

What about the man who kidnaps my son? I don’t want to catch him. I want my son safe from being kidnapped. These are the serious crimes. I’m not suggesting that theft is not serious. But I mean irreversible crimes, crimes where restitution is absolutely impossible. Don’t tell me that the system we have is going to work.

The system can’t work unless it involves protection. What do you want to do, punish somebody because they have done some terrible thing?

I submit that what you really want is to stop the terrible things from occurring before they happen. You don’t want to be hurt. You want to be safe. I hope you do. If so, I’m with you.

I can’t run as fast as I used to and I’m getting brittle so I break easily. Really, I want to be safe.

And restitution. Nay, I want to be safe to start with. And may I point out, if we have protection, in fact, retaliation is impossible. Restitution is impossi­ble. The question of restitution or retribution becomes academic. What we need is protection.

 

GOVERNMENT POLICE & TRAINING

The government never said it was going to protect anyone. Oh, maybe currently some of the politicians tell you that. But all anyone has to do is examine the facts. Government is a bunch of rules which say that if you break them, government will hurt you. It’s not going to prevent these rules from being broken. Government is designed only to retaliate and is successful only 20 percent of the time.

Now, people, protection is easier than retaliation. You can have a higher achievement average if you understand what protection is than if you try to operate on the basis of retaliation.

How do we protect? Again, what I’m getting at is that the government never said it was going to protect you. And I must make an additional point here. Because the government isn’t organized to protect you, you are the bait in the trap. You have to be hurt before the government can do anything. Think how dreadful it would be if the government acted before the crime by arrest­ing people before they’d done anything wrong.

I don’t know how many of you have attended a police training session where ordinary, decent human beings are made into policemen. If you ever at­tended one of these sessions, I think you’d find what I am about to say familiar.

The sergeant in charge of training addresses himself to the men who are called rookies. And he demeans them for a moment, making them feel very bad and then he says, “Now I want you to get this straight. If you ever do get out of this police academy and become policemen, your job is to enforce the law without fear or favor. We don’t want policemen here who like some laws and dislike others. That’s not your business. Your business is to go by the book. You learn what the laws are and you enforce them and you enforce them all the way up and down the line. Which means if your wife, your mother, your sweetheart, your daughter, or your best friend is caught violat­ing the law, you book them and bring them in.”

Now, you will find every policeman taking that training. He’s got to take that training to be a policeman.

 

POLICEMAN’S DUTY

 The proper relationship between persons is a market relationship which follows what we call the law of supply and demand. In fields of protection, you and I are the demanders and we find people who are suppliers who can provide protection. You go to the store to buy it. The fellow who has the store says. “My system works. It’ll cost you so much, and it will accomplish this much. I also have another system that will do this much more and accomplish this much more, and it will cost you this much more. And this third one works this way, accomplishes this, and it will cost you this. Which one do you want? My systems are guaranteed; they will do what we say they will do.”

Suppose you buy a private system, install it and it doesn’t work. You can have a guarantee and you can get your money back. But, notice something. The man who is dealing with you doesn’t look at you and say, “I can’t sell this until I’m sure you’re not a crook. How do I know what you want to do with this device? You can’t have it because I have to check upon you. I don’t trust you.”

(Using chalkboard)

Here’s what we get with the government in the picture. Here’s the govern­ment, and here are you and me as taxpayers. And we say to the government, “We want to be protected.” The government says, “Sure,” and they hire the police and the police are here. And what do they tell the police? They say, “You take a look out there where those taxpayers are and remember that every one of them is a potential crook.”

The police aren’t hired to protect you. They’re hired to keep an eye on you to see what you did that was wrong so that they can book you. That’s their function. They are not protectors. They are not hired to be protectors. They are hired to keep an eye on all of us as potential criminals. Now, do you think they’re going to make you safe? They weren’t hired to make you safe.

A friend of mine has a van and keeps his tools in it. He has rigged it up with a burglar alarm, by the way. But before he put the alarm, on it, this little event occurred. He parked it in a parking lot and left it unlocked because he was just going to talk to somebody right in the parking lot. So the van wasunattended and, of course, he’d left the back door open because he planned to be right there. But one thing led to another, and he moved several yards away. He looked back as he was engaged in this conversation and a total stranger was lifting one of his cases of tools out of the van. He ran back and said, “Wait a moment. That’s my stuff.”

Right at this particular time, he happened to see a policeman. So he called for help. The policeman came over and here was this man holding my friend’s set of tools. And my friend said, “This man just got into my van and helped himself to the tools.”

The policeman looked at the fellow and the fellow said. “That’s not true, officer. These are my tools. I was walking across the parking lot and this man accosted me and claimed the tools were his.” The policeman said, “Are the tools marked?” It happened that none of them were. So the policeman looked around and said, “I don’t know which one of you is telling the truth. But the way I see it, you’ve got the tools and you haven’t.” And the thief walked off with the tools under police protection.

How did the policeman know who owned the tools? He didn’t know. Natur­ally, when you’re the owner you feel a sense of outrage. But what would you do? Well, since then, my friend has taken care of it. It isn’t going to happen again.

This is the point I’m trying to make. The police are not hired to protect you. They are there to enforce the law and what you want is to be safe.

 

UNIFORM CRIME REPORT—FBI

 What I have here is a record going back to 1970—the F.B.I. 1970 Uniform Crime Report. But first, let me show you the 1971 book and these others because I think you ought to see them.

1971 provides a five-year record. Naturally, those lines don’t seem to go up as rapidly but the reason is this graph provides only a five-year base. And the crime from 1966 to 1971 went up 83 percent against a population increase of 5 percent. Now if you double that for ten years, it’s approximately the same as the ten-year chart. Crimes of violence up 90 percent, crimes against property 82 percent; that’s the 1971 story. Now, a slight variation once in a while. And the criminologists, the penologists, the scholars who are studying this are now beginning to tell us there is a reason for it.

You notice that in 1972 there was, in fact, a downturn. In 1972 crime in all categories diminished slightly. Of course, the average for five years is still up. But that year it declined; it was actually still up on violent crime but it went down on crimes against property sufficiently to bring the average down in 1972. That happened once before and the criminologists said, “We don’t understand it; we don’t know what caused it.” But now they’re beginning to come up with an idea on it. After that improvement we got in 1972, it almost looks as if the criminals had just taken a sabbatical and come back with greater enthusiasm than before. Because they made up for lost time and went right back up to where they would have been if they hadn’t slackened off.

And I must give you the sad news. This is the last report out, 1976. The 1977 report comes out in August or September of 1978. They’re always behind in Washington.

But now we have the Carter administration and do you know what they say? They say, “We are not going to be doing them—the Crime Reports—the same way after this. Instead of tabulating the known crimes (because we know that they’re not accurate), we are just going to estimate.” If this is done from here on, the reports will be worthless. Absolutely. They weren’t much good to start with but from now on—zilch. I wanted you to get that picture. So there have been a couple of occasions in American history where the crime rate has gone down slightly. What was the extent of crime in the United States in 1970?

I have to make a very careful delineation at this juncture. One of the tragic things that we face all the time is that people tend to equate the law or legislation passed by lawmakers with what is morally correct. And so there’s a tendency to believe that what is right is what is lawful. And what is wrong is unlawful. If it’s against the law, we assume it’s wrong and if it is in harmony with the law, then it must be all right. Ladies and gentlemen, there’s no necessary connection.

We have to make a distinction. This is not a distinction made by the F.B.I. But we must make it. There are types of crime. There are some crimes in which some person was injured as a result of another human being violating his boundaries in some way, either his person or his property, and inflicting an injury by theft, mugging, rape, murder, whatever. So an injury was inflicted. And then there are some crimes that are merely violations of some legislative enactment where nobody was injured at all except perhaps the dignity of some piece of paper. That’s all. Now, the government doesn’t make a great deal of distinction here.

There are various categories but when it comes to, for example, the differ­ence between a bank robber and a man who doesn’t pay his taxes; the gov­ernment sees no significant difference. The government will tell you a man who doesn’t pay his taxes is essentially a thief. He is robbing the government. Now, that’s the government’s point of view. I don’t happen to share it and I don’t think many of you do. But that is actually what they will say so they will treat a tax evader with exactly the severity they would a bank robber. Fromtheir point of view, he’s done the same thing. He has taken money belonging to others. Okay, now, I wanted to get that into the record because of these two very definite classes of crime, the class of crime where there are injuries and the class of crime where crimes are crimes only because the government says they are.

 

THE CRIME REPORT

Going back to the 1970 book then, let us list the kind of crime that we had and the cost in terms of dollars, in the United States. The total cost of crime, according to a study that was performed by U.S. News and World Report in 1970—and there has been no composite study of equal merit since then—the total cost of crime in that year was $51.1 billion.

I’m going to make the breakdown I told you about. First. I’m going to talk about real crime where injuries are inflicted. The largest category in the United States is business theft; that is to say, theft from employers per­formed by their employees—that’s the number one category. And it has been for a number of years and it is the number one today. This is a sad commen­tary on what is happening in this nation. There is such, an anti-business, anti-capitalist mentality in the land that a businessman is viewed as fair game by a great many of his employees. They simply take advantage of him at every opportunity. And they don’t think it’s wrong. Some of it is petty. They will steal a few stamps, some pencils, paperclips. They put a little gas into the car from the company pump and they don’t report it. They pad their expense accounts. In fact, that’s almost a new form of literature in the United States, the padded expense account. They do anything and everything against the boss and they think nothing of it. If you work for a grocery store, you take out a half a ham or half a case of peaches, stick it in the car. If you work at a machine shop, you take a few tools or maybe a few machine parts. And it goes on and on. Additionally, we’ve actually found whole rings of thieves profes­sionally operating within given plants and just fencing the material the firm is making or handling. Business theft is a big item. And it was the largest in the United States in 1970. The figures today would be larger but then it was $3 billion. All of these numbers will be in billions of dollars.

The second largest crime in 1970 was homicide, $2.1 billion. Now, how is that figured? Obviously, one cannot calculate the value of a human life accurately. Nobody said these figures were accurate. The victim’s earning power based on his educational background or his business experience, whatever it may have been is estimated. Then “the loss to society” from the date he was eliminated is calculated. Thus, if a person was relatively young at the time he was murdered, the loss to society is great. If he was past 65—boys will be boys. Of course, now it’s going to be past 70 because they’re changing retirement laws. But that’s the general idea, so the loss is calcu­lated dollar-wise based on the anticipated earning power of the deceased. To which is added hospitalization costs in the process of becoming deceased or any insurance payouts which are also added. It came to $2.1 billion. (Q. Do your figures include court costs? A. No, that’s separate. I’ll show them as I have them.)

Robbery and burglary, listed as a single crime, came to $2 billion. Of course, business theft is also robbery and burglary but it’s separately classed.

Then we have drunk driving. Not that the driving is the problem. It’s stopping in the wrong way. And when that happens it can be a very costly affair. Not only automobile damage but manslaughter and other property damage is included here, $2 billion. Then we have fraud and embezzlement, and that’s $1.5 billion. And we have vandalism, $1.1 billion. Hijacking is $900 million. And shoplifting is $500 million. Notice, most of these are theft or robbery of one kind or another, but they give them special categories. And this, of course, adds up to $13.1 billion.

You will notice that they have not included mugging or rape. The reason is that they couldn’t figure out how to put a dollar value on them. So we don’t have it in dollars. The F.B.I, keeps an eye on it, but we don’t have a dollar value, so take a mental note. It’s bigger than this by the cost of those particu­lar crimes.

So that is the total cost of crime where there were victims as opposed to the total cost of crime. I submit that those numbers are widely apart, $13.1 billion as opposed to $51.1 billion.

Now, let me show you where the government feels the big problem is. You’re going to love this first one. Gambling: number one crime in the United States. Oh, not just gambling—illegal gambling. This doesn’t include Los Alamitos or the state of Nevada: anything that’s legal doesn’t count. This is illegal gambling. Hang on. Fifteen billion dollars—bigger than all of these put together. Bribery of officials, $5 billion. (Q. Does that include government officials? A. These are the only ones that are reported.) Obviously, it’s bigger than this, but these are the only ones that have been reported. I’m sure I don’t have to tell you if the officials weren’t there, you wouldn’t have to bribe them.

Who was it? Professor Buchanan, University of Virginia, has done a study showing that if you had a government in which bribery became impossible, nothing would work. You have to be able to bribe government people to get the wheels to turn around because they’ve so many legislative enactments that freeze everything shut you have to grease the wheels. Fortunately, we are not likely to run into that kind of government where bribery doesn’t occur. You just have to be careful.

Narcotics, $2.2 billion. All of these figures are dated. They go to 1970. Let me pause for a moment to take up this question of narcotics because I would be very happy to be on the record with you as being strongly opposed to the use of hard drugs. I think hard drugs are bad news. And I would like to see this practice of using hard drugs reduced as rapidly as possible. Therefore, I must urge that we get the government out of this area as fast as we can in order to control it. Here we have a very serious problem.

 

DEMON RUM & THE 18th AMENDMENT

Ladies and gentlemen, there is no reason for us to be confused in this area. We, of all people, have had experience. And it should have come to our minds when we were getting all uptight in this area a matter of ten, fifteen, twenty years ago.

May I recite just a very little history of the United States? Earlier in this century, during the ‘Teens, a group of very well-intentioned ladies decided that alcohol was a dangerous substance and it ought to be forbidden. The men of the country were too weak-willed to resist the temptation of demon rum. Therefore a law would have to be passed to protect their helpless wives and children. For the husbands were getting paid on Saturday, stopping at the saloon on the way home, and then the rent money wouldn’t arrive home with them.

Therefore, to protect the helpless wives and children, a law would be passed to prevent the manufacture, sale, and distribution of alcoholic bever­ages. Now, these ladies were, of course, marvelously well intentioned. And there’s no question but that alcohol is a dangerous drug. It is not a food. It is apreservative. When you drink it you do not get nourished, you get pickled. That’s the way it works.

So the ladies decided to do something about it and they raised quite a bit of money and made quite a bit of noise. In process, they were joined by another equally splendid group of men, a ministerial organization, who likewise went out and thumped the drum to get money and to get the 18th Amendment passed, while they were in the midst of this brouhaha getting everything revved up, what should happen but a nice supply of money came in from out of the country. And they were able to put the whole thing across. The 18thAmendment was ratified in 1918.

Where do you think that nice lump of money came from? It came from Sicily. Why do you suppose the people in Sicily wanted to see us ratify the 18th amendment? Well, it’s called profit. You see, if you can get an addictive drug—and alcohol can be an addictive drug—forbidden, against the law, then there are people—we sometimes refer to them as Mafia, or the Syndicate, or whatever affectionate term we have for them—who don’t mind breaking the law. A legitimate businessman does. If you make alcohol illegal, the legiti­mate businessman goes out of business and the Mafia comes in. And they don’t mind dealing with the police; they either bribe them or shoot them. To the Mafia it’s a matter of indifference either way. So the policeman is handled and now the one thing the Mafia can’t handle he doesn’t have to. The govern­ment’s handling it for him. The thing the Mafia can’t stand is competition. But the government can handle the competition so the Mafia would like to have it that way. With no competition, they come in.

I see that there are probably a number of people in the audience tonight who can remember the happy days that followed the ratification of the 18th amendment. I was around at the time and I presume some of you may have been. Let me just remind you that prior to 1918 we had, in the United States, one of the lowest per capita consumption rates of alcohol in the world, one of the lowest. We were, indeed, a sober nation. Our sobriety was almost Victo­rian. We were, really, a little bit prissy in that area.

But let me remind you what the situation was. Saloons were almost as plentiful then as filling stations are today. The “corner” saloon. You didn’t say the saloon, you said the corner saloon because the chances were good that there was a saloon every few blocks. It was on the corner where you could get at it from either direction fast. Now, what about the liquor that was sold in the saloons?

In those days you could go into the corner saloon and for five cents you could buy a bucket of beer, the finest brew made, and while you were drinking it the bartender would have sandwiches on the counter and pretzels and peanuts. And you helped yourself and there was no charge. If a man had as much as a nickel, he could get full.

You know, people, in those days we didn’t have much of a welfare problem. A man could always panhandle a nickel even if he was broke. You could go out on the street and say, “Sir, could you spare a nickel or a dime?” And you could get fed with that. But you could also get drunk with it. What aboutwhiskey? The finest whiskey available: rye, scotch, bourbon—ten cents a shot. Back then it was readily available. In every corner saloon, a nickel for all the beer you’d want to hold, well, all the beer I’d want to hold—more than I’d want to hold to tell you the truth—and hard liquor, ten cents. And we had one of the lowest alcoholic consumption rates in the world.

Okay now, in 1918, the amendment, the Volstead Act, and the enforcement teams come out. And from 1918 to 1933 and 1934 when the Act was repealed, what happened? We went from one of the lowest per capita consumption rates in alcohol to one of the highest in the world while the government was suppressing it. Now’, people, if you don’t understand that, see me after we’re through tonight. I mean, this is so conspicuous that it should have warned us.

What about hard drugs? In 1960 a survey was made to discover the rate of hard drug addiction in New York City versus London. The two cities are huge: they were comparable in size at that time. I believe they still are. At that particular time, in I960, in London there were no laws whatsoever against the taking of hard drugs. In London, a person could go into any chemist’s—that’s a drug store — and for one shilling could buy six fixes of heroin, the pure stuff, uncut. And for your information, not that I have to tell some of you, but with six fixes of uncut heroin you can go into orbit for a month. You don’t even have to touch the landing strip. And that’s a shilling. Now, how many drug addicts did they have in London when hard drugs were readily available? It was not viewed as a crime and anybody who wanted it could get all he wanted for a shilling. At that particular time, according to the figures, there were 200 drug addicts in London.

 

THE NEW YORK CITY ADDICTION

Let’s compare that with New York. In New York City, and for nearly a hundred years prior to this time, this goes back to the 19th century in our case, we’ve been fighting hard drug traffic that long. The Treasury Department, the T-men, had been given the task of trying to suppress trade in whatever drug the government says is banned. And this, of course, included hard drugs right from the beginning. And hard drugs are bad news, no question. So the Treasury men had been fighting it and they had been fighting it for years and spending millions of dollars in suppressing it. And in 1960, when the survey was made, in New York City there were more than 14,000 drug addicts.

Now, how could a person get the drug in New York City? The only way was from your friendly neighborhood pusher, who was, of course, tied in, directly or indirectly, with the underworld. What would it cost? Well, it depended on what the pusher thought he could get. He might charge $25 for three fixes of questionable quality that might have been cut with a strychnine, so you didn’t know what you were getting. Or he could charge $30 or $50 or $100, depending on what he thought he could get out of you.

At that price a person can’t go out on the street and say, “I need a fix. Can you let me have 50 bucks?” You might be able to panhandle a nickel or a dime, but you can’t go up to someone and say, “You know, I’m having a problem” and get that kind of money.

So what happened? Well, you not only have over 14,000 addicts in New York, but according to the figures that have been released, 60 percent—that’s the figure they gave me, I don’t know that it’s accurate but that’s what they tell me—sixty percent of the crimes with victims are drug – connected. Why? Because when someone gets hooked on hard drugs, he can’t earn his own living. And when he comes out of his stupor and effects a landing, as it were, he has to get back into orbit as fast as possible. He has a craving that isenough to make the strongest man scream for help. It’s a terrible thing and he’ll do anything to support the habit. He can’t earn the money so what will he do? Literally anything. In fact, a good many of the heavy crimes we are getting today, unquestionably, are drug-connected. So he’ll steal purses or slit throats, take hubcaps or automobiles, smash windows, set fire to build­ings, anything that he can do to get his hands on that kind of money. And this is the figure—60 percent—drug connected. So that’s why I said what I did.There is no justification whatever for allowing the government to get into this area, as sensitive as it is. And, of course, the hard drug thing is a bad scene. We’ve got to get the government out of there so we can handle it.

Let’s go to the next item. This is the illegal manufacture of alcohol. I see it’s still a business and it is charted at $770 million. A good deal of the illegal alcohol today is manufactured in the Carolinas and Georgia by the moon­shiners. They’re still operating there as they did during’ prohibition days. Why is it illegal? You want to know the reason? There’s only one. These fellows won’t pay taxes, that’s all. They’re simply evading alcohol taxes. These are tax evaders, but they’re listed as criminals. They’re moonshiners.They’re bad people, quote unquote, because they’re not paying their taxes. They are manufacturing alcohol and selling it without paying the tax. I can’t tell you how good or bad it is. I haven’t sampled it.

Okay. Next item. Illegal interest charges, $500 million. Now, ladies and gentlemen, loan sharks can be tough. But so far, the record is overwhelm­ingly clear. Loan sharks have never been known to go after anybody who hasn’t borrowed from them. If you would like to stay out of the clutches of a loan shark, that’s entirely within your capacity. Don’t borrow from them. So I’m not too impressed with the idea that these people are criminals. Oh, sure they are very rough, but you know, if you go to them, you’re asking fortrouble. And I’d recommend that you not go unless you pretty well know what you’re doing. Then if it doesn’t work out right, don’t come crying to me.

Then we have prostitution, $400 million. I understand it’s enlarging again. It went way down although it used to be big.

And then they list tax fraud. I know this figure has to be wrong but they say $100 million. They don’t want to tell you how big it is.

And that comes to $23.9 billion. Ladies and gentlemen, those crimes listed here are crimes because the government says they are. And it’s larger by $10 billion than crimes where people get hurt. These two figures added up still don’t come to $51.1 billion.

But, now, you asked a question about court costs and so on. Here’s where they come in. In addition to these losses, the police departments around the country cost $5 billion. Penal institutions cost $1.0 billion and the courts cost another $1.8 billion for a total of $8.6 billion. That still doesn’t add up.

The other $5.5 billion, ladies and gentlemen, was spent by those who finally, beginning apparently about 1972, began to realize that the police didn’t pro­tect them and weren’t going to. So they went out into the market and began protecting themselves. And that worked. Now, I’m not selling subscriptions to these. They’re probably good. These are two magazines and they’re put out right in this area, the Los Angeles area,Security World and Security Distributing and Marketing magazines. Both of these are filled with ads and articles that tell you how to protect your life, your property, your person by going into the market and getting the job done.

And what do the insurance companies tell us about this? They tell us if you will protect yourself and not wait for the police, that, in many cases, they can lower your insurance rates because the evidence shows that when people are alert to the problem and protect themselves that private protection is about 90 percent effective. Government protection is 80 percent ineffective. And, people, that’s a broad, broad, difference.

If you rely on the police you have a 20 percent chance and if you rely on yourself and go to the marketplace you have a 90 percent chance. Now, nothing’s perfect. Many times this is my most serious difficulty in trying to explain what government does in this area.

The American people have been deceived so often that they expect me to offer them a panacea in which I give them a written guarantee that all they have to do is go to the marketplace and no crimes will ever happen again. That’s baloney and I know it and you know it and I can’t give you any guarantee. But the government did, you see, or at least many people think the government did. What the government said was, “Trust us and we’ll handle it for you.” That made it possible for you to forget all about it. You presumedthat the government was going to handle it for you. They can’t handle it. They haven’t been handling it. But I am not going to fool you. The government has gotten many of you to believe they’re taking care of the problem. They’re taking care of nothing. You are vulnerable, but if you’ll go into the private area, you can move significantly in the direction of your own protection.

 

GOVERNMENT IS AN INSTRUMENT OF VENGEANCE

Now here is where the hang-up is. If you are still concerned with retaliation and want to get after the fellow who, despite your best efforts, breaks in and steals from you, then you are going to have to have a government. Government is an instrument of vengeance. That is all it is and that is all it has been from the start. Of course, I repeat, if you protect yourself and if you are protected in fact, then you’re safe. And the question of punishing someone for hurting you can’t come up because you weren’t hurt. That’s what you want. If you can’t think that way, and I have found many people who really can’t, then you have a problem. Some can’t think protection. They can only think retaliation. I can’t say to them, “Go into the market and I’ll guarantee that there will be no more crimes.” Then they say, “A crime is apt to happen.” And I’ll say, “Yes, that’s true. Any crime is still apt to happen. I’m talking about reducing it from its present level by a tremendous factor.” And they say, “Well, a crime could still happen,” Yes, that’s right, it could.

But what do you do with the guy who did it? Well. I don’t know. What do you want to do with him? My suggestion would be this. If you buy a lock for your door and somebody breaks it, buy a better lock. You aren’t going to know who did it any more than the police. So all of your worry about how to get even is predicated on the idea that somehow: 1) You know who did it; 2) You can catch him; 3) You’re bigger than he is; and 4) You can beat it out of him. Well, people, you’re chasing a mirage. It isn’t going to happen. But you don’t have to worry about it if you’ll start thinking in terms of protection.

If we were to get rid of the government—not that we can. Certainly we can’t do it overnight. But just let your minds flow free for a moment. Let us suppose that, by some magic process, we could eliminate the government overnight. These costs would disappear.

The costs of government retaliation would vanish. That’s $8.6 billion. Then the costs of retaliating against those who offend legislative enactments would vanish. That’s another $23.9 billion. The cost of retaliation against victimless crimes. When it comes to crimes with victims, they could be reduced. Thefigures I have say that 60 percent of these crimes are drug connected.

 

EXAMPLE: COMMUNITY A & B

Now we could reduce this figure. I’m not going to tell you 60 percent. That’s a government figure and I question it. But let’s suppose we cut this by a substantial amount. Let’s suppose we cut this, say, by $3 billion. And we were left with a $10 billion problem. So we have a $10 billion problem. Let’s suppose we have to double private protection costs in order to protect ourselves. That would give us $11 billion and we have moved, by the simple process of getting government out of the way, from a $51 billion problem to a $21 billion problem. You still have a problem, but I don’t think that’s bad for openers. That would just get it started. You could reduce it from there. This is the example I was leading up to. Let us suppose that we have two communities. Community A and Community B, in the United States. And they’re identical in all respects except one. Let me presume, for purposes of comparison, that both of these communities have 100,000 population, 25,000 homes and 5,000 businesses. And they’re equally attractive or unattractive depending on what you think of cities of 100,000. So, they’re alike in all respects save this. Town A has a city manager and a mayor and a city council and the constabulary, the police force, the jails, the courts, the judges, the laws, the works. What we would typically expect today is an American town of 100,000. And Town B is the same except it doesn’t have any of those customary legal trappings.

What would we have in Town A? In Town A, ladies and gentlemen, how many police would there be? If we take the national average, we will dis­cover, as of now, about 175 police in Town A that has a 100,000 population, including meter maids. That means that we have 175 people working round the clock, three shifts a day. We have to allow for vacations and illness. We would do well to have 50 people on duty at one time. And you’re asking those people to protect 100,000 people, 25,000 homes and 5,000 businesses. Theproblem is absolutely insurmountable. It can’t be done. That’s an absurdity.

But there’s something else. Last year, in the average town of 100,000 in the United States, 9,000 pieces of real estate were sold to pay the taxes that provide the basic cost for the police. That was the biggest rip-off in that community, the loss of 9,000 pieces of real estate to pay the various tax-supported agencies including the police.

If you were to go to this community and add on to the police department the numbers of personnel required to perform an adequate job, you’d end up confiscating all the rest of the real estate and you’d shut the town down. You have a system here that is so bad that as you improve it, it gets worse. Let’s see what else you have in Town A.

The police department, ladies and gentlemen, is the best advertised of any governmental agency. There will be no newspaper issued that will not recite their exploits. If you watch television, every major television station will have at least one drama every day in which the police are the heroes. And they are handsome and they are loving and they are kind and they are good. They are trustworthy, loyal, friendly, helpful, courteous, thrifty, brave, clean, and reverent. And they get their man and we love them. And that goes on day after day and in color and in your living room. So you are exposed to that. So we know about the police. They have, what we would call, a high profile. You know about them. They are there. And the result? Let me tell you. You pay a lot of taxes for them and you know that, too. You’re convinced the police are there; you’re paying for it; you hear about the police all the time.

 

OUR PROFESSION IS UNDERSTAFFED

 So what do you do? Well, I’ll tell you what you do. You go to bed one night without locking your front door. And you get up in the morning and you don’t even know the door’s been unlocked until you start to leave for work. You go to the door and, my gosh, it was unlocked all night. You start out and there is your car at the curb. You planned to put it in the garage but the kid’s tricycle was in the driveway so you pulled in front. You were going to go back later but you didn’t; you forgot. So, okay, at least the car’s there. So you walk down and as you get to it, you’re feeling in your pockets and you can’t find your keys. And you look at the car and dangling from the ignition are all your keys. You pulled them out a little to break that noise because it bothers you. And your keys have been in the ignition in front of your house all night and nothinghappened. And you say, “It’s a good thing we’ve got the cops because if it weren’t for them, I sure would have been ripped off.” That is exactly what happens. You begin to live in a fool’s paradise. You think you are safe.

I have an article written by a burglar who wrote the item while he was serving time in the Missouri State Penitentiary. More on that, if you’re interested.

I’ll tell you how he happened to get there. He got there by design. And he says, “If you haven’t been ripped off recently, don’t credit the police.” He says the reason is: “Our profession is understaffed.” He says the American people are simply inviting the burglars and “We don’t have enough people to take care of the opportunities.” But he says “Don’t worry. We’ll get around to you in time. Our fellows are working nights.” You know, trying to catch up. So obviously the burglar knows what he is talking about. He’s a pro. He says that a professional burglar rarely has to break in.

You don’t break. You just walk around and try the doors. And about one in five will be unlocked. So you open it and walk in. You don’t ring the bell; you walk in and when you get inside you say, “Hi, Maude. I’mhere.” And you wait. The likelihood of Maude being there is very remote because probably there is no Maude. You pick a name like that, you see. There aren’t many Maudes anyway but the likelihood of Maude being there is very remote. But what if somebody is home? They come to the door. And here’s a strange manstanding just inside the door. And the first thing the crook says is, “Where’s Maude?”

The lady of the house says, “There’s no Maude here.”

He says, “Well, where is she? When is she coming back?”

“Well, no Maude lives here.”

“Oh, really? Maude Jones?”

“There’s no…”

“Well, ma’am, excuse me, but isn’t this 122 Maple Street?”

“No, this is 122 Elm.”

“Oh, I beg your pardon. I’ve been away for a year. I used to live in this neighborhood and I moved away a long time ago. And I’ve got the streets mixed up. I hope I didn’t startle you. Excuse me, please.” He leaves. Do you think that’s going to be reported as a crime?

This is how it’s done. But what if nobody’s home? Ha. This man is a pro. He knows where your stuff is. First thing he does, he gets one of your suitcases. He doesn’t carry one. He knows where you’re going to keep yours so he takes that, zip, zip, zip. He gets stuff in it and he goes sauntering out of the house. And if anyone asks him, he’s going to meet you. You forgot something. He’s got your bag to prove it. You really think he’s going to be caught? Nobody was there. He made sure of that to begin with. How does he make sure?

Do you know what a crook can do? He goes down to the local police station, provides a card showing that he’s a member of a national writers association and says he’s doing an article studying police methods. And he’d like to bone up on the police methods that are employed in the local town. He’d like to ride around in the black-and-whites, get to know the officers, and see just what they do. They’ll tell him. They’d better; he’s a taxpayer, isn’t he? He learns all about how the locals work. I’m speaking of a pro. I’m not talking about amateurs now; they get into trouble. The pros know what to do. They meet the policemen. They find out what the police beats are. They know where the cars are. They time it. They know how long it will take for a radio response. And you wonder why the police are only 20 percent effective? I marvel they get results at all. What they catch is the amateur who doesn’t know how to do it. Well, this burglar explains this.

Of course, once in a while he would get greedy enough so he would break in. And he told about one place where he thought the pickings would be good enough to warrant breaking in because the story was that there were plenty of goodies inside. But when he went to the house in a very nice neighborhood he discovered that the people inside had anticipated that somebody might show up. And guess what they had done?

They had put bars on all the windows, ornamental bars, quite attractive, but they were there. Now, you know that’s an interesting point. We seem to have complete confidence that after a man has committed a crime we can arrest him, put him behind bars, and he can’t get through them. It’s true. But if you put the bars in front of him, he can’t get through them, either. And if he doesn’t get through them, then he can’t commit the crime. So the same process will prevent the crime rather than trying to take care of it after thefact. These people had anticipated that so he couldn’t get through the win­dows.

He checked the door. The average door on the average house can be opened with a credit card. And everybody has one of those, at least one. Most doors don’t have good locks. That is, they have the convenient lock which is the night latch. But you can buy for a relatively few dollars a good bolt action lock. If you’re worried, buy two and put them on the same door. If you’re really worried, buy four and put them on the hinge side as well as the latch side and one top and bottom.

And then, if you really want to be sure, you know most doors are just plywood with air between and you can get through both of them with your fist. Put on a glove and “bing” you’re right through. But for a very small amount of money if you have any mechanical ability, take down your doors, take off the top strip of wood, and you can buy these metal rods that are used to reinforce concrete, and you weave that into a network, a grid, and stick it in your door. Then go to the sawmill and have them blow sawdust mixed with glue in there and fill it up. And if anybody hits that door with his fist, he’s going to break his arm. Put that in.It’s going to look exactly as it did before. It looks like a plywood door. And heaven help the man who runs intoit because whatever contacts it is going to be hurt. And now you put it up with good locks and nobody’s going through it. Well, that’s exactly what this burglar found. These people had fixed their doors. He couldn’t get through the doors and he couldn’t get through the windows but there was still a chance.

It was a two-story house and the window on the landing halfway up didn’t have bars. So he stashed a box in the alley. A ladder, you know, would have been too much of a giveaway. And a box was just about the right size. So he waited until he saw his victims leave. He got his box, stood under the window: it was just the right height so he could reach the window. And he’d come prepared. I perhaps ought to charge an added fee for some of this informa­tion. Anyway, you take masking tape and you put a couple of strips, zip, zip,across the glass leaving a loose part in the middle so you can control the glass. You have a glass cutter, zip, zip. You take out the glass—doesn’t make any noise—set it down and now the crook is ready to crawl in.

He started through the window and looked up. He was at a landing as he had anticipated. At the top of the stairs a pair of cat’s eyes were looking at him in the dark. The only trouble was they were eight inches apart. His first thought was. Well, what do you know? A pair of one-eyed cats. He had a little pocket flashlight, turned it on, and there was a black panther looking at him. The panther was chained, he said. He wasn’t and left. Now, that’s protection.

 

NOBODY’S BEING PROTECTED

I’m not trying to boost the stock of black panthers. The fact is that these people had realized they didn’t have any safety with the police and so they had done what seemed intelligent to them. They had successfully turned aside a professional. But you don’t have to go to this extreme. You can accomplish the same objective if you use your head. And for goodness sakes, don’t expect the police to protect you because they’re not going to.

A friend of mine used to travel a good deal and left his wife behind. One day she was at home in her house. She was upstairs but the phone was at the foot of the stairs and the downstairs was dark. The phone rang and she went down the stairs to answer it. Looking through the darkened room and out of the window, she saw a man sneaking up onto her porch. Well, it was a friend calling on the phone so she said, very quietly, “You’ll have to get off the line. I’ll have to call you back. I’m scared.” She got her friend off the line and called the police. She identified herself, “I’m Mrs. So-and-so at such-and-such an address. I’m alone in my home and there’s a man sneaking up on my front porch.”

Now, what do you think the sergeant on duty said? “What is he doing now?”

She said, “I can’t see him now and I’m afraid to go out and look.”

The sergeant said, “Has he broken in yet?”

She said, “No, he hasn’t but he could do it any minute.”

“Well,” he said, “Ma’am, if he hasn’t broken in, maybe he won’t.”

She said, “That’s true but maybe he will.”

He said, “Well, ma’am, I’m terribly sorry but I’m alone here at the station. I don’t have anybody I can send out. I’ll tell you what you do. Keep a watch on him and if anything happens call me back.”

The policeman was doing his duty. He was telling the truth. He was alone. He couldn’t shut down the police station. What were the other policemen doing? They were following up after other crimes that had been committed. Nobody’s being protected. This woman wasn’t protected. But we get so confused we think that’s protection.

 

PLAYED BY THE RULES

Oh, there’s one other thing, a tremendously important point.

In Town A, ladies and gentlemen, the police operate according to the rules. And the crooks know the rules as well as the police. So the crooks can predict exactly what the police will do. Their whole scene is laid out for them in advance. Indeed, if a policeman attempts to do something that is contrary to what the rules are, the crook will back him off and say, “Now wait a minute. You can’t do that. I know my rights,” etc.

And the policeman must back away. So there is predictability on the side of the crook. The criminal knows what the police are going to do. He can find out where they’re going to be. He knows what his odds are. His chances of getting away with an undetected crime are overwhelmingly in his favor. And, of course, he gets away with it.

I was going to tell about this fellow who got arrested whose article I was quoting. He tried to get arrested. The reason: he had a friend in the Missouri State Penitentiary who had some information and he wanted it. But when he went in on visiting days, the man was sure that the area was bugged and hewouldn’t talk. The only way this fellow could get the information was to get locked up. So he began to perform his burglaries in a sloppy way, hoping he’d get arrested but the police couldn’t catch him. So even when he was leaving a trail for them, they couldn’t find him. He finally decided to take events into his own hands and he went downtown carrying a rock in his pocket. And he finally got a policeman’s attention by acting sort of weird. When he was sure the policeman was watching, he went up to a jewelry store and threw the rock through the window and stood there and got arrested. When his case came up, the policeman was actually a witness on his side. He said to the judge, “You know, your honor, I never had a more cooperative prisoner. This man didn’t try to run away and he didn’t try to resist arrest and he didn’t try to steal anything. He just broke the window.”

And the judge said, “Do you realize that you wouldn’t be here if you hadn’t broken that window?”

“Yes, Your Honor, I realize that.”

So the judge said, “Well, you’re certainly cooperative.” So he sent him up for sixty days, which is what he wanted. He had a bad tooth and he wanted to get some bridge work done. Of course, that’s done at the taxpayer’s expense and he got free room and board. He got to brush elbows with some of the hardened criminals. He sharpened his techniques…this is where you get your graduate work done if you’re a criminal. He went to prison and then, on top of that, got to talk to his buddy. That’s where he wrote the article. He’d already entered into a contract with Reader’s Digest that agreed to pay him $1,000 if he was a professional burglar and he would write the article while he was in prison. So he did. So he made $1,000, got his teeth fixed, got free room and board, everything done at your expense. How good can it get? I mean, this is; the way things are arranged for the burglar.

 

THE UNPREDICTABLE TOWN

 Now let’s switch over to Town B. Town B is the same as Town A except it doesn’t have all of these things we’ve been talking about. I’ll tell what else it doesn’t have. The people in Town B don’t pay taxes and they don’t have illusions. They don’t live in a fool’s paradise.

What do they do? I don’t know what they do and neither does anybody else. They are unpredictable. I suspect that quite a few of them wouldn’t do anything but I don’t know which ones. Some of them, of course, would take out an insurance policy, which is available now to reimburse them. That wouldn’t prevent the crime but, at least, the victim can get something back.

Which is more than you’ll get from the police unless they get awfully lucky. I think quite a few in Town B would buy insurance. Then there would be some who’d get better locks on their doors—maybe put bars on the windows.

There would also be people in that town who would be truly frightened and would want to make themselves very safe. They might do some astonishing things like the man in Iowa who booby-trapped a farmhouse he wasn’t using with a sawed-off shotgun. And lo and behold, a burglar tried to break in. The shotgun went off but the burglar took the case to court and won a $30,000 judgment against his victim. Of course, that couldn’t happen in Town B because, without legal restraint, you could booby-trap your house with a shotgun. Now I wouldn’t recommend that. But the burglar doesn’t know that much about me.

I go along with the old Quaker. You remember the story. He was asleep one night and he thought he heard a burglar downstairs. So he took his shotgun off the wall, went creeping down, turned on the light and, sure enough, there was a burglar. So he aimed the gun at the burglar and said, “Friend, I would not injure thee for the world. But thou art standing in the space into which I’m about to shoot.” And the burglar left. The Quaker told a lie. He wouldn’t have shot, I’m sure. Or am I? You see, that’s the point.

If we can get the crooks off balance, they wouldn’t know what you’re going to do. So when he comes to my house, the burglar doesn’t know whether I’m a Quaker or whether I’m the Count de Sade. Maybe I have a little throw rug in front of my door over a trapdoor. And I have a timer so that if you stand there for seventeen seconds, it opens and you fall down into a pit of quicklime. There is nothing in Town B to prevent that because there’s no government telling you how to protect yourself. You could do it your way. I wouldn’trecommend that, either. You’re apt to lose a postman that way. Of course, I can think of some postmen…no…I still wouldn’t recommend it. I’m only pointing out that there would be nothing to stop it.

In other words…think about it for a minute. If you went to Town A, every­thing is arranged for you. If you go to Town B, you know there could be land mines in the lawn.

In San Francisco right now, there’s a jewelry store that prevented burglars from breaking the windows by a very handy device. They keep a tarantula in the window. Nobody breaks the glass. Well, it’s a friendly tarantula. It’s also as big as my hand and it’s a nice high-type tarantula. How would you like to have a nice high-type tarantula jump on you? They jump, you know.

I have a picture of a man protecting his van. He keeps a boa constrictor in the cab with him. It’s a friendly boa constrictor. How would you like to be affectionately treated by a friendly boa constrictor? Nobody steals his cab. And I’ve got magazines here full of devices that you can put on your own property and use to protect your own person. And, people, that’s what would happen in Town B. Because there would be nothing to restrain the property owner or the individual. Think about it for a minute and decide.

If you were a burglar, where would you go? If you went to Town A, you can predict everything that’s going to be arrayed against you. And if you go to Town B, you could disappear and there wouldn’t even be an inquiry.

Again, I suggest to you that if you want to solve your problems, take it out of the hands of government. Does government protection protect? It doesn’t do anything of the sort. It takes vengeance in your name after you’ve been hurt and calls it protection. But firm in the center of the system is your prior injury. You’ve got to be injured by the tax collector. And then you’re going to be injured by the crook in addition before the government will stir itself. Then the tax collector injures you again. That’s not good enough. I want to be safe and I think you do, too. And the answer is pull the job away from government.

Ladies and gentlemen, if the government can’t protect you, will you kindly tell me what you want it for? Thank you very much.

 

**** QUESTIONS AND ANSWERS ****

Q: In Town B, would there be Martial Law or civil war?

A: Only if the people there decide that they want to deal in vengeance. Then either could occur, and that would be no gain. In other words, you could set up private protection as long as you limit the action to provide procedures. It is when you begin to decide that you have to go in and violate the boundaries of the party that’s already been wronged that you get into government. So if you could set up private protection without vengeance, you’re on the target. If you can’t, you’re right back where you are now.

Q: With your friend with the tool box, wouldn’t it have been a very simple thing to say, “Okay, burglar, if this is your tool box describe its contents. And I will describe its contents and by identification I can prove what’s mine and what’s not.”

A: I would think so.

Q: That would seem logical.

A: I would think so but that’s not what happened. So, sometimes under pressure…incidentally, this fellow’s a pretty sharp guy. But sometimes you get excited.

Q: How about when the government is the criminal?

A: Well, it was implied. Of course, I agree. You don’t really have to make a separate category. The government really can’t act unless it is engaged in violating boundaries because it has nothing else to do.

Q: Returning to Town B, you’ve done away with the court system and you no longer have the arbitrator. That raises the age-old question of who settles disputes.

A: Well, whoever wants to, I would think. You know, when it comes to settling a dispute there are only four possible outcomes. You win, you lose, you compromise, or you keep fighting. That’s all that can happen. And it really doesn’t take an elaborate system to establish that. Now, there have been a lot of studies in this area. Actually, your question is deep enough to take an evening. But may I say that I have found, and I’ve done this myself, I’ve served as an arbitrator in a couple of disputes this way. And it has worked beautifully. As a private citizen, the plaintiff and the defendant come to me and here’s how I’ve done it. I let the plaintiff tell me about the wrong. And I give him all the time in the world and he can keep talking as long as he wants to and I don’t care how often he repeats himself. He can call the defendant every name in the book. The defendant has to sit there and take it. In this connection, by the way, it’s good if you have an additionalaudience. Let the plaintiff run on, but you’ve got to be patient. Let him go the distance. When he’s said it all, then you ask him to be still and you turn to the defendant and ask him to have his say. And he says it, and let him go without any interruption however long it takes. When he’s through, go back to your plaintiff and let him do it again. When he’s through, go back to the defendant. Never interrupt. Let him say it all. Let them finish. If you keep that up, you will discover a very interesting thing. The periods of tirade get less and less vituperative and briefer and briefer. In process, this has happened whenever I’ve been involved. All of a sudden, in the midst of one of these recitations, one of the disputants says, “Wait a minute. I see. I’m at fault.” He sees and everybody else sees it. The problem becomes visible and then the thing is settled.

Q: But I’m the biggest guy in the bar and I don’t want to go to you.

  1. Then don’t.
  2. Then who intercepts my blow?

A: No one, unless someone dislikes you enough to shoot you. And, of course, in Town B that could happen.

Q: I’ve never been there.

A: I’ve never been there, either. What I think you are asking is the conven­tional question. It’s a good question but it needs more examination than we have time for here. The point is how do you deal after the crime has happened. I’ve shown you how to reduce the incidence of it. I have never said you could eliminate it. I don’t know how to eliminate it. I can reduce the incidence by getting government out of the way. There are other things that can be done. That’s a study in itself. We can go a lot further and there are things you can do without trying to get the guilty party and make him suffer. That’s an old barbaric idea, and as relatively civilized men, I hope, you should put that aside.

Q: But there’s a point at which protection becomes aggression. If I’m stationed in my living room and I aim a shotgun at everyone who looks funny in my picture window, then that’s protection if you’re eliminating all protection cohesion.

A: Correct, correct. And I didn’t get into defense and I didn’t get into a lot of other things because of the time element. It’s a broad subject but nonethe­less protection can occur in such a way that the costs of protection are limited to the party protecting himself. And they need not go beyond that. There are many things that people call protection that I wouldn’t myself use. But I know I have no power to prevent them from doing it just as I have no power to prevent anyone from committing a crime if he wants to. What I can do is to raise the cost to him of committing a crime against me so he won’t do it. I’m happy about that. Let me just say this one further thing. I have a limited competence and so does everyone else. I can feed myself and my family, though not perfectly. I’ve missed a few meals in my life. But I do a pretty good job. However, there’s no way I can feed society. I can clothe myself and my family. I can house myself and my family. I can provide a certain number of comforts and conveniences for myself and my family. There’s no way I can do that for society. I can protect myself and my family and I can protect my property and myself. I can’t do it for society. I can handle it within the area of my competence and most people can. Those who have anything worth protecting can.

 

QUESTION OF COST AND EFFECTIVENESS

Q: I’ve had this question before and I’ve never gotten a fully satisfactory answer out of you, but I’mgoing to try again. Okay, Town B. Let’s assume that in Town B we have people who accept, an ethical base, the idea that they’re not going to use force in retaliation. If they can build a better lock, fine, they’ll build it, an impenetrable house with bars, fine. But once you get in there, they’re not going to use force against you. Okay, it’s my supposition that there’s no wall so thick that someone can’t come up with an explosive to break through.

A: I agree.

Q: Okay, it’s simply a matter of cost-effectiveness at that point. And, obvi­ously, there’s a point beyond which crime does not pay. Okay, but beyond that, doesn’t every other one of these protective methods imply the threat of force in retaliation?

A: It doesn’t have to. Often the first argument offered against my position is that private protection works as well as it does because the police are there to back it up. That isn’t the case. For instance, when a private alarm is installed which turns in a signal at the police station, it has proven to be ineffective. A very loud alarm which the criminal can hear has been far more effective. The police take a long time to respond. Further, they often come with sirens so the criminal can hear them a mile away. But few criminals can do their best work with a very loud sound or siren wailing in their ears. But again, you are not thinking “protection.” You are respond­ing AFTER the fact. Protection, when it works, prevents the fact.

Q: Most criminals, though, as I understand the analyses they’ve done lately on why people become criminals. One of many things is very short-term thinking. Okay, in other words, not thinking of the consequences beyond the next moment.

A: Well…

Q: The analytic sort of thing.

A: I think that’s true of amateur criminals but I don’t think it’s true of the pros.

Q: I think that the pros are in a minority. I think that as we say a good deal of crime is increased at the moment. Someone is desperate or something like this to increase this sort of criminal.

A: Well, for the amateur, relatively unsophisticated methods are very good protection. For the pro, you have to be more professional yourself in protecting yourself, but right here you are going to meet the point where the pro experiences a no-return situation. You could raise the cost to him and he’s intelligent enough to go elsewhere.

Q: Okay, I can accept this all down the line. In other words, for your indi­vidual unorganized, even professional criminal, it seems to me that, given a market situation, it’s going to be a known situation. Okay, we come essentially to an organized assault where a gang like a raider-gang or government…

A: You mean government comes in? Yes, I admit this. If you have a govern­ment acting…I’m helpless before that.

Q: You see in this case only a counter-threat…

A: No. no. no. I don’t think a counter-threat is going to be any more effective than a surrender. In fact, sometimes a surrender is more effective. The bullet doesn’t care whether you’re shooting aggressively or defensively. So you reduce the casualties as much as you can. In cases of this sort I’m a professional coward. When I’m faced with superior forces I analyze it quickly and say to my opponent, “You won! Let’s assume that you’ve beaten me. I surrender. Where do you want me to fall?”

Q: But you’re assuming superior force.

A: Yes, it happens very quickly at my age. It’s easy to assume. Incidentally, I stopped a riot one time with just that procedure. Because I was confronted by some people who thought they might like to have a riot and they wanted to know what I would do. And I said I would run away. If they wanted a physical contest with me, they would win. So why would I fight when I know I’m going to lose? That’s an absurdity. So knowing I would lose, I wouldn’t fight.

Q: If you know you will lose, then your response is logical. If however…

A: With me, it’s logical. The consequences. That has made me safer than going around with my dukes up ready to fight. I tried both when I was younger and I got into more fights when I was trying to defend myself. I stopped doing that and the fights stopped. So you can’t tell. The guy who walks around like this and says I’m defending myself looks just as if he’s going to attack you.

Q: We also have the martial experts…who are very calm and serene and don’t do a damn thing until the actual force is present.

A: And I don’t do anything. And I tell them I’m not a martial arts expert. If they blow on me, I’ll fall down.

 

A QUESTION OF EDUCATION

Q: If we assume that Town B is a place where it’s going to work, I don’t get any feeling of this practical transition from a Town A situation to a Town B situation. And additionally, we’re not talking about isolated towns of 100.000 people. We’re talking of a nation of 3 billion people. I don’t get a feeling of the practical…

A: Well, very good. Let me respond…

Q: …in a society as complex as we have.

A: Obviously, we’re not comprised of a series of 100,000 towns. But you can begin the transition right where you are by realizing the police, whatever their intentions may be, are not protecting you and you can undertake your own protection. That’s the beginning of the transition. As you do this and more and more people will join in—and it is beginning—the crime rate will come down. In fact, that is beginning. We are beginning to whip it by this method. As that occurs, and the knowledge spreads, we can begin to get rid of these areas that aren’t needed. Of course, from my point of view, we don’t need any of them, but I realize that it is all a matter of personal education. And that’s going to take a long time. In the final analysis, it is amatter of education.

Q: By whom? Who does the educating?

A: Well, step one is followed by step two. And step two is more education. Who is going to educate? Anybody who has information to impart and that includes you and everybody else. We inform each other. You don’t have to have formal classrooms or lecture situations in order to be educated. You are educated every day of your life with all the things that you do and all the contacts you make. And when you understand that, you understand that as a parent you are a natural educator of your children. As a memberof a club, you are an educator of the people in the club. As an employee or employer in a business, you are a natural educator of your co-workers. And so on. These are natural arrangements. You communicate, you exp­lain, and we all do this. And gradually we all make progress. You can’t do it overnight. But you begin where you are and you do what you have the competence to do. You can’t do more than that anyway. So you do what you can.

Q: In the practical sense, these things start happening and people see what exists is not working and they have to choose some alternative. And the plan springs from that so then you go up and down each housing tract. In Palm Springs, for example, you will see little signs in front of each house. There are three or four different security forces that these people have contracted with because the city police force doesn’t seem to be doing an adequate job. They have also contracted for burglar alarms and other types of self-protection. So that as people discover what they think is supposed to work doesn’t, they will have to turn to some other alternative. And eventually, perhaps, they’ll just decide to eliminate the police forces entirely.

A: Thank you.

Q: One thing that works with problems like that is neighbors. Like, when we moved into a house the next door neighbor didn’t know us or recognize us so she called the police. She saw furniture and didn’t know if we were moving it out or what. It was embarrassing but with neighbors like that something can be very effective.

A: We have that where we are. In our neighborhood we all watch; we happen to live in a cul-de-sac. Everybody watches every strange vehicle that comes in here…

Q: Maybe there’s a Town C. Instead of individual protection like a medieval Dark Ages situation, in Town C you could have people watching out for one another the way it was before we got to Town A.

A: Very good, yes, indeed. And I don’t think that with our current technology we have to go back to a medieval situation and have a fortress. You know, for the amount of taxes that you spend in one year, if you had that money you could convert your home into a perfectly safe refuge. Your expendi­tures would be over. For example, you could put in sliding steel panels that disappear in the wall and operate like the windows on your car. With a key, you’d activate it. And these are ornamental panels with holes cut in them so ventilation can continue. They can slide across in steel grooves behind every door and window in your house. You can activate it from inside or outside. And it becomes easier to go through a wall than a door. That’s relatively inexpensive. Relatively. It costs something but, compared to taxes, you do it once and have your home equipped. Nobody would even know the system was there. Until you used it, of course. So there are so many things that can be done. But I agree. You can work with your neighbors and join forces with them. And it’s a wonderful idea. The police themselves have acknowledged that it is the upsurge of private protection that is helping to reduce the crime rate. And the police acknowledge it isn’t their job to prevent crime. Their job is to enforce the law. If you want to prevent crime, you have to prevent it. And they are now saying this. Of course, I’ve been saying it for twenty years. But it takes about twenty years. Talk about education. You just keep on.

Q: What happened in 1972 to reduce the crime rate?

A: I don’t know.

Q: Do you think it was due to private protection?

A: This is what I’m not being told. There was a tremendous upsurge that year in the purchase of private protective devices, but what caused that, I don’t know. Why did the people suddenly decide…Gosh, this stuff’s been around longer than that. But somehow in 1972, there was such an upsurge that it really did cut down. Of course, it came back later.

Q: Maybe I should share this, Bob, because wasn’t our friend Nixon in office then? Perhaps the burglars were watching about Watergate.

A: Or maybe they were employed by Nixon. I’m not angry with Mister Nixon or Mister Carter. You know, people, it doesn’t pay you to get angry. It pays you to protect your own life and property. That you can do.

Q: (Lawrence Samuels) I just want to mention one thing. In case you are thinking about some more questions, we have just a little more time. In our publication, which I hope you’ve taken and eventually someday you may get through the mail, we have an article. You probably saw it in Associated Press. It’s in Robin, Ill., where they fired the whole police department of that city. And some of the crimes against them were armed robbery, car theft, and burglary. This is not too far from Chicago, I believe. They had fired the whole police department before, about seven years earlier. But it’s Associated Press’ report. We do take them out of there and you might find it interesting in our publication. I thought it was appropriate for this speech and that’s why I had it in there. Also, one other thing I’d like to mention. There’s one time, I don’t know if you remember, where one town, a pretty good size town, where the policemen went on strike. And all of a sudden, serious crimes dropped because they didn’t want to confront angry citizens. Because the police would step in there and take them to court or take them to jail. Citizens, on the other hand, just might shoot the criminal. And so crimes declined drastically.

A: We’ve also had the other experience. I don’t mean to contradict you at all because I do recall the instance, but somebody’s going to put this all together so let me do it for you. Quite recently, during the blackout in New York and on other occasions when there has been a sudden cessation of police activity, you have seen an upsurge in crime. Yes?

Q: But, Bob, I have to say that’s not necessarily because of lessening of police protection. Because, the first blackout in New York the crime rate went down.

A: The birthrate went up, right. It went the other way. I agree, I agree, I’m trying to make the point. I’m on your side. The thing is that in these instances that are sometimes brought forward to prove we have to have police, you are talking about a notification to the criminal world, in fact, that nobody’s going to protect anything. And that’s going to bring the criminal out. Now, if you serve notice at the same time, the police aren’t going to be around, but private persons will. Then you achieve the point that Larry has made. In the case I’ve just brought to the fore, there was a virtual invitation made to the crook. The police weren’t going to be there. Nobody was going to protect anything. The burglars couldn’t have had a better invitation.

(Lawrence Samuels…)

Okay, I think it’s time for one thing we’re going to have. He doesn’t know this is happening.

But we decided since Robert LeFevre has been giving us so much help for these speeches and helping us get out his last speech and so forth that we decided to give him an award.

Really, this is the first time Ken has seen this. He’s supposed to give the award. So maybe you can say something. It’s called the Libertas Award and also we have Dave (Moore) over here to get some shots of it and give you a photo of it. So I’d like Ken to present Robert LeFevre with our Libertas Award. This is our first one. Dave, are you ready with the camera?

(Ken Grubbs…)

I remember a few years ago I presented a similar award to R. C. Hoiles but it was a “Sons of Liberty” Medallion and I could hang it around his neck, which I did at a conference at Long Beach State. But I will read this one. It says: “Libertas Award. The Society of Libertarian Life wishes to express its deep appreciation and gratitude to Robert LeFevre for his time and energy in behalf of SLL and in the cause of liberty. Presented at Santa Ana College, May 19, 1978.

 

THE LEGEND OF SOCIETY FOR LIBERTARIAN LIFE

 It’s no mystery. Legends are made; they don’t just happen. It’s hard work and it takes courage to advance against almost insurmountable odds. But Society for Libertarian Life (SLL) met the challenge and the world hasn’t been the same since.

It was a meager beginning in early 1973. Lawrence Samuels, an art student, organized a non-credited experimental college course on the fundamentals of libertarianism at California State University, Fullerton (CSUF). The first day was a big success—five students showed up and enrolled. Society for Libertarian Life was on its way. A legend was in the making.

At the conclusion of the semester, SLL began publishing a small journal entitled Libertarian New Horizon. It was issued under the name of Students for a Libertarian Life. Two years later the name was changed so as to include individuals from both the campus and the community. Presently, SLL membership is equally divided between high school/college students and people from the community at large.

The first years were painful and difficult for SLL. Very few persons understood libertarianism, let alone pronounce the word. Others confused libertarianism with “liberation” or something to do with “librarians.” Still others tried to associate libertarians with either reactionary conservatives or radical leftists. Those who strongly opposed libertarianism, merely shrugged it off as soon-to-be-forgotten fad. Little did they know the extent of the libertarian movement and SLL.

The second major activity of SLL was to sponsor a speech by self-pro­claimed anarcho-capitalist, Liz Keathley, who captured the Peace & Freedom Party (PFP) gubernatorial candidacy in 1974 (Calif.) from the socialist faction. More than 100 students attended the speech at Cal State Fullerton.

That same year, libertarians under Eric Garris and Jean Berkman captured the state PFP while SLL members won control of the Orange County PFP cen­tral committee, proceeding to shut it down (made headlines in LA. Times).

The first major venture by SLL was a speech by former Progressive Labor Party leader Phillip Abbott Luce. In a very cunning move. SLL members joined the CSUF Economics Association and voted to fund Luce’s speech on campus. The speech drew 60 students and strong criticism from campus fac­ulty. Luce had attacked public education, advocating the demise of tax-supported education. The uproar in faculty circles was extensive, especially since, as some faculty members pointed out, Luce’s speech was funded by the university.

A new direction was taken in 1976 as SLL began operating lectures and activities on other campuses and in the community. In early 1976, SLL sponsored Dr. Nathaniel Branden at Fullerton College. More than 300 persons attended. That same year SLL sponsored Prof. Tibor Machan at CSUF and Cypress College, premiered the film The Incredible Bread Machine, and staged an anti-tax protest demonstration at the federal building in Santa Ana, California. Karl Bray was to be the keynote speaker, but was detain­ed by the federal gov­ernment.

In October of 1977, SLL co-sponsored with the Cato Institute two lectures by Prof. Murray Rothbard at the University of California, Irvine. “The Economic Future” was the title with around 50 students attending the daytime lecture and some 200 attending the evening lecture.

In early 1977 Hospers gave a speech at Fullerton College on Will Freedom Survive Until 1984? The speech was covered by the L.A. Times and later incor­porated into a magazine article (Californian Journal,July edition, titled “Libertarians, GOP successor or philosophical study group?”). Almost 100 persons attended the lec­ture a reception was held afterward.

Karl Bray was one of the most beloved libertarians in the movement. He died at an early age in Florida (May 12, 1978). Bray gave a lecture to SLL members on June 9, 1976 on taxes and libertarianism. A former Utah radio com­mentator, he spoke to SLL a few months after being released from federal prison after serving a six-month sentence. He was jailed for possess­ing an IRS note known as a seizure notice. The notice is available to any citizen under the Freedom of Information Act.

Warning that Americans must resist taxa­tion, Bray said, “If we don’t resist, we’ll lose by default. You’ll have a greater chance of surviv­ing terminal cancer than national socialism if it comes to the United States.”

Two anti-tax demonstrations and marches were held at IRS offices in 1976 and 1977. A coffin was used in the march with a sign tacked to it reading: Tomb of The Unknown Taxpayer. Dave Bergland, former Libertarian Party vice presidential candi­date in 1976, was one of the main speakers, arguing that it was “perfectly possible to have a society without taxes.”

John Matonis, an attorney from Washington D.C. spoke at Santa Ana College in November, 1978 to a crowd of 100. Described as a cross between a fighter like Davy Crockett and the sharp wit of an Abraham Lincoln, John Matonis is one of the leading anti-establishment lawyers in the country.

Mationis has defended tax rebels, laetrile users, fought against vitamin regulations (appeal case) and defended the Scientologists (E-Meter case).

Author of Common Sense Economics, John Pugsley spoke in early 1979 at Santa Ana College. Around 60 persons attended the lecture. At 12 noon on the same day of the Briggs/Garris debate, SLL and Students for a Libertarian Society held an anti-Prop. 6 rally with Ed Clark, Libertarian Party candidate for California governor, as the key speaker at CSUF.

One of the most exciting activities of SLL (1978) was a scheduled debate between Sen. John Briggs and Rev. Eric Garris on Oct. 26 at CSUF. Briggs failed to appear and is currently be sued by SLL’s attorney, David Bergland. Briggs’ office sent down Prof. Kent and Garris debated him in a crowd of 300. One of Briggs’ attorneys, Ward, said that Briggs failed to appear because supposedly SLL leaders told Briggs that he did not really have to make an appearance to debate in favor of his Prop. 6 anti-gay initiative since libertarians believe in voluntarism. No such call was ever made to Senator John Briggs.

The biggest event of SLL was its May 1, 1979 anti-draft demonstrations at Cal State Fullerton, Orange Coast College and Chapman College. More than 200 students with an eight piece rock band named Horizon Street Band made the CSUF demonstration a great success. Front page coverage, TV cameras from NBC and CBS and radio reporters centered on the mass draft-card burning segment of the demonstration.

 

The Executive Board of SLL in 1979

Lawrence Samuels, National Chair; Kevin Kordes, national Vice-Chair; Paul O’Neil, Executive Board member; Dean Stephens, Treasurer, Barry Turnbull, Recording Secretary; Howard Hinman, Editor; Jim Gallagher, Computer Director; Ray Irvine, Executive Board member; David Lynch, Executive Board member; David Moore, Publicity Director; Pamela Falk, Secretary; Jeff Smith, Executive Board member; Alan Schoff, Executive Board member.

SLL was an affiliate of the CSUF Associated Students and affiliated with Society for Individual Liberty (SIL).

Back Cover of Booklet:

Rober LeFevre

1978

 

“Ours is a system that

is so bad that as you improve it,

it gets worse.”

 

“Governments have never really said that they are going to protect us,” Robert LeFevre argued to a large crowd at Santa Ana College (California) on May 19, 1978.

Implying that government offers vengeance and not safety, LeFevre began his two-and-a-half hour lecture by defining protection. “Protected you are safe and nothing happens to you. Governments have provided us with laws of retaliation, not laws of protection.”

LeFevre pointed out that somehow the terms retaliation, restitution and defense have been lumped together with protection. “Retaliation (or governmental protection) is made up of punishment…something inflicted by authority”, restitution is “something taken away is restored” and defense is “to curtain (a form of combat),” according to the gray-haired LeFevre. “All of those things are undesirable; what you really want is protection.”

Grasping a copy of the official FBI Crime statistic book, LeFevre began to show evidence that current governmental policing methods offer little or no protection for private citizens. Jotting figures on the blackboard behind him, LeFevre’s interpretation of FBI crime statistics show that “Police are successful only 20 percent of the time.” In 1970, 2,169,300 burglaries were reported, 19 percent were solved, 9 percent were convicted and 3 percent of the criminals served or are still serving time. “Meaning,” LeFevre explained, “if you’re a burglar, you have an 81 percent chance of doing your burglarizing without being caught, a 91 percent chance of not being convicted, and a 97 percent chance of not having to serve out your time. That’s better odds than you can get in Vegas if you own the casino.”

LeFevre stressed that one of the reasons why government protection does not protect is because, “The police are hired to keep an eye on the taxpayers as potential criminals.” In other words, “The government rips people off to get together the money to keep people from getting ripped off.”

LeFevre’s solution to the protection dilemma is to stop paying protection taxes and invest the money into their own protective devices and methods from locks, burglar alarms, private security guards and steel bars. But LeFevre’s basic idea is to get law and order services out from under the control of the ineffective and chaotic public sector. “There is bound to be an increase in crime as long as the legislature is still in session,” LeFevre said in paraphrasing mark Twain. “The government really can’t act unless it is engaged in violating boundaries because it has nothing else to do.”

 

First published in May, 1979 by Rampart Institute, a non-profit, educational organization dedicated topraxeologcial studies of human nature and action.

Transcriber: Antoinette Brenion

Layout, design, bookcover: Lawrence Samuels

Proofreader: Pamela Falk

Photographer: (Libertas Award) David Moore

Photographer: Alan Schoff

Recorder (taping): Kevin Kordes

 

© Rampart Institute
This booklet was re-published by Freeland Press, P.O. Box 22231, Carmel, CA 93922. Many of the ideas expressed in this booklet can be found in Robert LeFevre’s magnum opus book, Fundamentals of Liberty, which is available at www.lksamuels.com. Considered the definitive work on the nature of liberty, The Fundamentals of Liberty is a combination of over 25 years of work as a lecturer, author and president of Rampart College. The book took five years to complete and was finished only a few weeks before LeFevre’s death in 1986.

Lawrence Samuels worked closely with Robert LeFevre, becoming the primary founder and later president of Rampart Institute under its 501(c)(3) tax-deductible status.  His book In Defense of Chaos: The Chaology of Politics, Economics and Human Action was published in 2013 (available at www.lksamuels.com).

GOOD GOVERNMENT: HOPE OR ILLUSION?


Robert LeFevre

 

Society for Libertarian Life Edition

P.O. Box 22231, Carmel, CA 93922, lawsam1951@hotmail.com

 Lecture at Santa Ana College, CA – May 27, 1977

 

Profile of LeFevre

Robert LeFevre is one of the most influential libertarian theoreticians and authors on the West coast. It is said that he is mainly responsible for motivating the first major student libertarian movement in California in the late 1960’s. It was LeFevre’s presence at the libertarian Long Beach 1969 Con­ference that inspired student leaders across California to rally behind LeFevre’s Rampart College and libertarianism. (Professor Ludwig von Mises was the keynote speaker at the Long Beach Conference.)

Born in Gooding, Idaho, in 1911, LeFevre’s life-long love was the theater. He attended Hamline University in St. Paul to achieve that dream, but never graduated even though Hamline waived LeFevre’s freshman English requirement because of his ability. Hamline University told LeFevre that the combi­nation of courses he wanted to take would not get him a degree. LeFevre replied by saying he wanted an education instead.

In years following his college days, he took jobs ranging from newsboy to door-to-door salesman. When the United States entered World War II, LeFevre joined the Army Air Force for four years. LeFevre had no real interest in the military although he was over the draft age at the time enlisted. Publicly, he has said that he joined the Army because it was “the only proper procedure.” He served on year on General Lee’s occupation staff in Paris.

After the war, LeFevre re-entered the real estate business and soon came face to face with government restrictions. Everywhere he turned, from the real estate business to apartment owner to restaurateur, LeFevre confronted government harassment. At one time, the city wanted him to install a dry standpipe for the attachment of fire hoses. Soon he discovered that only one man was authorized by the city government to build them, and the price was anything but inexpensive.

In another instance, the office of Price Administration accused him of rent-gouging. At the time, LeFevre charged $25 a month for two-room, furnished apartments with utilities, and wanted to raise the rent to $30 a month. The increase was to cover tax increases. “When the government raises taxes,” LeFevre said, “that’s not a gouge, but when you try to earn money so you can pay your taxes, that’s a gouge.”

In 1948, LeFevre went into semi-retirement for one year to study economics and political philosophy. After discovering that government couldn’t do anything that people couldn’t do by themselves, he decided to do something. LeFevre turned to politics believing that the solution was to elect “good” people into office. He ran for Congress in the 14th Congressional District as a Republican. Since California at the time permitted cross-fling in primary elections, LeFevre lost to Democrat Sam Yorty and fellow Republican Jack Hardy.

Turned off to politics, he worked for the United Taxpayers of California until he landed a job with WQAM in Miami. Later he became the news director for WFTL-TV in Fort Lauderdale.

In 1954 he became the editorial writer for the Colorado Springs Gazette which was part of the Freedom chain newspapers owned by the Hoiles family in Santa Ana, California. A few years later he became its editor.

Remaining with the newspaper for 10 years, LeFevre started the Freedom School in 1965, as in his words, “a part time hobby.” The school was located at the base of the wooded foothills of Colorado’s Rampart Range near Larkspur. Colorado. With his second wife Loy and his four children, they renovated three uninhabitable old cabins. Eventually, they expanded to 14 dude – ranch – style log buildings with 526 acres.

The land was sold in 1966 and the operation moved to downtown Santa Ana, California. Since the move, Rampart College increasingly became the center of the West Coast libertarian movement. Students operated many of Rampart College’s ventures, which included a newsletter, a large, short-lived magazine named Pine Tree, seminars, publish­ing pamphlets and books, and sponsoring conferences like the Left-Right Festival of Liberation at USC in February, 1970. It attracted hundreds of dropouts from both the Left and Right, including such speakers as Karl Hess, Carl Oglesby, Phillip Abbott Luce, Dr. F. A. Harper, Lowell Ponte, Dr. John Hospers as well as Robert LeFevre. Organized by Dana Rohrabacher, Shawn Steel, Jean Berkman (Doug Kennell) and others with assistance from Rampart College, USC Liber­tarian Conferences are still being held today.*

By 1973 Sy Leon, author of None of the Above, became the new president of Rampart College. LeFevre retired to write books and publish his quarterly LeFevre’s Journal.

LeFevre is the author of This Bread is Mine, The Nature of Man and His Government, The Philosophy of Owner­ship, Lift Her Up, Tenderly, and a small booklet entitled The Libertarian.

Unfortunately, Rampart College closed its doors in late 1975.

 

*Rampart College worked closely with the California Libertarian Alliance during all of the USC Conferences held prior to its closure.

 

 

Introduction by Prof. Devon Showley

I wondered where this remarkable person had been hiding. Bob is a dynamic speaker and fortunately many of us had a chance to hear him again last month as he spoke at the libertarian conference (Future of Freedom Conference, 1977) at USC and again he gave us another really beautiful talk! I would have to use the word inspirational to describe it.

I never had the chance myself to be in a class that Bob has taught and that is my loss. I noticed that among those who have been in his classes, there is some sort of apotheosis that takes place. You become more than a mere mortal, Bob; so I am going to have to take a class from you sometime.

I had a chance to be in Bob’s home a few years ago. I remember two thing about this; one, the really genuine warmth and hospitality that he and Loy extended to everyone there. It was beautiful evening. Really beautiful. And another thing I remember were the books. There were over 10,000 books along the balcony circling the living room.

Bob has a rich and varied background. He has a skeleton in his closet also. We won’t hold this against him. I found out last month that he ran for Congress as a Republican many years ago. But no one is perfect.

Bob is also sort of minority with our minority libertarian movement. He is an “autarchist.” I hesitate to use labels but I believe this is the proper word. For those of you who are not familiar with it, I am sure you will know more about it before the evening is over.

He has done television, radio and newspaper work all over the United States. I suppose most of us have known of him through Rampart College in Santa Ana where he did much of his educational work. Currently, he is giving one week seminars all over the country. In fact, he is booked up at least a year in advance. I know that there is one place where he hasn’t spoken recently and I know he would like to, and that is right here in Southern California.

I also would like to mention his new book—The Power of Congress. In addition to his writing, Bob publishesLeFevre’s Journal. I am sure many of you are already on his mailing list. The caption on the masthead of LeFevre’s Journal states that it “is published every quarter approximately in Orange, California. It is not for sale, but it is supplied to those who are dedicated to human liberty and those who are dedicated make it possible.

Bob LeFevre—

 

 

GOOD GOVERNMENT: HOPE OR ILLUSION?

By Robert LeFevre

 

Thank you very much, and good evening ladies and gentlemen. This is a great pleasure for me.

In talking with the distinguished gentleman who just introduced me, he said one of the things he likes about me is that I have a sense of humor. Gosh, I hope that holds true tonight! I don’t feel particularly humorous. But it may be that things will be funnier…before I get through.

Anyway, the topic this evening, as I presume you know from the numerous blurbs that went out about it, is “Good Government: Hope or Illusion?” It is in that area that I want to concentrate my remarks.

First of all, I would like to utter a word of warning. Please, ladies and gentlemen, in my remarks I am seeking a cerebric, and not an emotive, reaction. What I mean to say is “don’t get mad.” I am going to say some things that tend, I suppose, to be a little inflammatory, but I don’t mean to inflame. I mean, instead, to engender thoughtful consideration. I think this is the prime need today.

We Americans seem to be bent on doing something, but very few of us are bent on thinking through what needs to be done. We’re a little bit like the famous general who was so patriotic that when he heard the bugle call he raced from his tent, leaped on his horse and rode off in all directions. We’re a little bit like that. We want to do things, rather than think them through.

Now I am going to talk about government. And if I do inspire you to action, make it thoughtful action. Let’s think through what we are going to do first. My presentation tonight is not intended to get you to march out of here to burnthe Post Office or something of that sort. I hope that is understood.

The second thing I had better do is to define for you what I mean by “government.” The word “government” means so many different things to so many different people that I am not always sure I’m being understood when I use the word. So I want to be sure that we are in communication on this point.

Many people, for example, equate government with almost any kind of organization. And so, if they hear me say “I don’t think we need any govern­ment,” they think they heard me say, “We don’t have to organize”—humanbeings don’t have to organize. Well, that’s NOT what I mean.

I think it is a natural thing for human beings to organize. I think it is true that no one of us has enough brains or enough time or enough energy to put the pieces together that we have to put together, if we are going to live and live inrelative comfort and happiness in this troubled world. So I am not at all opposed to organization.

However, there are two kinds of organizations, just as there as two kinds of human relationships. There are organizations which are coercive in charac­ter and organizations which are voluntary by character, just as there arerelationships between persons in the same categories. And by the way, those are the only categories we have.

The relationship that you have with another is either a voluntary or a coercive one. What else is there? That’s all there are. So when it comes to organizations it’s the same thing. There are two kinds of organizations: coercive and voluntary. What else have you got?

1 do not mean for you to relate the word “government” to organization. And it is my position, of course, that when it comes to motivating people to perform well that the carrot is always superior to the stick. I think that whenwe use coercion to get something done what tends to happen is that people will do only enough to prevent punishment. However, when there is a long, and often a visionary dream of carrots before one, there is almost no limit to what one will attempt to do in order to increase his supply of carrots. I am using the terms “carrot” and “stick” with the assumption that you are familiar with the old cliché and know what I mean.

So the thing I object to about government isn’t its organizational feature. Organization has to be accomplished. It is the coercive nature of government organization.

My argument is that we can organize better without coercion. People don’t like to be coerced; they resent being pushed around. And in consequence, they do not perform as well under coercion as they will perform if they are leftalone and inspired, encouraged by an offer of carrots.

 

THE FAMILY

Now, in speaking of organizations, I want to get to specifics. I would like to stipulate that there are three types of organizations that are basic to our species. We are going to have them regardless of what government says about them, and, I might say, government has said all kinds of things down through the ages about these organizations. These organizations are such that they provide the essential law and order that we must have. Now let me expand that one before going on.

Many times when 1 use the term “government” people think that I mean law and order. And so, if they hear me say “We don’t need government,” they think I mean we don’t need law and order. Well this is probably what makes me an “autarchist” rather than an anarchist. I think we need law and order. You see, I am dedicated to the idea of lawful and orderly procedures. And because of that I have to stand against government. Because government doesn’t provide either law or order, as I am going to show you.

The first and fundamental organization that human beings put together—and we have done this since human beings appeared on this planet so far as I know—for want of a better term. I am going to call “the family.” I am notreferring necessarily to the current legally recognized, and often abused, situation which we call monogamy. This particular arrangement is not what I am talking about: 1 am talking about something that could be termed “genetic necessity.” It just happens that our species arrived on this planet with two genders. I have been informed that there may be more, but there are at least the basic two. Now, I don’t know if that is the best design—male and female. I wasn’t consulted. This sexual division was working before I ap­peared and we’re stuck with it. But I have news for you. The boys and girls will get together. You can relax: we are going to have families. Now that is what I mean by a natural non-coercive organization. There are going to be men and women who voluntarily get together because they are men and women. We call this “genetic necessity.” It’s going to happen people. Relax. Be free. It’s going to happen. I am not suggesting indiscriminate happenings, but boys and girls will get together.

I might say that at times in the past certain governments had decreed that certain males in a given territory are required by law, by what they called law, to be married to certain women in another area as of a certain year. Youknow what has happened in those cases, historically? The men flee the territory. It isn’t that they don’t plan to have families. It’s that they plan to have their own families: when and with whom they please. And the govern­ment can go fly a kite.

Then there have been times when the government has declared that people of this particular cast or class cannot marry at all. What do you think hap­pens? They get married, when they feel like it with whom they choose. Governments constantly intrude; they constantly try to tell you that you can do certain things and that you must not do other things. But when it comes down to genetic necessity, you know what we do. We thumb our noses atgovernment and do as we please. And we are going to continue to do that. We have always done it. That’s the first type of organization — the family, based on genetic necessity.

 

BUSINESS

The second type of organization, ladies and gentlemen, for want of a better term, I am going to call “business,” or “enterprise.” Why do we have that? We happen to live on a planet in which all resources are in scarce supply.There isn’t enough to go around. And that means that for us to have the things we need so that we can stay alive and stay alive with some degree of happi­ness and comfort, it takes more than the effort of one person. We have to gettogether and put the pieces together so that we can have enough to eat, clothing to wear, and buildings to meet in and microphones and all of this nonsense, etc., etc. It takes a putting together of the resources in the hands of people who organize for this purpose or, quite frankly, we would all starve to death.

Don’t tell me that you can build something like this (LeFevre picks up the microphone). I don’t know whose this is, but, you know, it is a very delicate, complicated instrument. You cannot produce it without organization. Thepeople who put this instrument together had to have some kind of blueprint to follow. They had to draw up all kinds of diagrams, understand circuitry, build all kinds of tools. That takes careful planning, careful organization, people of great skills. And I am only talking about one little item here. There are thousands of things in this room that have been put together the same way…by human beings volunteering their skills, their energies, their time to put things together so that all of us can have more and better things. This is how we stay alive, and this is how we improve our standard of living. That is what I mean by “business,”

Business is certainly something that is carefully organized. And it is or­ganized under rules which you can call laws, if you like. For business organi­zation works that way.

If I want to buy an automobile, for example, I don’t want to buy an au­tomobile that was put together by haphazard workmen who went to work when they felt like it and did whatever they felt like doing while they were there. I want to have an automobile put together under very rigid, quality control specifications so that when that automobile comes out it will have been engineered to the peak of efficiency. And if the one I buy isn’t, I’m going to scream my head off. I want one that’s good. And. ladies and gentlemen, so do you.

That takes organization. It takes people disciplining themselves, learning how to work together. This is not one of these “Oh, let’s just go have some fun and in the process make a car.” You don’t do that. You work at it and it’s hard. But then you get something that is worthwhile. That’s the second type of organization. And, ladies and gentlemen, we’re going to have that regardless of government. It’s called “the business” and it’s based on what can be called “economic necessity.”

I don’t say that it is necessarily a happy thing. I’m saying it is necessary. Just as I don’t know that the man-woman relationship is always a happy thing. It’s necessary. These are the grim facts that face us on this particular planet before the STAR WARS take over.

Okay, so these are two of the basic organizations that we are going to have. Incidentally, government has gotten into the act on business. Well, you know that! But I mean in another way. Sometimes government has issued orders and even helped finance certain types of businesses which they wanted to encourage. You know what happens when they do that? Investors try to find some other place to put their money. If the government favors it, investors will be certain it’s a loser.

And then sometimes the government comes out and says “We forbid you to produce this.” You know what we do? We produce it anyway. We call it a “Black Market.” A black market is just a free market driven underground by some silly regulation put out by a bureaucrat somewhere. That’s all it is. Of course, we call it a criminal act because the government doesn’t know the difference between a criminal and a free man. Both of them confuse the people in government.

 

THE FRATERNITY

And then there is a third type of organization that arises out of the nature of man and the nature of the world in which we live. This third type is probably not as well known as the others. We are only today beginning to study it in depth. This organization, for want of a better name, I would like to call “the fraternity” or “the sorority,” “the brotherhood,” or “the club,” if you’ll pardon the term. What I am getting at is this. Human beings by their nature are fundamentally communicative creatures. Perhaps you haven’t thought about that particularly.

From the moment of your birth and all through your life you are going to be engaged in an almost frantic effort to communicate with other people the unique fact of your own individual existence. There is no one else quite like you. You are unique. And you are very eager to let others know about that. It’s fundamental with us; with every one of us. In consequence, we human beings have developed a vocal language. No, we have developed hundreds of vocal languages. We have written languages. We have a language of facial expression. We have a language of gesture. We have what we now call “body language” which we are only beginning to understand. Our posture, our stance, the things we wear, the places we go, the people we associate with—we employ all of these to constantly scream, “Look at me! I’m unique. Here I am! I exist in this one place in the universe and that’s me!”

What is the result of this behavior? The result of this, ladies and gentlemen, is that I want to talk to people I can reach with whatever communicative talents I may have. How do I do that? In this world there are literally thousands of things that take our attention. And the consequence is, I find, that there are people who get together, for example, because they want to communicate about, say, yachting. So we have yacht clubs. And people like to communicate with others of similar interest. “Hey, look at me! I’m a yacht captain! I own a yacht.” They want to talk to other people who have yachts because they have “yachts and yachts to talk about.” Terrible! But it’s what happens to me because my philosophy makes me happy.

There will be people who get together to organize the Boy Scouts or the Girl Scouts or the Women’s Sewing Circle or the Chowder and Marching Society, if you like chowder and like to march, or they will even organize a libertarian club or some other thing. Why? Because these are people who communicate with you in the areas of your interest. How are these groups organized? Well, when you organize these clubs, many are organized under a charter—a constitution—if you’ll pardon the expression, and many have by-laws. It’s all spelled out. The dues are so much a month, a year, or whatever. It’s all very carefully set down.

But, ladies and gentlemen, it’s still a voluntary organization: nobody has to join it. You are not compelled to get in. And if you’re in and you don’t like it, you are not compelled to stay in. You can get out.

So what do we have? We have three basic types of organization: the family, the business, and the fraternity. Each is strictly voluntary. You get into them because you like them. You move into them, in other words, because there are plus factors in it for you. If you find that the plus factors you anticipated aren’t there, then you leave. And it’s up to you whether you stay or not.

Now, here’s the interesting point. You and I spend about 98 percent of our time, our waking time, in the family, the business, or the fraternity. What else do we have? That’s where we live. That’s it. Aside from these, you’re driving somewhere.

 

GOVERNMENT: BAD AND WORSE

Now, what do you want a government for, a coercive one, when here are by-laws, rules, constitutions? We have everything arranged beautifully so ev­erything fits together in an orderly fashion and it’s all voluntary. It works beautifully. That’s where we live.

So, ladies and gentlemen, when I say I don’t think we need government, I hope you’ll understand I’m not saying, “We don’t need law and order.” Of course we need law and order! I have to explain that a little more, because some of you are still looking a little doubtful. People, government doesn’t provide law and order.

Law is always a derivative of reality. Reality binds us; that’s law. Our job is to discover reality. We don’t create reality; we discover it. You know we learn something is real? You kick it and it kicks back. Then you know.“Hey, that’s a brick wall.” You run into something, and it’s real. Its reality is impressed upon you one way or another. That’s what life is about: learning about reality. That’s where law comes from.

Ladies and gentlemen, law leads to order. In the same way, for example, here is the law of having a meeting. It’s not because I have anything to say about it, but because you cannot have a meeting unless you fulfill two re­quirements. You have to have an agreed upon time and place. Try to have a meeting sometime if you don’t have a place to meet in or a time at which to meet.

So, that’s the law of having a meeting. We didn’t ask Congress to enact that. You don’t enact those things; they just exist. We deal with reality. We have to. Well, then what does government do? Ladies and gentlemen, the governmentdeals with legislation. That is not the same as law. What is legislation? It is the opinions, the subjective judgments, if you’ll please, of a handful of people who write down what they want other people to do. That’s law? Come on! What has that got to do with reality? I mean some of these may be nice people. But they are putting down in writing, “I want those people over there to behave as I wish them to.”

Let’s be entirely fair. The people in government are at least as intelligent as we are. Though, one sometimes marvels. But let’s give them the benefit of the doubt: they were human once. But, these people at least should be able to detect reality, let’s say, as well as we can. Therefore, it is entirely possible that legislators could write a piece of legislation completely in harmony with reality. They could pass legislation which says, “We now make it law number…special law 21-12, (whatever), that all people in California wishing to have a meeting will have to first announce the time and place. That could be done. Such legislation could be passed. But, may I point out the obvious? This is a redundancy. You don’t have to enact legislation to compel people to do what they’re going to do anyway.

All right, what other kind of legislation can be enacted? Ladies and gentle­men, the only other kind is legislation that is contrary or other than natural law. It’s either in harmony with reality or it’s out of harmony with reality. What else is there? That’s all there are. Things either correspond to reality or they do not.

Reality binds us. So what can the legislators do? They can enact legislation that corresponds to reality, which is a redundancy, a foolish expense. We are already bound. We don’t need it. The only other kind of legislation possiblewould be contrary to reality. And that would be positively vicious.

So what do we have? You have two kinds of government—wasteful, redundant, unnecessary, which I would have to classify as bad. And then you have the other kind that is vicious. And that’s worse. So we have two kinds of government: BAD and WORSE. What else is there? Nothing. It comes down to bad or worse.

 

FRUSTRATION AND DISORDER

 

Now, what happens about order when government appears? The real reason for having a business, a family, or a fraternity is to engender orderly processes so we can work together in harmony towards mutually acceptableobjectives. We put the things together so that will happen. It happens; it works for us. That’s order. Now, what happens when government, as I am describing it, gets into the act with some of its legislative fiats? What happens when we are forced to do something we wouldn’t do unless forced, or we are prevented by force from doing what we normally would do?

Well, ladies and gentlemen, I think psychiatry and psychology have reached a consensus in this area. That’s unusual in itself, and should be noted. But the fact is that any person who is engaged in a perfectly proper pursuit and who knows within his own heart and mind that he is doing a perfectly proper thing suddenly confronts a bully who says to him, “I’m not going to let you do what you’re doing: you are going to do what I want you to do, and I am not going to let you keep the money you earned. That’s my money. You are only good enough to earn it; I know how to spend it better than you do.” And when this force interferes with you, you experience what is called “frustration.” That’s the technical term. You’re mad as hell. But to express it politely, you’re frustrated.

What does frustration do? Well, when you are frustrated by someone larger than you are, and you cannot strike back at him, you sort of bottle up your feelings. This creature has made you furious, but he is too big to attack. You know, you’re facing King Kong. So, what do you do? You’re pushed down, repressed, but you’re seething inside. You don’t like it. But this process repeats: it goes on. Again and again you find yourself frustrated. You get a job. Why? So that you can earn some money. Why? So that you can buy some of the things that you need to stay alive. You begin to have plans, dreams, things you want to achieve. And here is a 600-pound gorilla standing on your front doorstep telling you what you can and cannot do. You become frus­trated.

Here’s how it works. I’ll just give you a quick and very graphic illustration. A man goes to work, a nice fellow. He feels good: he had a nice weekend. He starts doing his job, whatever it is. The boss comes in. And for no reason that this fellow can observe, the boss bawls him out. Maybe the boss had a bad weekend, whatever. This young fellow now experiences frustration. Of course he could tell the boss off, but he would probably lose his job. So he doesn’t tell the boss off; he just sits there and takes it. Okay. The minute the boss’s back is turned this fellow is seething and the emotional upheaval goes on until somebody comes in that has less authority than be has. He jumps him. He gets it out of his system and lays it on the next fellow. Well, he, too, has no recourse but to bottle it up. And finally when he goes home he walks in and there is his wife. She’s smaller than he is. So he lights into her. And tells her what’s what. And, you know, she doesn’t want to get knocked down, so she bottles it up. But the kid comes in, so she lays it on the kid. And what can he do? He waits until the dog shows up and he kicks the dog. The dog yelps, runs down the street and bites the boss who lives in the next block. And that ties it together.

You have a self-perpetuating mechanism that continues to feed on itself until all of us get increasingly angry and distressed at what the government is doing. We feel absolutely helpless and shut out. And we don’t know what we can do. That’s one of the reasons why I cautioned you at the outset; please don’t be angry. Our job is to think the problem through and to see what we can do about it. But let’s think it through first. For tonight we are going to think. Later if you want to do something: that’s something else again.

So I wanted you to understand. When I am talking about government, I’m not talking about law and order. I think we need law and order. I think we get law and order out of our voluntary organizations. I am now ready to definegovernment for you. 1 would like to give you my definition.

Government is “a group of people who sell retributive justice to the inhabitants of a limited geographic area at monopolistic prices.” I think you will find that’s quite precise. I’ll repeat it; some of you are taking it down.Government is “a group of people who sell retributive justice to the inhabit­ants of a limited geographic area at monopolistic prices.”

Now. I want to give you the definition of politics, because politics is the thing that makes the government work. Politics is a method—some call it a science—some call it an art. It’s neither one nor the other. It’s a methodol­ogy. Politics is “the method employed in power structures by means of which a monopoly of coercion can be obtained and maintained.” That’s power. Now that means that the government I’m talking about is a group of people who sell retributive justice to the inhabitants of a limited geographic area through the method of getting and keeping a monopoly of coercion. That’s what I’m talking about. And that’s what we can do without in the interest of law andorder.

 

NOBODY’S CHOICE

Now, where did we ever get the idea that there is such a thing as “good government?” That is a contradiction in terms as ridiculous as “constructive rape.” There is no such thing. So what we want to do is to take a look at government to see what it is, where it came from and how it got started. Oh, and this, also. I run into this so many times. People tell me one of the great privileges we have in choosing is choosing our own form of government. Of course, anybody who wants to can choose a government. There is nothing wrong with a person having a government. There is nothing wrong with a person having a government if he wants one.

Now I’m just going to put this to you. I am going to suggest that there isn’t anybody in this room; there isn’t anybody in this city; there isn’t anybody in this state, in this nation, or in the world who has ever selected a government over him. Never! Now if you think I’m wrong, let me show you how easy it would be to have a government. I could go up to my good friend who intro­duced me and say, “Sir, I hereby appoint you as my government. I grant you the power to take whatever part of my earnings that you think you ought to have taken from me. I furnish you with a gun so that, if I resist, you can get it by force. If you feel that I’m hiding something in my house, you can kick my door down and come in and take it. If you think my wife is interfering, arrest her. Do whatever you please because I’mchoosing you as my government.” I can do that, if I can find someone who will agree to these terms and condi­tions.

That would be setting up a government of my choice. Have you ever done that? Can you think of anybody in his right mind ever having done that? Do you think anybody ever did it? People, you have been told that this happened in this country. That your forebears got together and did it. That is utter, unmitigated, uncollected garbage. It simply isn’t true. It never happened. I am sorry if this is offending anybody. I don’t mean to offend. I don’t mean to make you angry. But, it is ridiculous. I wish I had time to get into it more fully.

Do you know how governments are established? I have made a list of the things that happen. Number one is by direct force and violence. That is basic. Governments all use force directly or indirectly, because governmentsemploy politics and rely on a monopoly of coercion. So force is always there. Another procedure that some governments employ is that they convince a significant number of people in the territory over which they propose to rule that God has willed it. Therefore they are carrying out the orders from on high.

That’s a very persuasive argument. Very few people want to defy God. And if you can, convince a significant number of people that God is behind you, you can become a God in their eyes.

Then there is another method that is used.

The argument is, that although when I’m your government I’m going to kick in your door, steal your property, abuse your friends and relatives, and take your money, if you don’t let me do it, there is a guy bigger than I am on the other side of the hills. And he’ll hurt you worse! So you had better take it from me because I’m a nice fellow. This argument is called the lesser of two evils.

Next you are told that your ancestors approved of government. You we­ren’t around. But your ancestors did it and because your ancestors did it, you are stuck with it. You leave no recourse but to do as your ancestors wantedyou to do. That’s a very interesting point of view.

And then, of course, this one is often heard. No matter how bad the govern­ment is, it’s better than not having one. Because if you didn’t have a govern­ment, you would have chaos. Now we are back to a point I have already triedto remove. The government doesn’t provide law and order. It never did. It simply provides frustrations leading to disorder, legislation and so on.

And then we have this approach; the supposition that once you have a government your neighbors will be able to support you above and beyond your ability or willingness to support yourself. Government is endorsed for that reason.

And finally it is believed that the government will not do to you what you confidently want it to do to your neighbor.

 

PYRAMIDAL GOVERNMENT

These are the reasons that you justify government and ask it to exist.

Now, when we got started with our noble experiments here in this country a number of years ago, we had been following the example of Great Britain to a large degree. And Great Britain, of course, had produced a government that was originally an unlimited monarchy. The king was at the top of the struc­ture. And everybody else was down below. The king had total, unbridled power.

Now, of course, all government is pyramidal in shape. There will be some­body at the top and everybody else will be less high in the pyramid.

Let me put this down. The first prerequisite, if you are going to have a government de facto, (That’s the only kind that interests me; one that works. I’m not interested in governmental theories or all the various niceties fre­quently discussed.) is a ruler—someone at the top. Absolutely essential. And I don’t know of anyone who said it better than Harry Truman. He said, “The buck stops here.” There has to be somebody at that desk where the buck stops. That’s the way governments work. This is the rule when it comes to making decisions. Somebody has to make the ultimate decision. And the fellow sitting at the top in a government, and I mean at the top, well, the buck can’t go past him. He’s at the apex. You have to have somebody in that position.

There has always been a certain belief fostered in this country that the way we arranged our government prevented having a man at the top as a ruler. I am going to deal with that so hang in there. I’ll be at that point in a few minutes.

What happened, of course, back in the early days when we first began to have monarchs, the king was usually a nice young fellow. So we put him at the apex of the triangle and gave him power. We cheered him and the energy of our support revved up and became power in use. Once that topmost position was occupied by the ruler, then he began to crack the whip and power flowed from the top down. We put the king in an exalted position, but he was a nice fellow when we put him there. Then he began to rule. And he said, “I want her arrested. I want him eaten.” And various other orders were given. And we carried out his wishes. Presently, we begin to say, “What happened to our king? You know, when we put him up there he was a nice guy. But now, he’s hurting us.” And we begin to conspire against him. And pretty soon we do one of two things. We either endured it until he died or we got rid of him one way or another. Sometimes we chased him off his throne and sometimes we killed him before he could get out the door. But we got rid of him. In the meantime we placed another fellow in the wings because he has already assured us by saying, “I’m going to be a good king.” We believed it. So we crowned him and relaxed and we said, “Now we have a good king.”

Then the new king gets this power, you see. And he begins saying, “Pass this law…Arrest this fellow… Do this.” And we finally say, “What happened to him?” So we get rid of him and get another king.

Age after age we did this with monarchs. When the monarch first was crowned we loved him. Then he began acting as a person would act if his mother barked. And finally we said, “Ah, the problem is not the man, the problem is the structure. We built it wrong. We shouldn’t put anybody at the top. No one man has enough brains or wisdom to handle that accumulation of power.” So we built an oligarchy.

An oligarchy means rule by a few. We would elect or appoint or shake dice for oligarchs. You get a bunch of anywhere from 3 to 60, you know, depending on the population you are trying to placate.

Then you put the bunch up there. And you say the beauty of this is that no one man will have all power. Everybody at that level has the same power as every other person. The first thing that happens when you get an oligarchy is that when they meet, one of them is chosen as chairman.

You have to have order. It’s a necessity. The chairman picks up the gavel. The minute he picks up the gavel a little pimple of power forms over him. And as he uses the gavel, the power intensifies and the pimple becomes a boil. Andhe keeps on using it and the boil enlarges and becomes a carbuncle. And then you’re back where you started, with one man as a ruler.

As a matter of fact, this has happened with every oligarchy we ever had. Every oligarchy has converted into one-man rule sooner or later, most of them into direct dictatorship. This is not because of the nature of man. It’s because of the nature of the political method in structures of the type I am talking about. We have played around with this and the result was exactly the same as when we had a monarch—the accumulation of power in the hands ofthe man on the top, with power rolling down to oppress, intimidate, terrify and kill. Finally we say, “Oligarchy is no good. Let’s get rid of that. Let’s get something closer to the base.” And we invented democracies and republics. And those are theoretically awfully cute things. Because the idea is that the people at the base are going to elect people at the next line and so on up the ladder; each stratum gets together and elects people at the next level and so on up, until you ascend into heaven. And then, of course, when you arrive at the top, you have a man who does the same thing again.

 

THE AMERICAN EXPERIENCE

Now when we came to the American experience, we said we wanted to avoid the errors of other democracies and republics. We were inspired by the British experience. Britain, as I mentioned earlier, had had an unlimited monarchy. And prior to the landings at Plymouth and Jamestown and so on, they had created a parliament. And the parliament, in effect, provided a second branch of government. They had the parliament, but they also had the king.

The British thought they were on the right track because when they went into the throne room and said, “Your majesty, how would you like to have a parliament over here that can check your actions?” And he said, “I don’t like it at all.” And they said, “We’re on the right track.” And then they went over and talked to parliament and said. “How would you like it if every time you do something you still would have to get the king’s approval?” They said, “That’s terrible. We know enough to run the show.” So they said, “Well, at last we are doing the right thing. Because now these two areas will check each other. And that will prevent the growth of this colossal structure with some­body on top.”

When we got started in this country, we were inspired by the British experience. And we said, “If two points at the top are good, three would be better.” So we decided to have an oligarchy of branches—executive, legisla­tive and judicial. And each one, theoretically, would have the same power, and in consequence, we would have a limited government. And of course, whenever you ask these people, you say to the President, “What do you think of having Congress pass laws and the Supreme Court ruling on constitutional­ity?” The President would say, “That’s terrible. I cannot run the country with my hands tied.” Then you go to the legislative branch and ask them and they are always upset about the President and the Supreme Court. And you go to the Supreme Court, and you experience their dissatisfaction. So Ameri­cans rejoiced and said, “We’ve got a triple deal here, where each branch checks the other.”

Do you know what has happened? I know you do.

(LeFevre picks up a book.)

I showed this down at USC a month ago, and I thought maybe you people would like to see it, too. This is the current issue of the “U.S. Government Organizational Manual.” Government gets this out every year, and this is thelatest edition.

In this single volume the federal government lists all of its functions. I want you to see what’s in the volume. This is your government. That’s what it says. The Constitution of the United States is here in the first part, together with theAmendments to date and a chart. See, they have a chart.

Then we go over here to what is called the “legislative branch,” starting on page 25. Here is a listing of the officers of the Senate and the House, and a very well written description of how these two bodies function. Here are thecharts. They always have charts. Then we have the “standing committees.” See, they have the chairman of the standing committees. The chairman sits and the standing committee stands. Then we have the various standing committees explained.

Here, we have the names of the Senators identified by name, state and party affiliation. They’re all here; by name, state and party affiliation. They’re all here; this is current. Next we have the Representatives, byname, state, party and election district…all listed. And, of course, there are a lot of these. You have no idea how many salaries you pay. But here they are. Several pages of them.

Now we come to the architect of the Capitol. I know you are relieved to know that we have one. The architect of the Capitol, by the way his name is George M. White, is a bureau under the legislative branch. The architectreports directly to the legislature. And his job is to act as the agent of Congress in looking at the government buildings in Washington. That is what he docs; he looks at the buildings.

Here’s the United States Botanic Garden. That is another bureau under the legislature and the fellow heading that is George M. White. He’s not a botanist, but he’s an awfully nice fellow. This is called consolidation. We’rereducing the size of government. And his function is to look at the gardens. So the same man does both now: he looks at the buildings and he looks at the gardens, and it’s all explained.

Next we have the General Accounting Office. Listed are the chief accoun­tants and a description of how the office works, and the charts and the descriptions continue. This is also a legislative function, as you can see.

And here we have the Government Printing Office. This is under the legis­lature. The names of the printers and how they work and a chart—the whole bit.

Then comes the Library of Congress, obviously Congressional, under the legislative branch, the names of the librarians; and here’s the chart. It’s all spelled out. Very carefully written.

Costs Accounting Standards Board. This is a new one. They just got it, and they are now accounting for the standards. Here it is. (LeFevre points to that section in the book.) And here is the index. It’s so new it hasn’t grown much. Just a few inches.

And here is the Office of Technology Assessment, which was born big! It’s new, but it’s quite big to start with.

And here’s the Congressional Budget Office. And that’s brand new. And that does it.

Ladies and Gentlemen, to list all of the people in the legislative branch and to describe all they do, including every Senator and Congressman in the United States, it takes from page 25 to page 63, including the charts. Thismuch of the book is devoted to the legislative branch.

Now we come to the judicial branch: the Supreme Court of the United States, with the names of the members and officers and a description of what they do. The lower courts are described. The judicial circuits are listed.(LeFevre pointing to a part of the book…) This is the Federal Appellate Court with the names of the judges and even their addresses. They haven’t got their phone numbers, but they’re all listed here so you can find them. Special courts are described, as is the United States Customs Court. This is de­scribed. And here’s the Administrative Office of the United States Courts and the Federal Judicial Center, which is brand new. That terminates the judicial section. It takes from page 67 to page 79 to list all of the people and describe all of the functions of the judicial branch.

(LeFevre fans hundreds of pages of the book in front of the audience.) As you see, this is called a “limited government of checks and balances.” What happened? The Executive Branch runs from page 83 to page 662. Whathappened is exactly what happened before.

We built this kind of structure, and we put three of these things on it. (LeFevre draws three closely fitted pyramids together on a blackboard and draws the middle pyramid larger and larger until it engulfs the two smallpyramids.) And we said they will check each other. The result was that one of them got bigger and bigger and bigger, and you’re back where you started. Why? Because, ladies and gentlemen, there is no such thing as “limitedgovernment,” anymore than there is such a thing as “good government.” That’s impossible.

 

THE CONTRADICTION

Now I doubt if anybody in his right mind would favor unlimited govern­ment. But when you favor government, that’s what you’re doing. Because government, by its very nature, is unlimited. You favor tyranny when you favorgovernment; though you don’t know it. This is why I am constantly staggered by those who say they are libertarian and are trying to set up their own particular way of providing a “good government.” It is a contradiction in terms. To say “unlimited government” is a redundancy and to say “limited government” is a contradiction. All you have to say is “government.” And that takes care of the whole thing.

Ladies and gentlemen, with the passing of time, as historians begin writing what has transpired in our own time, we’ll perhaps begin to learn that the entire Watergate episode that we are still on the fringes of, was probably littlemore than a power struggle in Washington—a struggle between the executive branch, the legislative, and the judicial branches. Certainly, you people un­sophisticated enough to know that this is not the first time that someone in high office has been caught with his hand in the cookie jar.

We have had corruption in government since government started. In fact, I have often felt that the best administration we had was George Washington’s. That, too, was corrupted, and it has been downhill since. But I wanted you to grasp the point that you can’t have a government without a ruler. However you try to design the government, it’s going to end up with a man at the top. Now he may not be the chief executive; he could be the chief justice. He could be the prime minister. He could be the chairman of the central committee. You can call him anything you wish. But if you are going to have a govern­ment de facto, you have to have a ruler.

 

SANCTION OF THE VICTIM

 Now ladies and gentlemen, let’s take the next point. To have a government de facto, there must be more than a ruler. In addition, you have to obtain a very special reaction which I am going to give by its exact name. It is called “sanction.” But it is a particular type of sanction. I am indebted to Ayn Rand for the phrase. She didn’t use it quite as I am going to, but she said it better than I could have. She said it is “the sanction of the victim.” And I want to make that point.

First before dealing with the sanction of the victim, let me sketch out a few of the characteristics that accompany all rulers sooner or later.

Whenever a person decides that he wishes to be a ruler, he develops certain psychological trails. In a few cases in history, ladies and gentlemen, we have had a man suddenly thrust into a position of rulership to which he did not aspire. When it happens, the same thing occurs, but there is a little lapse of time before you can detect it. But all rulers and would-be rulers have the same traits sooner or later.

What they develop, first of all, is an enormous self-confidence. They believe they are right. They believe that their opinions are objectively right. Their view is “The View.” If you differ, you are in error. I might say, many of us have this characteristic to some degree. Most of us, by the time we get past the age of twelve or thirteen, are pretty sure we know what’s what. So we all have that characteristic, but there is a very peculiar thing that happens to the psychology of the would-be ruler. Whereas most of us might feel very confident about the validity of our opinions, we also have a mediating feeling of weakness. Most of us find ourselves to consist of a bundle of good points and bad points, but we do detect failings in certain places. And if we are thinking as ordinary people, we usually find that, while we think that we are right, we also feel that somehow we don’t have the ability of convincing others of just how right we are. And that we feel inadequate while also feeling confident. This keeps us in balance.

But if you are a ruler or a would-be ruler, when you should have the feeling of inadequacy, you don’t. What you have is a feeling that the reason you can’t convince the other party is his fault, not yours. You’re right, and he’s wrong. He’s not only wrong, but he’s stupid. Because your position is absolutely right and he should see it. It’s not your fault that you cannot explain it. It’s his fault because he doesn’t grasp it.

That leads to a very interesting phenomenon called sublimation. The ruler buries his feelings of inadequacy. He can’t admit it, even to himself. This leads the ruler into a position where he attains what could be called “self-righteousness.” If you don’t agree with him, then he is justified in doing whatever is necessary to bring you intoline. If he has to tax you, that’s all right. If he has to fine you, that’s all right. If he has to put you on the rack and torture you or whatever, it’s quite all right.

The ruler is self-righteous. He has to be. The consequence is that he can order a country into war, plunge itinto a series of atrocities, command assassinations, mayhem and destruction. Then he can go to bed and sleep like a baby with a clear conscience. Because he’s right. And in the end the evil he does will all add up to good. So this is the characteristic that you find in rulers, sooner or later.

We had a case here in the United States, where a fellow became our top man and he had never planned on it. You know, the mantle was dropped on him. He never quite recovered. And you could see for the first few months that he(President Ford) was a little stunned by what had happened. But then the gleam began to appear in the eye. You have witnessed it. Anyway, that’s the characteristic of the ruler: self-righteousness.

Let’s return to the point I left in mid-air. You have to have sanction of the victim, as well as a ruler. And the sanction of the victim, ladies and gentle­men, is this: the government must have the approval of an enormous sectionof the entire population. I don’t care what kind of government it is—democ­racy, dictatorship, anything at all—it doesn’t matter. Obviously, any ruler or would-be ruler can get a following by promising goodies to people. He can say, “If you back me, I’ll let you eat at my table, and there will always be crumbs that I can provide for my loyal followers.” So people will line up behind him, and you have that type of sanction—the sanction or approval of those who are joyfully following this particular would-be leader.

But that won’t give you a government. All that provides is a faction. Government is a very peculiar hybrid that not only has to have the approval of those who favor it, but also it has to win the approval of those who know thegovernment is going to injure them. And they have to approve even their own injury. That’s what is meant by “sanction of the victim.”

You know you’re going to be victimized, but you approve anyway. That’s the hat trick. Until a government is able to win sanction of the victim, it cannot stand; because a government is more than just power alone. Poweralone is the military and the military can always conquer, but conquering isn’t the same as ruling. The government has to be able to win the sanction of the very people the government proposes to shaft.

 

THE LESSER OF TWO EVILS

There are two tried and true methods which are employed to obtain sanction of the victim. I won’t have to go into one of them in depth because I know you’re familiar with it. It is the most widely used in this country. It is called”The Lesser of Two Evils.” I have already mentioned it as one of the ways in which a government is established. In this country we have two major political parties, and we always have champions from both. Then each candidate will tell you that the other fellow is worse than he is. And you weigh the relative damage that is going to come from each, and you vote for the lesser of the evils. This is the way it is done, and I am sure you’re aware of it. You’ve seen it.

This last time, this last presidential election, was probably not as good an illustration as we sometimes have had, by reason of the fact that Mr. Ford was not too well known, really, except you knew he was there. You couldn’t get angry with him. I mean, we had a man who couldn’t go down the stairs without difficulty. I mean, he was a nice fellow. Opposing him was a fellow from a peanut farm that you don’t know anything about. And you can’t really get angry with him either. So actually the race was close. And it just hap­pened that the people who looked at Ford versus Carter (more of them, and only under, I think, two million was the differential) said, “Well, we pretty well know what Ford is going to do, but we aren’t quite sure what Carter is going to do. After all, what could a guy from Georgia do?” And so they voted for Carter a little bit more than they did for Ford.

If you want a good example of the very thing I am talking about, go back to the prior election when Nixon went in by a landslide. Now, you know, the American public has never been enthusiastic about Mr. Nixon, but they voted for him overwhelmingly. Why did they do that? Well, you know why — a fellow named McGovern. In fact, Nixon didn’t campaign; he didn’t have to. He stayed in Washington. McGovern did the campaigning. Every time McGovern opened his mouth, he got votes for Nixon. Greatest ploy that Nixon could have had. In fact, Nixon was putting money into the McGovern cam­paign to keep McGovern from going down the tubes. It wasn’t that people liked Nixon, but… “McGovern”… “Oh, not McGovern”… “Anybody but McGovern.” This is how Nixon got the votes. This is the lesser of two evils, as we see it domestically.

 

INTERNATIONAL LEVEL

 I don’t know if this has occurred to you. We employ the same technique internationally. You may not have thought of that. But, ladies and gentlemen, the greatest asset that the American government has had for years has been the Russian government. Oh, yes. If, at any time, the American public stood up and acted a little bit independent, you know what happened? An American politician would say. “Now wait just a minute. If it weren’t for us, the Russians would come in and they would impose communism on you. And do you know what would happen? When they imposed communism, you would be forced to work where they told you to, at a wage that they would decide, and you’d be drafted into their armies. And if you disobeyed, you’d be tried and sent lo their prisons. Anything could happen. So, support us and we’ll tell you where to work and what you are going to earn and draft you into our armies. And if you disobey, we’ll try you or we’ll send you to jail or whatever, but it is better to be shafted by an American than a Russian.”

Now, while we are doing that, the same thing is happening over in Russia. Brezhnev or Kosygin or whomever stands up and says. “Ah, do you hear those warmongering capitalists in America? You better not get fresh with us. We are Mother Russia. You support us because if it weren’t for us, the American imperialists would be over here and they would impose capitalism on you. And you know what would happen? The big corporations would tell you where to work, and they would tell you how much you could earn, and they would compel you to do as they said. And they would draft you into their armies, and they would arrest you if you disobeyed, and punish you, and might even shoot you, so do as we say and we’ll protect you from these capitalists.” And the Russians say “Da, da. Don’t let the Americans come in. That would be terrible. If we gel shafted, let it be a Russian shaft.”

Meantime, the two leaders put in a telephone system and talk to each other about the weather because they are in the same club.

Look back in history. It takes a powerful foe to build a powerful nation. Rome might never have attained itsgreatness had it not been for Carthage. Carthage posed a threat, the Romans were told. England might not have attained its greatness had it not been for Spain and, later, France. You have to have the opposition scare your people. Show them that, “If you don’t take me, there’s a guy nine-feet high coming over the hill, and he’s going to do it to you worse than I will. So I’m going to do it to you, but I am your friend.” That is the lesser of two evils.

 

DIVIDE AND CONQUER

Then there is “divide and conquer.” And if you don’t quite see the application here, let us just briefly show it to you. The man who explained it better than anyone else, if you want to look it up, is a guy named Julius Caesar. You can read about it if you want to, but let me explain it briefly.

When the government uses “divide and conquer,” it sows suspicion so that the people who would naturally tend to affiliate will distrust each other. Thus, they don’t affiliate. The consequence is that everyone distrusts his neighbor. But everyone trusts the government. Let me just act it out for a moment to tell you what 1 mean.

We set up a government, and we elect somebody who now says, “I am your representative.” I don’t care what level of government he is from. He goes before a group of people such as this, and he says, “I represent everybody in this district. Do you people in this district have any problems? I’m in Washington (or wherever) to help. What problems do you have?”

Suppose that he gets in front of some people who have a water shortage. They will immediately say to him. “We’ve got to do something; we have a water shortage.” And he will listen to everything they say, and he will respond. “You know, you’re right. I can see your point. It’s a good thing I represent you. I’m going to go back to Washington and see what I can do to get some legislation passed in your favor to make it rain or whatever has to be done.” Now this same man or another and, people, it doesn’t really matter — “Republican,” “Democrat,”… whatever—it doesn’t matter, the face of a politician has no features. It’s like an ad for Dristan.” Nothing is there. (The advertisement for Dristan on television shows a human face without features.)

So this fellow stands in front of a group of people who happen to have a supply of water. And he says, “Do you people have any problems?” They say. “Do we ever. We’re drowning.” He says. “It’s a good thing I came because I can see your problem, and I am going to go to Washington to see if I can enact some legislation to save your lives.” They relax and say, “It’s a good thing we have someone to represent us because we don’t trust those people who want our water.” And the people who want the water don’t trust the people who have the water. And what happens? Now you have a schism. But both sides trust the government to solve the problem.

Take a quick look at what has happened to American society. In this country the workers do not trust the businessman; managers don’t trust workers; and workers don’t trust managers. There is a rift between them as wide as the Grand Canyon, which is absurd in itself, since both are on the same side serving customers. But there is a rift.

Both sides look to Washington to solve the problem. Each faction believes Washington is going to pass legislation in its favor. Washington is its friend. The rich don’t trust the poor, the poor don’t trust the rich. But both look to Washington to solve the problem. The South doesn’t trust the North. North doesn’t trust the South. But they both look to Washington to solve the problem. The Blacks don’t trust the Whites. The Whites don’t trust the Blacks. But both look to Washington to solve the problem. The Chicanos don’t trust the Blacks. The Blacks don’t trust the Chicanos. The Chicanos don’t trust the Whites. The Whites don’t trust the Chicanos. But they all look toWashington to solve the problem. The people who wear long hair don’t trust those with short hair, and those with short hair don’t trust those with long hair. But Washington will take care of everything.

We’ve even gotten to the place where the men don’t trust the women. The women don’t trust the men. But Washington is going to take care of that one, too. The kids don’t trust their parents. The parents don’t trust their kids. We have a nation that has been smashed into a thousand shards of what were once a single great people. And this is the method called “divide and conquer.” We are suspicious of everybody in our block, but “Big Daddy” will look after us. He has a Band-Aid to fit. And will take care of any of your problems and whatever you need. That’s all that is needed to destroy a people… to conquer…to make them abject and subservient. That’s “divide and conquer.”

We have used both of these methods in this country. So we have a ruler and the sanction of the victim. These are the two most important items.

 

ACHILLES’ HEEL

Let me point out one enormously important factor. This particular area is the government’s Achilles’ heel because, my dear friends, government cannot take sanction from you by force. That is impossible. The government can take your money: the government can take your property: it could even take your life—all of those are actions of force. But the government cannot take your sanction. That you have to give. But please realize, the government cannot stand without your sanction. You have a handle on the problem, if you care to use it. You can withdraw your sanction. And you can do it peacefully. You can do it effectively. That doesn’t mean running for Congress, as I did once. I had that idea once. The reason I am speaking as positively as I am here is because I had all the characteristics that I’ve described. I was going to get into government and straighten you all out. I was going to do it for your own good…if I had to kill you to do it. Certainly, I know. I’ve been there.

Sanction of the victim gives you the whip hand.

 

POINT OF CONTACT

Let me offer one other idea.

There must be a “point of contact” between ruler and ruled, if you’re going to have a government de facto. That is, a point where physical imposition is exerted by the government upon the governed. One of the great myths that wehave is the belief that you and I are the government. Now, you and I are not the government. You and I are the “governed.” The government is up here. (LeFevre points to the top of the pyramid drawn on the blackboard directlybehind him.) And you and I are down here. (LeFevre points to the base of the pyramid.)

What has happened in this case is that by virtue of the democratic process, you have been conned into believing that voting means you’re running the show. You’re not. If you doubt that, you can prove it to yourself tonight. Go out of here to the nearest phone and call Mr. Carter and tell him you don’t want any government benefits this year and you are not going to pay any taxes. You have decided not to patronize the goods and services of the government. And you would like him to take his sticky fingers out of your pocket. Then let me know what cell you’re in so I can send you a postcard. You are not running anything, though you may have been told you are.

The system we have is essentially analogous to this. Imagine a penitentiary in which quadrennially the inmates elect their warden. That doesn’t mean they’re running the jail. They never get out of their cells.

Now, for a contact point to exist, the government has to perform a public act that is recognized by the people as being a kingly act. It ties back to this. The government has to establish publicly that it can obtain obedience. Let me see if I can make it clearer.

Today, the government concentrates in the field of taxation. Taking your money isn’t absolutely essential. But, making you obey is. The government today has a monopoly in the field of money and credit. I know many people imagine that they could control the government if they didn’t pay their taxes. My dear people, the government could declare all the money presently in circulation to be null and void and issue a new currency. You need your money, but the government needs your sanction; they are not the same. Because you and I need our money we often think that by refusing to pay taxes we could get the stranglehold on government. I think we are deluding ourselves if we think so. The government doesn’t need your money; it needs your sanction.

 

RULING THE RULED

Let me describe what I mean this way. If any of you are familiar with the writings of Lewis Baudin, who is viewed as the authoritative author concern­ing the Incas of Peru, you may be familiar with his study in which he shows that the chief of the Incas faced a real problem when it came to getting a tax from one village. This village was so poor that it had absolutely zero surpluses. And that meant that if the chief of the Incas taxes them at all, someone in the village would die. And that is no way to keep a flock of sheep. If you start killing off the flock, you know you’re a bad shepherd.

So the Incan chief had to figure out a way in which he could tax, or the people in that village would forget that he ruled them. That’s the real point. Not the money, the obedience. And believe it or not, he finally figured out just such a tax. He ordered all of the villagers to sit down annually and search their persons for a flea. Fleas comprised the only surplus the village had. One flea was collected from each individual, shoved into the hollow stem of a quetzal feather and a fast runner took that feather down to Cusco, the capital city, and paid the tax for the village. By that process the people in the village were kept subservient. A public act had occurred in which the people bowed and did as they were told. Thus, the mythology was maintained, and govern­ment rule was maintained.

Knowledgeable individuals are rarely in a position to confront the government when a show of force is present. But each of us can withdraw his sanction by voluntary, peaceful and even legal means. There is nothing in theConstitution or in law that says you have to approve of it. All that is said is that you must obey. Nonetheless, the government is counting on your approval, for without it, they will be unable to rule. Thus, sanction is in your own hands. You can withdraw it any time you choose.

 

Back Cover:

Robert LeFevre is one of the most powerful lecturers and authors in the United States. His lecture “Good Government: Hope or Illusion?” at Santa Ana College is a classic in wit and common sense which has made LeFevre almost a legend in his own time.

Never before has anyone defined the role of government so brutally precise. “Government is,” LeFevre repeated twice to the audience, “a group of people who sell retributive justice to the inhabitants of a limited geographic area at monopolistic prices.” LeFevre continued, “Politics is the method employed in the power structures by means of which a monopoly of coercion can be obtained and maintained…This is what we can do without in the interest of law and order.”

Founder and former president of Rampart College, LeFevre constantly reminded his listeners that he is an “autarchist,” and not an anarchist because he strongly supports law and order. And since government is usually unlawful and disorderly, LeFevre pointed out, the need for government has few merits if any.

As for good government, LeFevre contended that there is no such thing as good government. “That is a contradiction in terms as ridiculous as ‘constructive rape.’”

LeFevre’s “Good Government: Hope or Illusion?” is a must for any libertarian library.

 

This booklet was re-published by Freeland Press, P.O. Box 22231, Carmel, CA 93922.  Many of the ideas expressed in this booklet can be found in Robert LeFevre’s magnum opus book, Fundamentals of Liberty, which is available at www.lksamuels.com. Considered the definitive work on the nature of liberty, The Fundamentals of Liberty is a combination of over 25 years of work as a lecturer, author and president of Rampart College. The book took five years to complete and was finished only a few weeks before LeFevre’s death in 1986.

 

Lawrence Samuels worked closely with Robert LeFevre, becoming the primary founder and later president of Rampart Institute under its 501(c)(3) tax-deductible status.  His book In Defense of Chaos: The Chaology of Politics, Economics and Human Action was published in 2013 (available at www.lksamuels.com).

A lecture by Robert LeFevre at Rampart College in the mountains near Colorado Springs.

“Government is a disease masquerading as its own cure.”

–Robert LeFevre

Foreword to Truth is Not a Halfway Place by Carl Watner


by Karl Hess


It is a measure of the breadth of Robert LeFevre’s influence and character that so many will remember him for so many different reasons. Teacher. Schoolmaster. Consultant. Businessman. Philosopher. Soldier. Religionist. Social Theorist. Debater. Author. Socratic Goad. Experimenter. Maddening Demander of Consistency. Searcher. Finder. Good Friend. Implacable Foe. All of that is detailed in this book.

My special reason for remembering him is civility. His. Not mine. Being given to temper and rash actions, I always felt that Bob was a great anchor to windward, reminding me that it is possible, indeed desirable, to keep a steady helm and an even keel even in the stormiest debate of contention.

Bob’s civility was majestic. It made him seem as a great rock around which angry waves could crash, but which they could never submerge or move.

Bob actually acted as though humans, being rational, would recognize thoughts that coincided with material reality, and then act accordingly. That belief, that informed thought will move an individual – an institution – a people – to action is one of the human race’s most enduring optimisms.

But many develop cynicism, seeing such a belief as an illusion. Others, doubting people will change themselves, see it as a rationale for imposing their ideas on others. LeFevre seemed to me to be an alternative. He acted on his beliefs. He certainly encouraged others to do the same, to understand what he understood. But he neither despaired cynically of the project, or roared in frustration for a crusade to teach the heathen. He saw the world in terms of individuals. His appeal was not to society. It was not to history, or humanity, or future generations, or to any such abstraction.

His difference would be with you. His agreement would be with you. He did not want to change the world. Individuals changing were the only way the world would ever change. And he felt that only you could change yourself. He did not, to cut to the core of it, want intermediaries of coercion in that process. Life, in his view, should be a matter of self-controlled, volitional actions between free humans.

Of all the intermediary forces that LeFevre despised and abhorred, violence was foremost. According to him, violence – certainly not money – was the root of all evil. Without violence, for instance, all humans would be free to make up their own minds about their own lives. The alternative to violence was infinitely more exciting: the opportunities for self-owned and self-controlled individuals to make voluntary agreements among themselves.

LeFevre’s main point, which he once summed up in an interview, was that each of us should “Do as you please – but harm no other in his person or property.”

From that position can be extrapolated everything that LeFevre taught and talked about. He tenaciously held that the individual was the key to it all. Not tides of history. Not winds of war. Not storms of ideology. Not pressure of politics. The individual must and does make up his or her own mind whether to be free or controlled. The person who submits to outside control “believes” that some one or some institution has the authority, the right to control the person. But, LeFevre believed that by nature humans are free, unique, and if they will it, absolutely able to control themselves.

Perhaps the most discord and confusion were generated by those who viewed his position as simple pacifism. His position rejected violence even in self-defense. He could see no gain for freedom in using the tool of tyranny – violence. But his wasn’t a position of simple pacifism, not a position simply in opposition to violence. It was a position in favor of the centrality of individualism, with violence seen as something to be resisted, not in the abstract, but in the concrete sense that it violated human self-control.

I have known many who profess what I think of as simple pacifism. They focus on the violence itself. They will not be violent against anyone else. To be violent would be to sin against someone, to commit a wrong against the person to whom the violence is directed. LeFevre’s point was subtle, and different. Although he shared the pacifist’s concern of what violence would do to someone else, LeFevre especially abhorred it because of what it would do to him! He taught that inflicting violence corrupts one’s own character. LeFevre was 100% consistent in a position from which he would absolutely refuse to harm another person. He could obviously hope that the refusal to do harm would be reciprocated, but he also knew that only he could be responsible for his own actions.

He proclaimed his position. He taught it to all who would voluntarily, listen. He would impose it upon no one. And he would live by his position as an individual though the entire universe might be against him.

LeFevre’s whole world view was a wonderfully comprehensive one. This is best seen by his attitude toward politics and government.

He did not believe for an instant in the possibility of good coming from political action, nor did he harbor any illusion about “improving” an institution so dependent upon violence as the State. The institution was beyond redemption, in his view, since – even with angels at the controls – it would still depend upon violence to enforce its actions.

He realized that some people want to be controlled by government. He never suggested that they be denied the fulfillment of that need. He never suggested overthrowing the politics that fed that need. He did advocate withdrawing from it completely. “Let the State exist for those who want it, but let it not harm me or any other who does not want it.”

Just as his refusal to engage in violence was not simple pacifism, his denunciation of the State was not simple anarchism. Anarchism, which is opposition to the institution of the State, is an ideological shelter for many positive forces as well as the single negative one of opposing the State.

It was many of those positive forces that LeFevre opposed with as much vigor as he opposed the State itself. For instance, the attacks by many anarchist against private property were absolutely contrary to LeFevre’s dictum of doing what you will without harming another. Peaceful humans who produce wealth, or other property, or who claim land, would never be dispossessed in a truly free society, one free of the institutionalized violence of the State. The ownership of self implies the ownership of those things associated with the labors of the self. Thus property. To dispossess someone of property, no matter how benign the motive, implies the use of force, violence.

On the other hand, the single negative position of anarchism, opposition to the State, was too narrow for LeFevre. He felt that the positive virtues of individualism were greater than mere opposition to an institution.

LeFevre’s position most closely parallels libertarian or free market anarchism, with its consistent defense of rights of ownership, and of individual self-ownership. Yet, he saw as clearly as anyone a most interesting paradox. Some of these same libertarians participated in political action, even while forswearing the use of force to accomplish political, social, or personal goals. How, he often goaded them, could they both renounce force while participating in a process founded fully upon it?

Education, person-by-person, no matter how tedious and slow, was the only fitting course for the improvement of the human condition – the only course consistent with what LeFevre saw as the nature of humans to be absolute controllers of their own selves. Education of the individual, the freedom education which is at the heart of this book, was the only alternative which justified its ends by its means.

It is a great measure of the civility of Bob LeFevre, that he could gently abide – without approving – the actions and friendship of many who, for simply utilitarian purposes (being nowhere near as composed in principle as Bob was), flirted with politics. As one of those myself, I was always mindful of Bob’s great patience, the truly caring nature of his advice, and, finally, the clear rightness of his principles.

Of all the people I have known, Bob LeFevre, more than anyone else, would want every individual to steer his or her own course, being fully responsible for its every twist and turn. LeFevre left us all a fine example and a magnificent chart. He did not leave us any command to sail. That, he knew, and we all should know, is up to each of us.

What is Secession?


by Donald W. Livingstone
Reprinted with permission of Rob Williams. Appeared November 2005 in Vermont Commons

 

Talk about secession makes Americans nervous. For many it evokes images of the Civil War, and is emotionally (if not logically) tied to slavery, war, and anarchy. That the word “secession” is laden with these negative connotations should be surprising since America was born in an act of secession. The Declaration of Independence is a secession document justifying an act whereby “one people…dissolve the Political Bands which have connected them with another.” George Washington, John Adams, and Thomas Jefferson were secessionists. Americans should be the last people in the world embarrassed by the thought of secession. To understand both why secession is at the heart of the American political tradition and why Americans are nervous about it, we need to review the strange history of the idea.

The first thing to appreciate is that the meaning of the term “secession,” as it is understood today, is no older than the late 19th century, and was forged in America. If I should stop someone on the street and ask whether he thinks secession is ever justified, the person might not have a ready answer, but he would know what I was asking. He would have an image of a people withdrawing from one political jurisdiction in order to form one of their own. For us the term “secession” has uniquely political connotations. But it was not always so.

The term derives from the Latin secedere, meaning merely an act of withdrawal, which is what “secession” meant until the 19th century. One could speak of the soul seceding from the body, or of seceding to the drawing room, or of seceding from the town to the country. To ask someone in 1760 whether he thinks secession is ever justified would be to draw a blank look. It would be like asking whether withdrawal is ever justified. When did “secession” cease to be a neutral term of withdrawal and become the name of a substantial political act?

Intimations of a change occurred in 1733 when the Scottish Church split. Those who left called themselves “seceders,” and their church the “Secession Church.” This church lasted nearly a century before splitting, but was soon reunited in 1829 under the paradoxical name of the “United Secession Church.” Here the term “secession” means not simply withdrawal but a religious-political act whereby a people dismember a religious jurisdiction to form one of their own. It also means the celebration and remembrance of that act by naming the new way of life the “Secession Church.” For the first time the term acquires substantial moral connotations. To be a seceder is a good thing. Though not strictly political, this religious-political connotation was familiar to an American Protestant culture for over a century, before it began to take on political connotations. The Oxford English Dictionary locates the first political use of the term in a statement by Thomas Jefferson in 1825 that colonies had seceded from the British Union. But there were earlier uses. Indeed, throughout the entire antebellum period, and in every section of the federation, prominent American leaders considered withdrawal of their state or states from the federation as a policy option. The section that most often considered withdrawing was New England: in 1803 over the Louisiana Purchase, in 1808 over the embargo of British trade, in 1814 over the war with Britain, in 1843 over the annexation of Texas, and in 1847 over the Mexican War. No sooner was the Constitution ratified by the states than debate began about the viability of the federation and the legal and moral conditions a state would have to satisfy to withdraw from the federation. For seventy years this discourse was hammered out and given considerable theoretical refinement. The result was the transformation of the term “secession” to refer to a substantial political act about which one could be for or against.

This discourse about secession was uniquely American. From the mid-17th century on, European political speech had been mainly the language of centralization and unification; of building larger and larger centralized states, and even empires. This disposition to centralize did not diminish with the overthrow of monarchy, but increased dramatically with the emergence of mass democracy. The French Revolution sought to establish individual liberty through a massive centralization of power which ruled out competing jurisdictions. The American Revolution, by contrast, sought to promote individual liberty through a polycentric order of competing jurisdictions where secession was a policy option of last resort. Prior to the Civil War, “secession” in America described a political act, conceived of in a morally neutral way: secession might be a good or bad thing depending on the circumstances. After the war, it would acquire exclusively negative connotations. How are we to understand this change?

Although it is morally flattering to think the war was fought to emancipate slaves, the reason actually given by Lincoln and political and military leaders was that secession had to be defeated in order to preserve the central government’s authority, which increasingly became identified with a new thing called the “nation.” Previously the central government had been viewed as a service agency of the federation, whose main tasks were to treat with foreign countries, establish free trade among the states, and provide for their defense. The United States were regularly referred to in the plural. After the war the United States would be referred to in the singular.

Lincoln explained his reasons for invasion in a letter to Horace Greeley on August 22, 1862: “My paramount object in this struggle is to save the Union, and is not either to save or to destroy slavery.” General Grant (a slave holder who refused to free his slaves after the war until forced to do so by the 13th Amendment) had said that if the war was about emancipation, he would take his sword to the other side. But why was it so important to establish a territorial monopoly on coercion in Washington? Was not the continent large enough for two federations, or even more? Lincoln’s answer was given in his First Inaugural: “Plainly, the central idea of secession, is the essence of anarchy.” Why? Because, he said, if a part of the Union is allowed to secede, that part itself can be divided, and a part of that part, and so on which would mean the unraveling of government as such.

In his speeches, Lincoln presented the war as a world historic struggle between the forces of republican government and the forces of anarchy. Most northern leaders who supported the war concurred. But many Northerners opposed the war. The Founding Jeffersonian tradition was still alive, and at least a third of the North was against the war, and another third was indifferent. To give just one example: Horace Greeley, editor of the Republican New York Tribune, declared on February 23, 1861, after a Confederacy of seven states had been formed: “We have repeatedly said…that the great principle embodied by Jefferson in the Declaration of Independence, that governments derive their powers from the consent of the governed, is sound and just; and that if…the cotton States, or the gulf States only, choose to form an independent nation, they have a clear moral right to do so. Whenever it shall be clear that the great body of Southern people have become conclusively alienated from the Union, and anxious to escape from it, we will do our best to forward their views.”

The war to suppress secession was largely the work of Lincoln and the Republican Party (the founding party of state capitalism), which is why unconstitutional measures were necessary, such as destroying and arresting the editors of some 300 opposition newspapers and suspending the writ of habeas corpus for the duration of the war in the North, which netted around 20,000 political prisoners. Lincoln even wrote an order for the arrest of the Chief Justice of the Supreme Court, who had ruled against suspending the writ of habeas corpus. Mussolini, in his most vigorous years, in a larger country, and with a more efficient police system, rounded up only 12,000 political prisoners.

Although Lincoln’s argument that secession means anarchy is incompatible with the American Founding, it fitted nicely with European thinking and practice, which for over two centuries had been building centralized states with territorial monopolies on coercion. The American polycentric order which allowed competing jurisdictions among sovereignties was viewed as antiquated and even as medieval. Nothing short of a violent revolution would be needed. With the triumph of the “Indivisible Union,” it appeared to many Europeans that America had finally become a modern state. The editor of London’s Spectator wrote triumphantly on December 22, 1866, that “The American Revolution marches fast towards its goal—the change of a Federal Commonwealth into a Democratic Republic, one and indivisible.”

The Civil War was the bloodiest war of the 19th century. Europeans were shocked, and the lesson many drew from it was that secession necessarily leads to war and must be prevented at all cost. This threat was especially real in 19th-century Europe, where monarchies were being challenged in favor of republicanism and nationalism, and where everyone was talking about self-government and liberty. James Bryce, in his magisterial The American Commonwealth (1888), argued that secession caused the Civil War. Secession was possible because Americans had a defective constitution that did not centralize political authority. The argument of Lincoln, Bryce, and European elites (though there were notable European exceptions, including Goethe, Proudhon, and Lord Acton) that political power must be centralized, and competing jurisdictions eliminated, was uppermost in the minds of the founders of the Australian Constitution (1900) and the Canadian constitution, called The British North America Act (1867). Both constitutions go out of their way to make clear that the federal units of the respective regimes are artificial creatures of the central authority and devoid of sovereignty. In this way they hoped to prevent an American-type war to suppress secession in Australia or Canada.

To sum up. By the mid-nineteenth century, Americans, in debates over the meaning of the states’ moral and legal relation to the Union, had transformed the meaning of the term “secession” from any act of withdrawal to a substantial political act. In the meantime, the modern European state, which was being imported around the world, was becoming more insistent on the need to suppress competing jurisdictions and make explicit its territorial monopoly on coercion. The American Civil War (caused, it was thought, by secession) was a wakeup call to this increasingly global European state system. And so it was that the political meaning given to “secession” by Americans in the antebellum period became the global meaning. And given the ubiquity of the unitary state system, this meaning was necessarily a negative one. Until the late 20th century, centralization and unification—however violently pursued—were generally thought to be good things; secession and division—however peacefully pursued—bad things.

But after a century of global wars of unprecedented destruction and intensity, along with totalitarian revolutions in which modern states killed more of their own people than were killed in both world wars, the mystique of centralization no longer has the authority it had in the early 19th century. After the peaceful secession of fifteen Soviet republics and other successful secessions, the term “secession” is beginning to acquire the morally neutral meanings it had in American prior to the Civil War. But this means that the modern unitary state, which has dominated political thought and existence for three and a half centuries, is beginning to lose its legitimacy.

The classical theory of the modern state is to be found in Thomas Hobbes’ Leviathan (1651). Hobbes argued that the innate tendency of mankind is centrifugal and violent. Without an artificial corporation having a monopoly on coercion in a territory, there can be no long-term peace and stability. Secession, in this theory, is logically ruled out, and it is easy to see why. The secession of a group within the state could be justified only as the aggregate right of the individuals making up the group. But if that aggregate could secede, so could any other, down to one individual, and that would contradict the very idea of the state.

Most modern theorists follow Hobbes in thinking of political society as artificial and held together by coercion. The classical statement of the counter tradition is that of Aristotle, who taught that political society is natural and occurs spontaneously, as does the family, society, and natural languages. Neither of these requires an all-powerful artificial corporation to maintain its existence. The enforcement mechanisms are internal to the practices themselves. Just what the bonds are that hold a political society together must be a topic for another day, but that such bonds exist should be obvious from the following examples, which refute Lincoln’s claim—itself a Hobbesian theorem—that “secession is the essence of anarchy.”

When the American colonies seceded from Britain they did not disintegrate into the endless secessions Lincoln feared. Kentucky would later secede from Virginia, Tennessee from North Carolina, Maine from Massachusetts, without further fragmentation. Norway seceded from Sweden (1905); Belgium from Holland (1830); Singapore from the Malaysian Federation (1965); and the vast Soviet Union peacefully dissolved in 1990. In none of these cases did Lincolnian or Hobbesian anarchy occur in the seceding units.

The Hobbesian picture is also static. Once a regime is established it remains indivisible. But on the Aristotelian view, political societies naturally emerge in the world. Consequently, over time, a new political society might emerge within a larger one, demanding recognition, and even the right to secede. What are the criteria for recognizing when these conditions have been satisfied? I am afraid there is little philosophers can say about this; anymore than they can provide criteria to know when two people should marry or when two people should divorce. All such judgments require what Aristotle called practical wisdom and a connoisseur’s understanding of the people involved and the circumstances. But at least we can rule out the Hobbesian doctrine that secession should never occur, in favor of the Aristotelian doctrine that it is a contingent good to be determined by an act of practical wisdom. And perhaps we can go further and say that if a new political society has emerged that wishes to govern itself and is capable of doing so, and if secession imposes no serious injustice on the remaining polity, then the presumption must be on behalf of secession.

The case for secession is even more compelling in a federal system such as the United States, Canada, or the European Union, where the federative units are already recognized as political societies, with a functioning legislature, executive, judiciary, and other institutions needed to be an independent state.

The Hobbesian modern state is ubiquitous, and in its three-century-long career has transformed the meanings of political words, hiding from view or delegitimating other political possibilities. Nowhere is this clearer than in its perverse understanding of secession. The Hobbesian state demands a territorial monopoly on coercion in order to eliminate revolution and civil war within the border of the state. It defines secession as revolution or civil war, but this is fundamentally wrong. Revolution in modern political discourse has two meanings. One derives from John Locke; the other from the French Revolution, which I shall call Jacobin revolution. The purpose of Lockean revolution is to overthrow a government that has violated its fiduciary trust and perhaps to alter the structure of government. Jacobin revolution is much more than that. It is an attempt to reconstruct the entire social and political order. Both forms of revolution are acts that occur within a modern unitary state. And the same is true of civil war. The paradigm of civil war is the English Civil War in the 17th century, which was a battle between two factions seeking control of the central government. But secession is neither revolution nor civil war.

Secession is not Lockean revolution. It does not seek to overthrow or alter the government of a modern state, but seeks merely to limit its jurisdiction over the seceding territory. Nor is secession Jacobin revolution. It is not an attempt to entirely transform the social and political order of a modern state. Seceders typically have no interest in changing the social and political order of the region from which they wish to withdraw. Nor is secession civil war. The seceding part of a polity is not engaged in a battle with the remaining part to control the central government of a modern state; it seeks merely to free itself from the jurisdiction of that government.

From these considerations it follows that there was no American Revolution, but a war of secession. And there was no American Civil War, but a war to suppress secession. Failure to make these distinctions means that “secession” is governed by the logic of the Hobbesian modern state and always appears as either revolution or civil war and, consequently, as a form of violence to be legitimately suppressed. By calling secession revolution and the battle against it a civil war, the public (already conditioned to think in Hobbesian categories) will fail to see that the arguments that could justify suppressing revolution, in either Lockean or Jacobin form, do not and cannot apply to the quite different act of secession. Lincoln’s justification for invading the Southern States was based on just this confusion of secession with revolution, which has ever since been an essential part of American historiography and even of American identity. Merely to recognize 1776 and 1861 as acts of secession rather than revolution or civil war would effect a revolution in the writing of American history and in American political self-understanding. Both of these landmark events are hostages of Hobbesian categories.

But the Hobbesian state no longer has the legitimacy it once had. The claim that the state is indivisible is not a truth about the nature of political order as such, but an artifact of the 17th century, like farthingales, stockings, and the indestructible atom. The American Union never was and is not now indivisible. I mentioned the great constitutional efforts in the 19th century to prohibit secession by the Australian and Canadian Founders. Yet in 1931 Western Australia voted to secede. Quebec came close to voting for secession in 1995, and the Supreme Court of Canada recently ruled that a Canadian province has a right to secede.

Canada and the United States illustrate the impotence of the Hobbesian doctrine of indivisibility as well as the hubris of constitution-making. Canada began as a Hobbesian state which ruled out secession, but has evolved into a polity where the secession of a province is an acknowledged policy option. The United States began as a federation of sovereign states with the central government being little more than a service agency for the states, and where secession was entertained in every section as a policy option. Astonishingly, it has since evolved into a Hobbesian state said to be one and indivisible.

Secession is a dialectical concept that cannot be understood without its opposite—the modern unitary state. The modern state cannot tolerate competing jurisdictions and demands a territorial monopoly on coercion; consequently, it absolutely rules out secession. As long as allegiance to the modern state was strong and people were confident of its worth (not only as an instrument but as an ideal), secession was a thoroughly negative concept. As the Hobbesian state and its ideology flourishes, so secession recedes in legitimacy. But as the state recedes in legitimacy, so secession flourishes. Since the end of the Cold War, we have entered a new period in which secession has again acquired the morally neutral connotations it had in its primordial appearance in antebellum America. That public corporation known as the United States has simply grown too large for the purposes of self-government, in the same way that a committee of 300 people would be too large for the purposes of a committee. There needs to be a public debate on the out-of-scale character of the regime and what can be done about it. This is the historic and noble task of the Second Vermont Republic. The long suppressed American idea of secession, as a public policy option, is returning to the United States as it came to the Soviet Union, Canada, Yugoslavia, Czechoslovakia, and other monsters created by a more than three-century-old policy of crushing hundreds of smaller polities into larger and larger monopolies of coercion.

“How Murray Rothbard became an Anarchist” (not a voluntaryist)


by Murray Rothbard

[Editor’s Note: The following transcription was taken from this youtube video:

The transcription runs from 26:42 to 51:08, and was taken from a speech he delivered at the Libertarian Party Convention in Denver in 1981.]

 

I became an anarchist and I can remember exactly what happened. It was pure logic that did it. I used to argue with my very close friends who were very intelligent liberals. We had sessions, sitting around, arguing, constantly. We had a similar session at my house talking till two or three in the morning. That’s usual for me because I’m a night person. Three in the morning is just about average for breaking up an evening.

I said to myself “I think something important happened tonight, what the hell was it?” because it wasn’t just like the usual argument. I thought the thing over and I realized what it was because one of them said, at one point, because I was in favor of laissez faire, a pure minarchist at that point, and they were just regular liberals, he asked “Look, why do you favor government supplied police force and courts? What’s your justification for that?”

I said something like “Well, the people get together and they decide that they can have this monopoly court system, and monopoly police.”

They said, very intelligently, “Well if the people can get together and say that, why can’t they get together and set up a steel plant and a dam and all the rest of it, all sorts of other government industries?”

I thought to myself, “By God, they’re right!” I came to the conclusion that laissez faire was inconsistent.

Either you had to go over to anarchism and scrap government altogether, or else you had to become a liberal, and of course that was out of the question for me to become a liberal. That was it. That was my conversion.

Then I started reading up on the stuff, anarchist writings and libertarian writings etc. etc., to broaden my perspective.

It was a tremendous winter for me, a double barreled conversion, first to Austrian Economics and second to anarchism. Also in Columbia graduate school, of course I used to have arguments with these people all the time. At one point an interesting thing happened which stunned my liberal associates. They said, look, here you are, an extreme right-winger, crazy anarchist. We’re going to meet you up with Whitey. Whitey was the communist party leader on the campus. He was a sort of thuggish type, liked sweaters; about six foot eight. At that stratosphere, who knows what the height is? A menacing looking figure in general. They set up a meeting in the street, on Broadway.

They figured they could get out fast. And they introduced me formally. It was kind of sweet. Here’s Whitey who’s the outstanding Marxist-Leninist on campus, and here’s Murray Rothbard who’s attacking Senator Taft for having sold out to the socialist. They figured that would be it, we’d pummel each other to death and they’d get rid of two extremists.

Oddly enough, was happened was that Whitey said “Oh, an anarchist, that’s great!”

We shook hands and had a very friendly discussion in which Whitey tried to prove to me that the way to achieve the withering away of the state is by maximizing state power. I thought that was little kooky.

My liberal friends were totally confused, asking “Why didn’t these guys hit each other over the head with clubs?” It was an interesting ideological experience.

And here’s another interesting political point is that the Libertarian Party didn’t yet exist so I wasn’t yet politically pure.

In the 1948 campaign, I supported Thurmond for president, a states’ rights candidate. There was a little club on Columbia University campus called “Students for Thurmond.” It was a very small club as you might expect. This was during the height of political activism. Most of the people on campus were Henry Wallace supporters.

Others were Truman supporters. There were two or three Dewey supporters. And here I was, a Thurmond supporter. The Thurmond members had one meeting. At the meeting there were four or five, and about 12 or 13 hostile observers trying to find out what kind of evil racism was being promoted here. Most of the people who got up to talk were Southern states’ rights types who didn’t have much to say.

I got up here as a New York Jewish guy with a passionate plea against centralized government and for decentralization.

Anyway, the students for Thurmond club did not flourish. That was my one experience with it.

At any rate, we had six or seven people, in this little circle of Bastiat. We got along very well. Thank goodness they were very happy times. We were a small number, but pure in spirit. We were arguing about arcane matters and never about strategy.

I remember also this was the first time in my life I ever got red-baited, a big new experience for me. Those of you who think I’m a commie now, well, there’s nothing to it. I considered myself an extreme right-winger. This is the old right Republicans who are semi-libertarian, anti-military, anti-intervention, anti-conscription and in favor the free market. I consider myself to be an extreme version of this. I wrote an column for an obscure little magazine called Faith and Freedom, which nobody’s ever heard of, I’m sure, here. It was a very good libertarian magazine for its day, written for right wing protestant ministers. That was the market they were writing for. With the people writing it, there was sort of a culture clash. I wrote the Washington column, succeeding Chodorov, one of my proud moments, when he left even though I’d never been to Washington at that point. I wrote under a pseudonym, Aubrey Herbert, for various obscure and unimportant reasons. This was beginning of the Eisenhower administration. So I had a lot of fun attacking most of his statist plans of the Eisenhower administration, attacking the idea that we should spend every drop of American blood supporting Chiang Kai-shek. I was having a ball. The editor comes flying to the East, and six months before he said I’d been doing a great job as a great writer and all that. He comes and says “I have to fire you.” “Why do you have to fire me?” He said our constituents were calling me a communist. These were right-wing protestant ministers, so I was kind of stunned. It was the first time I was red-baited, but now I’m used to it, so it was a kind of culture shock. So I said that I’d spent all this time attacking the government so how could I be a communist because communists favor all-out government ownership of everything? But logic was lost on the editor because he was just interested in his constituents. Fortunately or unfortunately, divine retribution struck and the magazine folded about three months later.

That brings me up to the middle or late 1950s. Before that, the 5 or 6 or 8 of us who were libertarians considered ourselves extreme right wingers in this spectrum/context. Then what happened was the right wing was taken over and changed dramatically by the National Review in 1955. There was a power vacuum because the old leaders had died off, like Taft and Colonel McCormick. It was easy for the National Review to take over and change the whole picture into what the right wing is now. The right wing in those days was not theocratic; it was not pro-war or pro-conscription. Anyway, the face of the whole right wing was changed at which point those of us who considered ourselves extreme right wingers had to leave. We started leaving the right-wing movement. It was a painful break as these things usually are.

I wrote quite a few economic articles and book reviews for National Review in the first few years. I was pretty appalled by what in those days was the “new right” and split with them about 1959. My best friend there was Frank Myers, a very interesting character. He was the book review editor and a general theoretician for National Review, now dead. A very charming chap, who was extremely erudite, intellectually exciting, very libertarian. He hated the public school system, and even hated the private schools, as a result, he raised his kids himself which as you know is a heroic act as many of you realize. He was pretty good on most things, but he was all in favor of nuclear war. To give you a sort of feel for what National Review was in those days, and probably still is, but I haven’t any contact with them for a long time, Frank and his wife Elsie, also a very charming person, used to argue about what the foreign policy move should be. Frank was in favor of an immediate nuclear attack on the Soviet Union. Elsie wanted to give them twenty-four hours to resign before we’d attack. That was the matrix, the spectrum of opinion on the right wing, the new right. So we did not politically see eye to eye for a long time.

The other thing that struck me about the new right was the monarchistic aspect. I remember many sessions or cocktail parties where the big argument would be something like this:

Should the Bourbon monarchy be restored first or the Hapsburgs? So that’s not the sort of thing I can relate very well to. It’s even worse than agricultural metaphors.

After the small growth in the middle to late 40s, after finding the movement in the middle to late forties and having some intellectual companions in the fifties, by 1959 or 1960 we’re back in square one more or less, and most of the libertarians were beginning to swing in the pro-war direction.

One of my close friends, an original member of the Circle of Bastiat, Robert Shuckman who died a tragic death very early, was the first chairman of the Young Americans for Freedom.

I’ll give you an example of YAF’s spirit in those days, and maybe still is. It’s at the founding meeting in Connecticut of YAF. This was the beginning of the libertarian-conservative alliance, not me but the other people. They suggested the term “Young Americans for Freedom,” but the “trads” who were the majority, the traditionalists, said “No no, we can’t use the word ‘freedom’ because it’s a commie word.” To me that sort of symbolizes the right wing from then on: “‘Freedom’ is a commie word.” But Shuckman was able to prevail with some of the cooler heads, like Buckley, to get the thing started.

We had a situation. By the early sixties, I had to start battling on the foreign policy front both with libertarians as well as other people. When the Vietnam war started, and the draft, of course, that made the whole thing more intense. Leonard Liggio and I founded “Left and Right” which we published three times a year, I don’t know how to say it. Tri annual or whatever. We figured nobody was reading it. We had some subscribers, but unfortunately we were so ill-organized that we never cashed anybody’s check, so we had a heavy deficit. But we figured nobody was reading it. It turned out later after the magazine died a lot of people seemed to have been influenced by it. Writing is sort of like, putting a note in a bottle and putting it out on the ocean and hoping somebody reads it someday. It’ll be very surprising to find out a lot of people have read it.

With this position of being anti-war and anti-draft certainly on the war question, it split us totally from the right-wingers. They accused us of being commies for the second and not the last time. Then we arrive at the famous YAF split. We get to the point in ’69, I guess it was, all of a sudden libertarian types pop up at YAF. You’ll hear them [later, during a] discussion of this. I wasn’t really close to that because the YAF split happened in St. Louis, but I did contribute to it by running a four-page article in Libertarian Forum which I had just founded in ’69 to replace “Left and Right,” saying “Listen, YAF,” urging them all to split with this organization, once again blowing my cool but it seemed to have a certain amount of effect. At any rate, YAF was split, of course, the big issue being the draft. The conservatives, the trads at the YAF convention being horrified and appalled when one of our people, the libertarian caucus people in YAF, burned his draft card openly, at which point they tried to lynch him. Our people at St, Louis were shouting “laissez faire, laissez faire!” as the motto while they were burning the draft card and the opposition, the trads were shouting “lazy fairies,” which again shows the mentality of these people.

In the meantime, the Libertarian Forum had been founded, one because Left and Right was running too many deficits. And two, because we figured that with the Nixon administration coming to power, and this has certain parallels right now of course, many libertarians at the time thought Nixon was going to be the savior. He was going to bring liberty to America. I swear it’s true! Several friends of mine at this time had become Nixon advisers were claiming Nixon was a libertarian. In fact some of them said Nixon’s really an anarchist if you can believe that. They said “Nixon’s one of us, you’ll see. Right now, because he’s running for office, he has to pretend he’s left-wing and statist and all that, but you’ll see when he gets in office, he’ll take off the gloves and come out of the closet.” Of course we did see, to our deep regret.

As a matter of fact, I coined a little quip at that point.

Nixon was one of the pioneers in the idea of having special groups, like writers for Nixon, housewives for Nixon etc. etc. So I wrote a thing saying there should be a group called “Anarchists for Nixon.” At any rate, I got a quick disillusionment with that. We founded Libertarian Forum largely because my publisher close friend Joe Peden believed that we should have a voice pointing out Nixon’s not really a libertarian, goddammit. That’s really how we got started.

About the same time the YAF split was going on, we started supper clubs in New York, libertarian supper clubs. There is now a libertarian supper club which is very successful and peaceful. Our supper club was successful, but not very peaceful. This was during the Nixon repression period. We figured out that the meetings in my living room were getting a little too large. I have a pretty small living room. My living room was legendary, but it’s small. So we decided to have a supper club and hire a Chinese restaurant or something, something nice and cheap. And have a meeting and announce it with someone reading a paper or something, so we did that. We met at a Chinese restaurant, seedy, but very good, at Broadway and 103rd street. We thought we’d get about 30 people. We had about 80 people. This was the beginning of the big libertarian growth. Where did these eighty people come from? Who the hell are they? Some of them were police agents, at least one. We have to realize, these meetings were extremely innocuous. It was on a Saturday evening, and my friend Leonard Liggio gave a paper on the history of classical liberalism. The next morning, we had a contact. We had one student group at Fordham University – it was the one big student libertarian group, the one and only, maybe there was another one somewhere – they knew the head of New York State YAF at the time. It was a very friendly at Fordham campus. After Saturday night, on Sunday morning, the YAF guy would call up my friends at Fordham say “Here’s what happened last night: Leonard Liggio gave a paper. The following people attended it:” and he wheeled off a list of attendees. He got that from his police spies. He was friendly with the New York City police department. That was the sort of atmosphere. They didn’t do anything in particular at that point, but I guess we felt we were on the cutting edge of revolution.

Then we did something very daring, but, in retrospect, pretty crazy. We issued a call in Libertarian Forum: “Come one, come all,” on Columbus Day in 1969. “Everybody show up for this mammoth thing.” We expected 200 people but 400 showed up. “Who are these people?” We never saw them before, and usually didn’t see them later either. It was very strange, phantasmagoric. We held this thing at a notorious commie hotel in Times Square. We weren’t the affluent crowd we are now. This was the old days. It was called The Diplomat with a very cheap meeting room. We had these scholarly papers and stuff like that, but we found peculiar things happening. We were standing outside and all of sudden somebody would pop up with a flash bulb and a take our picture. Somebody would swagger up with an obvious shoulder holster bulge and a crew cut and say “You one of those anarchists in there?” We’d say “Anarchists? Who’s that? We never heard of that. We’re just standing here going to a restaurant.” That was the situation, where there was almost a police bust, but they didn’t quite get to it, but it was close to it.

We were a very strange and motley group. Don’t forget, we were used to eight people in a living room, or twenty people. Here we find a tremendous spectrum of libertarian variety. Imagine people running around with capes with dollar signs on them to people with weird looking black armbands constantly shouting “Kill! Loot!” Without a close meeting of the minds, it probably turned off more people and set back the movement by quite a few years I think. We had to learn through experience. It was an essential learning process.

That brings us to the late 60s. I guess I should talk about the first publicity of the movement. It was the fall of 1970. The campus revolt was taking place in ’69 and ’70, basically all the burnings of the cards and whatever. By the fall of seventy, the whole thing had died out very very fast.

The New York Times was looking around for something to write about. They went to the campus and couldn’t find any political activity. They went to Columbia University, the year or two before, the heartland of sit-ins and burnings and all that, and couldn’t find any political activity at all except one peculiar group called the Freedom Conspiracy. Who were these people? Never heard of them before. Freedom Conspiracy was the only active political group on campus in 1970. They were in favor of Jim Buckley for senate, a deviation which fortunately has now been corrected. They were a weird group because on one hand they were talking all this stuff about laissez faire and free market and also very counterculture type stuff. They had things with black flags and long hair and all the rest of it.

The New York Times felt it was a very interesting phenomenon and wrote a little article about it. And then, two or three months later the New York Times magazine section, an extremely influential on the media and opinion groups wrote a front page article in early 1971 with a picture of these guys, the two leaders standing there in the Rosetto with a black flag and “anarchy” written on the back. It was a long lead article about this strange new group called “Libertarians” in favor of John Locke and so on. This is the first time, I think, the modern libertarian movement got any kind of media publicity and it kicked things off because then there were op-ed pieces about it.

Then they asked me to write something about it and I got in an argument with Buckley as usual. From that, they asked me to write For a New Liberty and the whole thing began to snowball. Later that year, the Libertarian Party was founded. I think since you’re all familiar with the history of the party and you’ll hear much more about it from the founding members who were really here in person in Colorado, I’ll end my reminiscences and nostalgia at this point. I brought you from the antediluvian period of my birth all the way up to modern times. So, thank you very much!

Slavery and National ID: A Portent of Things to Come?


 

By Carl Watner

 

Jim Fussell, in a review of “group classification on National ID cards” observed that in the pre-Civil War United States “‘Free Passes’, Freedom papers, and Deeds of manumission” functioned as ID’s for the freed Negro. [1] This observation sparked my interest in the relationship between national ID and the history of slavery, and it is these two subjects which I would briefly like to comment upon in this paper.

The whole basis of chattel slavery, as it was known in the South, was the ownership of one person by another. Although some Negroes owned other blacks, for the most part slavery in the United States before the Civil War was largely along racial lines: white ownership of black people. All Negroes were presumed to be slaves, unless they could prove otherwise. The burden of proof was on the Negro. People with white skin never had to prove to anyone that they were free. In other words, the presumption was that if your skin was black, you were considered prima facie a slave, or else a runaway, or fugitive. The only way of proving that you were a free person was to show your deed of manumission (under which your owner had freed you), or some sort of certificate of freedom (often issued by the clerk of a county court) attesting to your free status.

Nearly all of the Southern states and several of the Northern states had laws which reflected this presumption. Slaves were not to leave their owner’s land unless they had permission. In Connecticut, “[a]ny slave found wandering about without a pass was to be arrested as a runaway. Pennsylvania forbade blacks to travel more than ten miles from home without a pass … . Philadelphia directed its constables to arrest Negroes found in the streets on Sunday unless they had a pass from their owners.”[2] Laws were often passed requiring all free blacks to register with local officials, in and some cases to post bond for their good behavior, and to ensure they would not become a charge upon the community. The District of Columbia had a particularly egregious ordinance passed on April 14, 1821 (effective June 1, 1821). It required all free blacks in the city to register annually with the Mayor and

to enter into bond with one good and responsible free white citizen, as surety, in the penalty of twenty dollars, conditioned for the good, sober, and orderly conduct of such person or persons of color, and his or her family, for the term of one year following the date of such bond, and that such person or persons, his or her family, nor any part thereof, shall not, during the said term of one year, become chargeable to the Corporation in any manner whatsoever, and that they will not become beggars in or about the streets. Only after the bond was posted would the mayor issue a license to permit such free blacks to reside in the city for one year. … [F]ree Negroes were not permitted to change their places of residence until after such changes had been entered on their licenses by the registrar.” [3] Similar regulations existed in such cities as Nashville, TN., Montgomery, AL., Baton Rogue, LA., Raleigh, NC., and Petersburg, VA. [4]

As I have pointed out in other articles for this anthology, the whole premise of National ID is that the government owns the citizen, and must provide the citizenry with identification, beginning with a state-issued birth certificate. In principle, this is just the same as it was during the time of American slavery. Every Negro was presumed a slave unless the government (or his master, actually ex-master) documented that he was a free person. If a freed Negro lost his “papers,” then he was automatically considered a slave. If a Negro wanted to assert his natural born freedom, including the right not to carry government papers, his existence could be quite perilous, just as it would be to an American today who refused to carry government papers proving his or her identity.

It is next to impossible to function in our statist economy without a birth certificate, a drivers license, or a social security number issued by the government. If a person should try to operate in such a manner, he or she will surely eventually be apprehended by the authorities for “failing to register one’s birth,” for “driving without a license,” or for “failing to provide a social security number.” If, and when, a national or state ID program is implemented in the United States, the situation will be worse, because then it will undoubtedly become a crime to “fail to register” and “fail to carry one’s state or federal ID card on one’s person at all times.”

Despite the danger to themselves, historians point out that many free Negroes refused to comply with the numerous municipal registration codes or the demand that they carry papers. “Many simply never bothered to register,” “probably few carried freedom papers,” and most instinctively preferred to avoid white officials. [5] “In 1853, St. Louis [MO.] authorities attempted to chase alien free Negroes out of the city and to force native free Negroes to register. Police raided well-known free Negro haunts, whipped unregistered freemen, and shipped them beyond city limits. … The raids continued for almost a year, although they ended in failure.” [6] Negroes in Virginia were no more compliant. “In Amelia County. Virginia, for example, a consecutively numbered register of free Negroes kept between 1800 and 1865 listed about 150 freemen. In 1860, however, almost 200 resided in the county and many more had been born, had been manumitted, and had migrated into and out of the area during those years.” [7]

Are the colored freemen of the 19th Century trying to tell us Americans of the 21st Century something that we might do? It is surely food for thought. [8]

Endnotes

[1] Jim Fussell, “Global Survey (Jo to Vi) of Group Classification on National ID Cards, at http://www.preventgenocide.org/prevent/removing-facilitating-factors/IDcards/survey/index2. See “USA (Pre-Civil War).

[2] Edgar J. McManus, Black Bondage In The North (Syracuse: Syracuse University Press), 1973, p. 73 and p. 74.

[3] Leonard P. Curry. The Free Black In Urban America (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press), 1981, p. 86 and p. 301 (footnote 17) citing Washington, City Council, Laws of The Corporation of the City of Washington [1821] (Washington: Way and Gideon) 1821, pp. 110-111. The complete law is found at Chapter 133 of Laws Passed by the Eighteenth Council of the City of Washington, Approved April 14, 1821, Sections 1 -21 (pp. 109-116). Secs. 11 and 12 (pp. 113-114) deal with change of residence regulations.

[4] Ira Berlin, Slaves Without Masters: The Free Negro in the Antebellum South (New York: Oxford University Press paperback) 1981, pp. 319.

[5] ibid., p. 327.

[6] ibid., p. 330.

[7] ibid., p. 328. By the time of the Civil War there was a large number of free Negroes in the United States. “There were 59,000 free Negroes in the United States at the time of the first decennial census in 1790. … By [1860] the number had climbed to 488,000, … .” Over 40% of them lived in the South. John Hope Franklin and Alfred A. Moss, Jr., Free Slavery to Freedom: A History of Negro Americans (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, Fortieth Anniversary Edition), 1988, p. 137.

[8] What might we ask are the supposed benefits of government identification and documentation? Among other things it appears that our income can be traced and taxed; our children can be tracked from birth and forced to attend public schools; and our ages and the ages of our children can be known so that all of us might be subject to the military draft in time of war.

Why I Oppose Government Enumeration


By Carl Watner

[Editor’s Note: This essay originally appeared as Chapter 17 in NATIONAL IDENTIFICATION SYSTEMS, an anthology edited by Carl Watner with Wendy McElroy, published in 2004 by McFarland & Company, Jefferson, NC. ISBN 0-7864-1595-9.]

… as I was cold and wet I sat down at a good fire in the bar room to dry my great coat and saddlebags. … There presently came in, one after another, half a dozen … substantial yeomen of the neighborhood, who sitting down to the fire after lighting their pipes, began a lively conversation upon politics [circa 1773]. As I believed I was unknown to all of them, I sat in total silence to hear them. One said, “The people of Boston are distracted.” Another answered, “No wonder the people of Boston are distracted; oppression will make wise men mad.” A third said, “What would you say if a fellow should come to your house and tell you he was come to take a list of your cattle that Parliament might tax them for you for so much a head? And how should you feel if he should go out and break open your barn, to take down your oxen, cows, horses, and sheep?” “What should I say,” replied the first, “I would knock him in the head.” “Well,” said a fourth, “if Parliament can take away Mr. Hancock’s wharf and Mr. Row’s wharf, they can take away your barn and my house.” After much more reasoning in this style, a fifth who had as yet been silent, broke out, “Well it is high time for us to rebel. We must rebel some time or other: and We had better rebel now than at any time to come: if we put it off for ten or twenty years, and let them go on as they have begun, they will get a strong party among us, and plague us a great deal more than they can now. As yet they have but a small party on their side.”
– John Adams, “Old Family Letters,” p. 140 cited in David McCullough, JOHN ADAMS (New York: Simon & Schuster), 2001, pp. 74-75.

The purpose of this essay is to question the assumption that we need a government program that produces national ID (and by implication observe that resistance should be based on principle not pragmatism). From the Bible story of King David (who caused a plague by counting his people), to the Roman censors who counted Joseph, Mary and Jesus in Bethlehem, to Parliament’s attempt to list colonial cattle, to today’s call for national identification cards the essential purpose behind government data gathering has always been the same: to enhance government’s control over its subject population. The only difference between “breaking down barn doors” to count your animals, or forcibly implanting their offspring or our newborn children with a subdermal micro-chip is the advance of technology. Government identification programs, whether they are based upon a birth certificate, a wallet card (like the Social Security card), a smart card (with a programmable microchip), an implanted micro-chip, or some other form of biometric recognition are all based upon the same principle: that the government has the right and necessity to track, monitor, and control the people and property within its geographic boundaries.(1) As one commentator has pointed out, “there is no difference in principle between being forced to carry a microchip in a plastic card in your wallet or in a little pellet in your arm.”(2) The question is not whether one technology is better or worse than another; the question is whether we endorse the argument that some sort of government enumeration is necessary.

Whether what we call “national ID” would be administered at the state or federal level, each and every person in the United States would be issued a government identification, and would be required to use it in order to participate in numerous activities. A true national identification card would necessarily be universal (if not issued to every newborn it would be issued to children upon reaching a certain age) and compulsory (it would become a crime, punishable by fine or imprisonment, to refuse to accept or use such a document). It would also be a violation of the law to have more than one card, to use the card of another person, or to hold a card in the name of an alias. In short, a national ID would act as a domestic passport. In many countries around the world, where such cards actually exist, they are needed to rent an apartment, to buy a house, apply for a job, pay one’s utility and telephone bills, withdraw books from the library, or to access health care services. They could act as a surrogate drivers license, passport, voter registration card, and hunting/fishing license.(3) With micro-chip technology, such a card would act as a complete medical, financial, tax, and travel dossier, documenting where you have been, how you got there, and how you paid for the services you purchased. In conjunction with other income data reported to the Internal Revenue Service, it could be used to generate an income tax return for you every year. The chips could be linked “directly to all government agencies so the card could be used to verifv that the holder has no delinquencies on taxes or child support,” no overdue library books, no parking fines, no bounced checks, and no unpaid traffic violations. They would also “have the capability to be disabled from a central location at the discretion of any government agency, instantly rendering its holder unable to travel or function in society.”(4) In short, government identification would he a “license to live,” based on the idea that “living is a government privilege, not a right.”(5) It would be an attack on every person’s right to exist upon the surface of the earth without being seized by the authorities for violating the laws governing personal identification.

Most readers picking this book up for the first time would want to know if I am opposed to all government enumeration. “Don’t censuses and other government surveys, etc., serve many useful social purposes? Aren’t the various forms of government data gathering simply like other tools and technologies that are capable of doing both good and harm?” the reader might ask. Nonetheless, “Yes,” I am really opposed to all forms of government enumeration. My objection to government enumeration and data gathering is not to the collection and registration of information per se, but rather to the coercive nature of the institution that gathers it. If some private organization chooses to solicit information from me, I may or may not respond. However, I will suffer no criminal penalties if I refuse to cooperate. When the State demands we conform to its identification procedures or collects information about us and our affairs, there are usually fines, penalties, or imprisonment for those who do not cooperate.

There is a definite ethical question involved in justifying government data gathering. Is it morally proper to coerce those who refuse to participate in enumeration programs or provide information demanded by the government? Do the ends justify the means? I don’t necessarily object to the ends (such as improved public health or security) but I do object to the means, and question whether improper means can bring about beneficial ends for everybody.(6) In many countries if one steadfastly refuses to cooperate (e.g., in refusing to register the birth of one’s children with the government, or in refusing to carry a government ID card), one will be arrested; and if one resists arrest, one will be ultimately dragged off to jail. Or if one acts in self-defense to protect one’s self from arrest one will be killed for resisting an officer of the law. By using violence or the threat of violence against the non-cooperator, governments are ultimately violating the moral commandment not to kill or molest peaceful people.

Many times throughout history, government collection of seemingly innocent data (such as tribal or ethnic or racial affiliation) has resulted in horrible and deplorable genocide. The uses (and the abuses which are ultimately inherent in government administration) of government information in identifying and locating the civilian victims of the Nazis during World War II, or of the blacks in South Africa, or of the Tutsis in Rwanda, would, by themselves, be reason enough to question and then demand the cessation of government enumeration. The numbering and internment in the United States of over 100,000 American citizens of Japanese descent during World War II should be sufficient to prove my point. But even if it could be proven that government data collection benefits society in other ways (thus using the ends to justify the means), I would still be opposed because government necessarily has to act coercively in the manner in which it collects such information. I believe this to be wrong from an ethical perspective, and believe it sets the stage for the sorts of human right abuses that we have experienced under every species of government, whether democratic or totalitarian. As Robert Nisbet once noted, “With all respect to differences among types of government, there is not, in strict theory, any difference between the powers available to the democratic and to the totalitarian State.”(8)

The best example of a voluntary ID system that I can offer is that presented by the credit card companies, such as Visa, MasterCard, Discover, and American Express. These companies have managed “to make their cards acceptable in all civilized countries.”(9) Although they each might like to attain a coercive monopoly over the credit card market, unlike national governments, none of these organizations has the right to compel people to use their credit cards. Compare credit cards to national identification cards: no one is forced to have a credit card; some people may have more than one credit card from the same company, or even have multiple credit cards from different companies. Most people pay their bills because they want to maintain their credit rating and want to take advantage of the benefits and conveniences derived from using credit cards. But no one is put in jail: neither those who do not use credit cards, nor those merchants who refuse to accept credit cards in their businesses. In short, the absence of coercion and the existence of a “variety of legal choices does not mean chaos.” As the ruminations at the end of my essay on the history of the state birth certificate, and the discussion in Sunni Maravillosa’s essay, “ID Without Big Brother,” both point out, there are many noninvasive methods which might be used to identify people in the absence of a government monopoly.

No one can really know for sure whether the September 11th terrorist attacks would have been prevented by the existence of a national ID card, or if ways could have been found to circumvent the system. Beside the moral question, there are all sorts of pragmatic problems associated with the issuance of a national ID card. Fake identity documents are to be found in every country of the world.(10) If cards were issued to some 280 million Americans in the course of a year, that means that more than a million cards would have to be issued every work day, or at least 125,000 per hour. And more importantly, what sort of document will a citizen have to show to secure such a card? There is still no fool-proof system in existence in the United States affirming legitimate birth certificates or other proofs of identity. If you question this, then how did some 3000 dead people vote in one Florida county in the 2000 Presidential election, or why do statistics show there are many millions more drivers licenses issued nation-wide than there are adults who drive? The point is there are extreme problems with the integrity of data in existing systems, so how will a new system function effectively?(11) Certainly, national ID programs in such countries as Spain, France, and Italy have not stopped terrorists, and even if it could somehow be proved that a national ID program w6uld have prevented the September 11th hijackings, the point is that natioral ID is not really an issue about technology or its practical implementation.(12)

The decision whether or not to adopt national I.D. is really a moral and philosophical issue that we have to face: do our rights emanate from the State or do individual rights inhere in the individual? Is everyone “endowed by their Creator with certain inalienable rights,” as the Declaration of Independence puts it, or do we need to be registered and identified by government in order to be assured that we receive whatever privileges and benefits it (the government) grants us? While there certainly are dangers living in a free world, the principle behind national ID leads straight to a totalitarian society. With national I.D. there is no logical stopping point short of totalitarian control. Do we want to embrace that prospect? As “Harvey Silverglate, a criminal defense lawyer in Boston who specializes in civil liberties issues,” put it

Individuals, groups, gangs— the damage that they have done pales in significance when compared to the damage done by governments out of control. There is no example of a privately caused Holocaust in history…. I would prefer to live in a world where governments are more circumscribed than in a world that gives governments enormous, unlimited powers [such as a national I.D. program] to keep private terrorism circumscribed. I would rather live with a certain amount of private terrorism than with government totalitarianism.(13)

The evidence in this book lends credence to the conclusion that national ID cards are a “trademark of totalitarianism” and that no totalitarian government operates without such a system.(14)

Notes

1. My references to “national ID cards,” government enumeration, government identification, and government data gathering are all-inclusive. They refer to both “card-type” and “card-less” governmental systems, past, present, or future which track, identify, and monitor people within the space boundaries which governments monopolize. It is even possible that we might have a card-less system given the advance of biometrics technology. Using biometric features, such as iris-scan, voice recognition, and/or fingerprints each person’s features could be fed into a database and identification verified by scanners (thus obviating the need for each person to carry around their own I.D. card). Another card-less possibility would make use of the ability of surveilance cameras to match faces of people with centrally-stored digital images.
2. Peter Lalonde and Paul Lalonde, Racing Toward the Mark of the Beast (Eugene: Harvest House Publishers, 1994), p. 18, quoting Martin Anderson from The Washington Times, October 13, 1993.
3. Ching-Yi Liu, “How Smart Is the IC Card?: The Proposed National Smart Card …,” paragraph 6. ID cards are already used for these purposes in Taiwan and Singapore.
4. This point was made in a forwarded e-mail message of March 9, 2002 from John Utley [jbutley@earthlink.net].
5. See Robert Ellis Smith’s monograph, “A National ID Card: A License to Live,” Providence: Privacy Journal, 2002, p. 44., footnote 1. Fred Woodworth of The Match in Tucson, also developed this theme in personal correspondence (December 28, 2001) with the author. Also see Duncan Frissell, “What’s Our National Identity?” The Sierra Times, December 6, 2001.
6. See Murray N. Rothbard, “Toward a Reconstruction of Utility and Welfare Economics,” in Mary Sennholz, editor, On Freedom and Free Enterprise (New York: D. Van Nostrand Company, 1956), pp. 224-262. See the discussion of the unanimity principle and “The Role of the State,” pp. 244-253 (about 1/5 the way down).
7. On the numbering of Japanese-Americans see Mine Okilbo, Citizen 13660 (Seattle: University of Washington Press, 1946). Ms. Okuho’s family number and internment number was 13660. In the second printing (1989) of the reprint edition of 1983, see her drawings and commentary on pages 19 and 22. In Maisie and Richard Conrat, Executive Order 9066: The Internment of 110,000 Japanese Americans (Los Angeles: California Hstorical Society, 1972), see the photos of numbering tags on the frontispiece and page 50. In Lawson Fusao Inada (editor), Only What They Could Carry: The Japanese American Internment Experience (Berkeley: Heyday Books, 2000) see the photo of Hiro Niwa’s evacuation tag # 13664, at p. 57.
8. Robert. Nisbet, “The State” in D. J. Enright, editor, Fair of Speech (Oxford: Oxford University Press; 1985), pp. 185-202 at p. 186.
9. See Edward Stringham, “Market Chosen Law,” 14 Journal of Libertarian Studies (Winter 1998-1999), pp. 53-77 at pp. 62-63.
10. See the interesting article by Kitty Oviedo, “Only We Can Make Ourselves Safe: Personal Protection, Not Government Protection,” The Voluntaryist whole number 117 (pdf) (2nd Quarter 2003), p. 8, in which this observation is made.
11. “Technology Problems with the National ID Card” were raised by Jason Kosorec of Eaglecheck, Ltd., Cleveland, 0H, in personal e-mail of February 18, 2002.
12. See Julia Scheeres, “ID Cards Are De Rigueur Worldwide,”, paragraph 14.
13. Josh Gewolb, Assistant to Harvey Silverglate, approved use of this quote in an e-mail of April 10, 2002, to the author. The original version of this quote appears in Simson Garfinkel, Database Nation (Sebastopol: O’Reilly & Associates, 2000), at p. 239.
14. For the expression “trademark of totalitarianism,” see Congressman Ron Paul, “Statement for the Government Reform Committee Hearing on National ID Card Proposals,” November 16, 2001. For the assertion that “no totalitarian government operates without such a system” of ID see the 1980 reference to Analise Anderson, by Annie I. Anton, “National Identification Cards,” PUBP 8100s— Information Policy, December. 17, 1990, originally available at http://www.cc.gatech.edu/computing/SW_Eng/people/Phd/id.html, next to last paragraph of Sec. IV, Summary.

A Monopoly on the Means of Identification: The Evolution of the Compulsory State Birth and Death Certificate


 

by Carl Watner
Number 118

 

Introduction

When the Constitution of the United States was finally adopted by the thirteen states of the Articles of Confederation, the new federal government had no power to collect direct personal income taxes from each citizen or to record their births and deaths except once every ten years (in conjunction with the decennial census which was required to determine the apportionment of congressmen in the House of Representatives). “There was not the remotest idea in the minds of the framers of the Constitution as to the necessity of a complete record of vital statistics … .” [1] Even among the States at that time, there was little concern for the official, civil registration of births and deaths. As one commentator noted during the 1860s, it was probably impossible for a large portion of the American populace to prove that they were ever born, that “their parents were ever married, and that they have any legitimate right to the name they bear, … .” [2] Yet today, nearly every person has a state-issued birth certificate. The constitutional directive for the decennial census has been expanded to such an extent that serious consideration is now being given to assigning a federal identification number to each and every citizen and resident alien. How did we, in the United States, move from the point where very few of our ancestors were concerned about even having a record of their births (much less having a public official make that record) to the point where we are ready to accept a government number to identify us? The main purpose of this article is to answer that question by presenting an overview of the evolution of government-mandated birth and death certificates in the United States.

In the Beginning

When the colonists that settled at Jamestown, Virginia and Plymouth Rock, Massachusetts arrived in North America, there already existed a history of birth and death registration in the older European countries. For example, in 1538, Lord Thomas Cromwell had ordered that the English parishes be responsible for keeping registers to record baptisms and burials. Twenty-five years later, the Council of Trent made it a law of the Catholic Church that registers of births and marriages should be kept. [3] However, since the Puritans and Pilgrims took the view that marriage was a civil event, rather than a religious one, they held that the registration of births and deaths should be a government responsibility, rather than an ecclesiastical one. Therefore, in 1639 the General Court of the Massachusetts Bay Colony ordered that births and deaths should be reported to the town clerk by parents or household owners within one month of their occurrence. Thus Massachusetts holds the record for being

the first state in the Christian world which recorded births, deaths, and marriages by government officers; … the first state in the world which recorded the dates of the actual facts of births, deaths, and marriages rather than the subsequent ecclesiastical ceremonies of baptisms, burials, and weddings; and … the first state in the world which imposed on the citizen the duty of giving notice to the government of all births, [d]eaths, and marriages occurring in his family. [4]

The Connecticut colony followed suit in 1644, and the New Plymouth colony did likewise in 1646. John Locke, in his “Fundamental Constitutions” for the government of the Carolinas, which was prepared in 1669, made provision for a “Registry in every Signiory, Barony, and Colony, wherein shall be recorded all the births, marriages, and deaths that shall happen.” [5]

During the 18th Century, there was little concern on the part of American governments, either federal or state, for the recording of vital statistics. In 1785, James Madison proposed a law in the Virginia Assembly which would have created a system of statewide birth and death registration. It was defeated in the Virginia Senate. Similarly, on the federal level, under the North West Ordinance of 1787 there was no provision for the registration of births and deaths. Only marriages were required to be recorded within three months. New York City first recorded deaths officially in 1803, but it was not until 1847 that the city began recording births and marriages. Very few people, except the most wealthy, who were concerned with their legal inheritance, had any real interest in official public records. Until the last half of the 19th Century, the recording of births, deaths, and marriages was generally considered either a semi-religious or social function. Such events, if they were recorded at all, were more likely to either be entered in a family’s Bible, or a church register, than registered by a clerk in a government office.

It was largely the development of the public health movement and the advancements of medical science which propelled the demand for official vital statistics in the United States. Until the early 1900s, the American States might as well have been foreign nations, so far as measured by the uniformity of their health codes and registration of vital events. As one historian put it, “Only as European nations created efficient mechanisms in the course of the nineteenth century did the uncoordinated condition of American state registration begin to reveal the extent of its shortcomings.” [6] For example, the English Parliament had passed a registration law in 1836, which provided for the collection of vital statistics. The legislature of Massachusetts followed suit in 1842. However it was almost three decades later before any state in the Union had an official Board of Health (Massachusetts in 1869), and before the American Public Health Association was founded (1872). [7] The initial impetus for the improved collection of vital statistics usually came from public officials, doctors, public health officers, sanitary engineers, and statisticians who were concerned with enumerating the variety of sicknesses, infectious diseases, and epidemics prevalent within their state, and who began to scientifically study causes, containment, and control.

The States justified such activities under their police powers of providing for the public’s health, safety, welfare, the prevention and detection of crime, and the need to collect data for sanitary purposes and analysis. Lewis Hockheimer, in his 1897 article on “Police Power” in the Central Law Journal, noted that “The police power is the inherent plenary power of a State … to prescribe regulations to preserve and promote the public safety, health, and morals, and to prohibit all things hurtful to the comfort and welfare of society.” [8] The constitutional basis of such state power was found in the Tenth Amendment, which reserved to the states all powers not explicitly delegated or prohibited in the Constitution. Firefighting regulations, quarantine laws, laws governing weights and measures, inspection of flour, meal, beef and pork, control laws over strong liquors, and recordation of vital statistics: in short, “no aspect of human intercourse remained outside the purview of” the police power if it could be justified as beneficial to the happiness and welfare of the state’s citizenry. [9]

“Birth and Death Registration in Massachusetts”

Throughout the Nineteen Century, the State of Massachusetts remained a pioneer in recording the vital events of its citizens. However at the beginning of the 1800s, probably not more than 50% of the births and deaths in the state were actually registered according to the laws in force. Until at least the early 1840s, the main justification of the registration laws in Massachusetts was that “lists of births and deaths would be useful in cases of probate.” [10] In February 1842, when the state legislature appointed a committee to revise the law, increasing emphasis was placed upon the “importance of vital records in studying the public health, particularly in helping to chart the course of epidemic diseases through the State.” Numerous factors affected the collection of vital statistics during the middle decades of the century. For one thing it was estimated that less than 50% of births in the state were attended by a midwife or physician. Many parents were not aware that it was their responsibility to report births to the town clerks, and there was a “widespread reluctance to require physicians and midwives to report births.” State supervision of medical doctors had been “relaxed” from 1830 to 1850 (formal licensing was not resumed until 1894), and it was believed that involving “medical practitioners in the registration system again might require a state-sponsored program for distinguishing between competent and less expert physicians.” [11] So not only were the medical doctors fearful of involvement with the State, they resented being forced by law to report births and deaths, a service for which either they would not be paid, or receive very little compensation.

In 1849, the legislature again appointed a committee to close loop-holes in the vital statistics law. Lemuel Shattuck authored the report, which has been referred to as “the first treatise on the subject of vital registration” published in the United States. The committee demanded that town and city clerks both be “authorized and required” to collect birth and death information; that “all towns appoint superintendents of burial grounds and undertakers, who would have the exclusive right to handle interments;” and that amount of fees paid to those who had the duty to collect birth and death information be augmented. [12] Although much of the committee’s report was rejected by the legislature, the report served to bring publicity to the topic of public health and vital statistics. Nevertheless, there were still a number of ways that deaths went unrecorded. First of all, private farm burials had never been outlawed in Massachusetts, and they were especially prevalent in the rural counties. The legislature feared to prohibit such burials “for fear of offending the folk tradition that a farmer should be buried on the land he tilled.” Secondly, there were no state regulations regarding removal of bodies from one town to another. Thirdly, there was no requirement that coroners report violent deaths to the town clerks; and finally it remained very easy for sextons and cemetery superintendents to avoid the law. [13] By the early 1870s, the state legislature addressed these issues, including an order to all towns and cities to license undertakers (who were threatened with loss of their license if they failed to report deaths). Thus by the end of the 1870s, there was near 100% accuracy in the recording of deaths within the state.

However at the same time, problems remained in approaching such accuracy in the reporting of births. There were still parents and householders who remained unaware of their obligations, and “because parenthood was obviously not a government office, there were great obstacles in making parents comply with the law. … Perhaps they could have been prosecuted” but the widespread apathy with regard to birth statistics resulted from the fact that fertility was not regarded as a social problem at that time. [14] Nevertheless, with the advent of the State Board of Health in 1869, and the establishment of city and town boards of health during the 1880s and 1890s, and changes to the law in 1883 (which increased the fees paid to physicians and midwives who reported births), gradually more and more births were recorded. Additionally, town and city clerks often resorted to conducting municipal-wide censuses once a year as a means of recording births that either were not attended by a midwife or physician or births which they attended, but failed to report. [15] Thus by 1890, it was safe to say that the “the main features of an adequate system had been adopted and put into operation. No more than one or two per cent of the births and deaths which occurred in the State were not registered.” [16]

The Registration Area

With the State of Massachusetts as an example, the federal government tried to encourage other states and local governments to emulate its practices. In 1880, the Federal Bureau of the Census initiated a national registration area for the uniform collection of death statistics in order to provide a scientific basis for the study of public health problems in the states. The registration “area” was simply all or part of a State (such as a major city within the State) which complied with the federal guidelines for the collection of death statistics. In order to qualify for admission into the national registration area a State or municipality had to comply with two requirements. First it had to pass satisfactory a law and implement a suitable system for death registration, and secondly, it had to attain at least a 90% rate of completeness in recording deaths within its geographic boundaries. Wilson G. Smillie in his book on PUBLIC HEALTH ADMINISTRATION IN THE UNITED STATES discusses the evolution of modern registration:

Various checks [we]re used by the Federal Census Bureau to determine whether a given state ha[d] fulfilled all requirements. The national registration area began with Massachusetts and New Jersey, the District of Columbia, and nineteen cities. Gradually the various states were admitted by the Federal Census Bureau so that every state is now included in the National Registration Area for Deaths. The National Birth Registration Area was established in 1915. Criteria for admission were similar to those required for admission to the death registration area. All states have met the federal requirements, though a few states have difficulty in maintaining the national registration standards. This formation of national registration areas marks one of the progressive steps in public health administration in the United States. It was brought about through formulation of a model registration law which was first presented to the official Association of Public Health Officers and approved by it. This model law had gradually been adopted by the various states.

Registration of all births and deaths within the state is a function of the state health department. The state health officer, or some other person on his staff, who is responsible to, and is designated by him, is the official state registrar of vital statistics.

The basis for effective registration is the formation of an organization whereby each birth and death that occurs within the state shall be recorded immediately on an individual certificate. Standard uniform certificates may be used, as well as standard methods of collection of the certificates and standard methods of interpretation of the data. These certificates are filed as a permanent record, and become part of the state archives. [17]

The objects of the national registration areas was the uniform and standardized collection of birth and deaths throughout the entire United States, so that statistics from one part of the country could be accurately compared to that of another part. When the federal registration area for deaths began in 1880, it only embraced about 17% of the country’s population. In 1900 it was estimated that about 40.5% of the population had their deaths recorded; in 1915, the figure was up to 66.9%, and by 1925 the figure was up to 88%. As the author of Why Should Births and Deaths Be Registered? (published by the American Medical Association in various editions during the early 1900s), observed: the work of registration could not be called “a complete success until every birth and death in the United States shall be promptly recorded.” [18] The former Chief Statistician for Vital Statistics of the United States, in 1916, wrote of his hope of the “rapid expansion” of the registration areas, “not only for deaths … but also for births, until the entire country shall have attained a condition of 100% efficiency in this respect. [19]

American commentators and health officials during the later half of the 19th Century noted that “voluntary contribution of information by heads of families or physicians … ha[d] always been a failure.” [20] In a report prepared for the U.S. National Board of Health in 1882, Dr. John Billings, a surgeon in the United States Army discussed the problems surrounding the accurate collection of birth and death statistics. Members of the general public were simply not informed enough to understand the importance of birth and death registration. They “suppose that it is merely a hobby of the doctors, who want the information for their own private purposes, and that this information can only be obtained by an unjustified amount of meddling with private affairs and by a system of espionage which will cause much trouble and difficulty.” [21] In a report to the Kentucky legislature in 1853, it was noted that the vital statistic records in many European countries are universal and compulsory: “In this country they would, by many, be considered unreasonable, oppressive, and tyrannical.” [22] When a birth registration law was passed in South Carolina “many of the citizens absolutely refused to” cooperate with the law. [23] It soon became obvious to public officials that “We cannot … hope to obtain any entirely satisfactory system of registration of births until the people at large have become educated to the necessity for it, and are induced to seek such registration of their own accord in order to secure proof of legitimacy, title to property, &c.” [24] How true this observation was is reflected in the following comment: “The national Social Security Act [1935] proved to be a great stimulus to accurate birth certification. Many people had never considered a birth certificate to be of any importance until old age assistance, unemployment insurance, and other ramifications of the Social Security Act demonstrated to them that it was necessary to have this official proof of their existence.” [25] Another means of accommodating the people to the idea of registration was to use the public schools to instruct the up-and-coming generation about the importance of public health and the necessity of cooperating with governmental authorities for such purposes.

The 19th Century movement for registration of vital statistics emphasized the recording of deaths, not births. Authorities perceived that it was easier to enforce regulations which required a government certificate of death than of birth, because birth registration was considered a more invasive practice. A new born could go his or her entire life without a birth certificate, whereas a person’s body had to be disposed of within a few days of death. The laws in most American jurisdictions eventually required that a government permit be issued for “every interment and removal of a dead body, and the community soon learns to consider any attempt at burial without a permit as a suspicious circumstance … .” Another commentator noted that “The corpus of every deceased human being must somehow be disposed of. The central registration authority in each locality is the only person qualified to permit legal disposal. Therefore substantially all deaths must get registered.” [26] The City of New York first required a death certificate under its Act of April 2, 1803, “which established public health regulations for the metropolis.” All physicians were required to leave a signed note, which provided the name, age, and cause of death, with some member of the deceased’s household. Sextons (the church official responsible for the church graveyard) were required to have the physician’s statement present before any burial could occur. Violations of the law subjected the physician to a $ 50 fine, and the sexton to a $ 25. fine. [27] ] Thus it was that the entire death and dying process was regulated, so that no dead person could be legally buried without the proper state-required or city-required paperwork.

The doctor was one of the most important functionaries in the system of collecting vital statistics. As a person licensed by the state to practice medicine, it became the responsibility and duty of the physician to assist the public health officers in each locale. “It is an onerous public duty of each physician to report promptly to the health department all births and deaths that occur in his private practice. … Th[e] simple procedure [of filling out birth and death certificates] is one of the primary obligations to his patients and to the community that a physician assumes when he is granted permission by the state to practice medicine.” [28] However, this was not always the attitude of doctors during the 19th century. In an article in the Chicago Medical Journal of 1878, it was noted that

In this country there is only the curiosity of a few scientific men that can be relied upon for the moral support of a registry law, and it is probable that in Chicago not more than 12 in every thousand would be found to care for the registration of their nativity even in a family Bible. The reason why physicians do not execute the law is because they not only have no personal interest in its execution, but [also] because of an invincible, though not always clearly recognized, feeling of revolt against the injustice of a law which inflicts a special tax on the physician in the shape of postage, time, and trouble, and affords no compensation for the extra labor and expense. People do not like to make a present to the Government in any shape or form. It is as unjust for the State to add fifty cents to the doctor’s tax simply because he is a doctor as it would be to add fifty dollars. The State should pay for all such service and it need not incur any great expense. It might, as in the case of jury duty or military service by conscription, fix its own rate, but the obligation should be recognized. The payment would, of course, require increased general taxation, but the increase would be levied on all alike. The health officers are trying to get service from the doctors without paying for it. [29]

The Model Laws

Even after the Registration Areas for the recording of birth and death statistics were in place, it took government authorities many years to bring all of the United States into the system. In 1903, Congress officially endorsed the system by passing a resolution that called for nationwide support of “proper registration of all deaths and births” [30]. Pennsylvania was one of the states that embraced the system, and it was reported that in that state there were “hundred of actual prosecutions [which] have been directed by state authorities” against those who failed to register births. [31] In 1907, uniform legislation patterned after the law in Pennsylvania was prepared. This law, which became known as the Model Law, was “endorsed by the Census Department of the U. S. Government, the American Medical Association, the American Public Health Association, the American Statistical Association, the Committee on Uniform Laws of the American Bar Association, American Child Hygiene Association, [and] the American Federation of Labor … .” [32] When the registration area for births was established in 1915, it roughly embraced 31% of the American population. By 1927, it was in use in 45 of the 48 states.

The Model Law was officially titled “A Bill To Provide for the Registration of All Births and Deaths in the State of _____.” It essentially required the recording of all deaths within the State: no burials, cremations, removals, or interments were to take place without a death permit issued by the State Board of Health, and signed by the physician in last attendance [33], and if no physician was in attendance the next of kin or undertaker must notify the local health officer. The portion of the Model Law that concerned itself with birth registration began with the proviso “That the birth of each and every child born in this state shall be registered as hereinafter provided.” [34] The law stated that it was the duty of the physician, midwife, or person acting as midwife, to register the birth. If there was no one acting in this capacity at the birth, then it devolved upon the father or mother of the child, or the householder or owner of the premises where the birth took place to report to the local registrar the fact of such birth within ten days of its occurrence. Upon being notified of the birth, the local registrar had the responsibility to issue a birth certificate.

The Model Law was intended to be compulsory and universal. It applied to each and every person with the geographic area of the state and the law contained penalties for failure to comply. Under Section 22 of the Model Law, failure to meet the requirements of birth and death registration became a misdemeanor, “and upon conviction thereof for the first offense be fined not less than five dollars ($ 5.00) nor more than fifty dollars ($ 50.00), and for each subsequent offense not less than ten dollars ($ 10.00) nor more than one hundred dollars ($ 100.00), or be imprisoned in the county jail not more than sixty days, or be both fined and imprisoned in the discretion of the court.” [35] Although the Model Law did not explicitly endorse the idea, a footnote was inserted to the effect that “Provision may be made whereby compliance with this act shall constitute a condition of granting licenses to physicians, midwives, and embalmers.” [36] This meant that, assuming people practicing these occupations were issued new licenses each year, if they were convicted of failing to meet their obligations to register all new births and deaths which they attended, they would be denied their license to practice, and if they did not cease practicing their profession, they would be liable to be convicted of “practicing without a license.” Licensure denial was a very effective way of bringing about more complete birth and death registration.

It is interesting to note that as early as 1882, Dr. John Billings, the public health official who was quoted earlier in this paper, observed that:

All registration acts which are upon a proper basis presuppose also legislation providing for the determining of those who are properly qualified physicians, and for making the names of these known to the registrar. It may be said, therefore, that the registration of vital statistics depends for its efficiency, to a very large extent, upon some system of registration of physicians and midwives. [37]

An interesting implication to draw from Billings’ analysis is that unlicensed practitioners were the bane of the authorities. Unlicensed doctors (whether or not they were competent) were too difficult to track and too elusive to be certain whether they filed death certificates. In short, from the very beginning of the movement for registration of births and deaths, government authorities understood that they had to control the practitioners of the birth and death professions. If people in society at large were unwilling to conform to government dictates, the authorities realized it was much easier to enforce their regulations by focusing on a much smaller group of people, whose occupational activities could be regulated. [38] Billings follows the comments quoted above by a discussion of the obligation of physicians to report the existence of certain diseases to the public health authorities. He refers to this as “the compulsory notification of infectious diseases” and points out that if doctors are required to report infectious diseases to the public health department, there is no reason why they should not be willing to accept the compulsory reporting of deaths and the completion of death certificates. [39]

The Modern Era: The Logical Climax

In an article on “Documentary Identification and Mass Surveillance in the United States,” published in 1983, the authors noted the near total acceptance of birth certificates by all Americans: “It is practically impossible for an adult to live in the United States without frequent recourse to” documents of identification, such as the birth certificate, and “Today, documentary requirements make it difficult for anyone born in the United States to do without a birth certificate; … .” [40] The government has been so successful in convincing its citizens that identification papers are necessary that even forgers and identity thieves, when they want to create a new personal identity, rely on government documents (either stolen ones or forged ones). In short, in our society the only means of proving “who you are” is by means of government paperwork. Social Security numbers and drivers license did not even exist during the 19th Century. Before the 20th Century, “the majority of births in the United States remained unrecorded with any government agency,” but “[b]y 1950, census officials estimated that 97.9 percent of all births in the United States [were] being registered.” [41]

The success of the United States governments, both on the federal and state level, in accomplishing the feat of legitimizing itself in the minds and bodies of its citizenry has been phenomenal. In the span of four or five generations, Americans have moved from a situation of quasi-voluntaryism (of having their lives largely unregulated by government) to one of near-total government control over all their activities (literally, from birth to death). This success is best epitomized by the comment of William Smillie, who wrote that “the child has no real legal proof of existence in the eyes of the state without a proper birth certificate.” [42] Smillie’s comment represents how presumptuous the government is in making government documents the starting point of a person’s existence and identity. Traditionally in the United States, and in customary tribal societies, the members of the local community and social network into which a person was born stand as witness to that person’s birth (and death). Such events are “a matter of public record in the minds of the people” and there is no need for the government to take note of or register such events. [43]

In the monograph Why Should Births and Deaths Be Registered?, the author lists numerous reasons in support of his argument. Let us examine these reasons and see if the only way to achieve them is through government birth certification.

Such records are necessary in determining questions of parentage, heredity, legitimacy, personal identity, property rights, inheritance, and citizenship. No child labor law is of much value unless it rests on a system of birth registration and of birth certificates issued by the state by which the parent or the child can produce at any time positive proof of birth, paternity, and age. During the war [World War I], the operation of the selective draft act was greatly hampered by the fact that … no legal evidence could be produced or existed by which the age of the individual could be positively proven. [44] [Birth certificates are also useful:] To settle disputes as to age arising out of insurance claims; … [T]o obtain a marriage license; … [T]o gain admission to school; … As proof of citizenship in order to vote; … As proof of citizenship in order to obtain a passport. [45]

In analyzing these points, it is first necessary to observe how many of them involve some government regulation or the interaction of the individual with the state. Nearly all the uses of the birth certificate evaporate if the state is removed from the picture. Child labor law enforcement; military conscription of men over a certain age; proof of citizenship for voting and passport purposes; all these reasons disappear if there is no state. The non-state reasons for having a proof of birth then become limited to questions determining property rights, legitimacy, and inheritance. How were these issues handled before the advent of state-mandated birth certificates? They were clarified, resolved, and sorted out through personal testimony, family documents, and the appearance of witnesses and friends to support one’s claims. They certainly did not await settlement on the advent of state-issued birth certificates. Clearly, history is on the side of the non-state birth record, for people have lived, prospered, and died for thousands of years without such government documents.

There may be very good reasons for having records of birth and deaths, but this by no means implies that they must be maintained by the government. There are many “necessities” in life, but it does not follow that governments must provide them. For example, we all require food, shelter, and clothing, but during most of American history these necessities were provided by the free market to the extent that people could afford them and desired them. Realistically, there is no more reason for government to produce steel than there is for government to issue birth and death certificates. In a free society, a few organizations like Visa or MasterCard might evolve voluntarily to satisfy people’s demands for such records. Some people might choose to maintain their family’s birth and death records in an independent commercial registry; others might choose to use their family’s Bible; while others might simply keep track of such details themselves by issuing their own documents of record; and those who were either too ignorant or to unconcerned would simply do nothing. The point is that no one would be forced by another person or another group of people to become documented in a way that they did not desire. Those who wanted documentation could have all the identification papers they wanted and could pay for; those who objected would not be coerced. Charities would probably arise to provide for or pay for the documentation and identification of those who could not afford it themselves.

What opponents of state-mandated birth and death certificates object to is the “means.” They reject the compulsion involved in the state requiring that everyone have a birth certificate. They may or may not object to voluntarily having a birth certificate (of whatever form they or their parents chose), but they do oppose the use of coercion which would require that everyone have a state-issued birth certificate. Paraphrasing Robert Ringer, “I do not believe that I or any other person has the right to force men to be charitable [or to have state-issued birth certificates]. In other words, I am not against charity [or state-issued birth certificates], but I am against the use of force.” [46]

Before the days of official birth certificates, it was standard practice in many parts of the world for strangers to carry “letters of introduction.” Such documents, issued by a well-known personage, would assure the person presenting it of a much quicker reception and acceptance in a society where he was not known. Other ways of establishing one’s reputation in a strange community have historically involved the use of credentials, such as educational degrees and membership certificates in professional or religious organizations. Even the credit card serves as a credential of trustworthiness and reputation. [47] Similarly, in a stateless society, private companies and organizations would probably develop a means guaranteeing a person’s real or true identity. Such a procedure would be akin to the issuance of a surety bond, issued by a reputable insurance company. In transactions that merited the importance of such a guarantee, a “personal identity bond” might be demanded, so that in the event of one person masquerading as another, the party being deceived would have recourse to a reputable institution to recover his or her loss. Such a personal identity bond would be much like title insurance is today in real estate transactions. It would serve as a guarantee by an independent company that in the event of any legitimate and unexpected claim arising, the person defrauded would be reimbursed by the insurance company. The development on the internet of digital certificates, public key infrastructures, and private credentials represents a step toward a non-governmental means of identification. [48]

As with many of the services it provides, the State has done a poor job in the provision of birth-recording services. Undoubtedly, even in a free society there would be people who attempt to criminally pretend they are other than who they really are. However, under the existing state system, there is near total reliance on “self-identification.” So long as a person can supply a certain amount of personal information (date of birth, mother’s maiden name, father’s name, place of birth, and a legitimate address) governmental authorities will issue a duplicate birth certificate to that person. As yet, there is no relatively fool-proof system of identifying the person demanding the document with the person whose birth is recorded thereon. [49] The current government attempts to use biometrics, or even the suggestions of others to fingerprint or tattoo each newborn is a way around this impasse.

When state provision of birth and death records began there was practically no thought given to where it such government programs might lead. Jeremy Bentham, in the 1830s, was one of the earliest proponents of identifying everyone (by use of tattoos) in a given geographic jurisdiction. State involvement in vital statistics was justified on the perfectly innocent grounds of providing for the public’s health and welfare by concentrating on the causes of death. Anyone who would have taken a principled stand on this issue in the early 1900s would have been laughed down. No one could have predicted that state-issued birth certificates would have been linked to the issuance of Social Security numbers, drivers licenses, passports, and other government documents. [50]

Effective birth registration lies at the heart of the state’s governance of its people. Realizing this, governments have coercively monopolized the issuance of birth certificates by making it a criminal act for those who are responsible for a birth not to register the newborn. The classic definition of the State is that it is the only institution in society that derives its revenues from compulsory levies, known as taxation, and that it maintains a compulsory monopoly of defense services (such as the police, armed forces, and judicial system) over a given geographic area. [51] When you combine these elements with the state’s success in sustaining a monopoly over the means of identification, the stage is set for a totalitarian world. Once you grant local, state, or county government a role in identifying its citizens, there is no logical stopping place until you reach the federal level of demanding complete and total identification of each person in the United States, or in the world, if you are a supporter of world government. In fact, such demands have emanated from the United Nations, both in its 1966 call for the registration of every child at its birth, and as recently as December 2001, in an effort to reduce illegal immigration. [52]

“Therefore to oppose government enumeration is not only to oppose the government’s monopoly on the means of identification in modern society by opposing social security numbers, drivers licenses, biometric national ID cards, national databases, and other means now at the center of national controversy, but to oppose it at the most fundamental level, that of government-issued and-recorded birth and death certificates.” [53]

 

Endnotes

[1] Cressy L. Wilbur, M. D., The Federal Registration Service of the United States: Its Development, Problems, and Defects, Washington: Government Printing Office, 1916, p. 8.

[2] John S. Billings, M.D., Appendix E: “The Registration of Vital Statistics,” in Annual Report of the [U.S.] National Board of Health: 1882, Washington: Government Printing Office, 1883, p. 357. John Shaw Billings (1838-1913) was Director of Vital Statistics of the United States government and a “leader of the medical profession,” who played an important role in the historical development of the tabulating machine, the early predecessor of the IBM computer. It was he who, in an 1880 discussion with Herman Hollerith, first suggested “that the laborious work of hand tabulation could be replaced by mechanical devices and by the use of a card with holes punched to represent the items.” Hollerith went on to develop one of the first successful mechanical tabulator/punch card readers for the Bureau of the Census in 1890. The Tabulating Machine Company, which Hollerith founded, eventually became the nucleus of the commercial organization renamed International Business Machine (IBM) in 1924. See “John Shaw Billings,” II Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences, New York: The Macmillan Company, p. 542; James Connolly, History of Computing in Europe, IBM World Trade Corporation, circa 1967, pp. 5-6 and p. 22; and Edwin Black, IBM and the Holocaust, New York: Crown Publishers, 2001, p. 25.

[3] See Major P. Granville Edge, “Vital Registration in Europe: The Development of Official Statistics and Some Differences In Practice,” 91 Royal Statistical Society Journal (1928), pp. 346-393, especially pp. 354-355, and p. 375, “Appendix I. The [Compulsory] Registration of Births and Deaths.” Also see Billings, op. cit. p. 355.

[4] Robert Rene Kuczynski, “The Registration Laws in the Colonies of Massachusetts Bay and New Plymouth,” New Series 51, American Statistical Association, September 1900, p. 9. Also see Wilbur, op. cit., p. 37 and Billings, op. cit., p. 356.

[5] Wilbur, op. cit., p. 37.

[6] Generally see Richard Shryock, “The Origins and Significance of the Public Health Movement in the United States,” New Series I, Annals of Medical History, 1929, pp. 645-665. For the quotation see James H. Cassedy, DEMOGRAPHY IN EARLY AMERICA: Beginnings of the Statistical Mind, 1600-1800, Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1969, p. 211.

[7] Wilson G. Smillie, Public Health Administration in the United States, New York: The Macmillan Company, 1947 (Third Edition), p. 13. An “English law of 1874 adopted provisions already in force in Scotland, compelling physicians to return certificates of death; … .” W. P. Prentice, Police Powers Arising Under the Law of Overruling Necessity, New York: Banks & Brothers, 1894, p. 156.

[8] cited in William J. Novak, The People’s Welfare: Law and Regulation in Nineteenth Century America, Chapel Hill: The University of North Carolina Press, 1996, p. 13.

[9] ibid., p. 14.

[10] Robert Gutman, Birth and Death Registration in Massachusetts 1639 – 1900, New York: Milbank Memorial Fund, 1959, p. 24 and p. 10.

[11] ibid., p. 56 and p. 32.

[12] ibid. pp. 48-49.

[13] ibid., p. 60 and p. 63.

[14] ibid., p. 103.

[15] ibid., p. 106.

[16] ibid., p. 109.

[17] Smillie, op. cit., p. 189.

[18] Why Should Births and Deaths Be Registered?: A Summary of the History and Present Condition of Vital Statistics Law, Including the Text of the Model Bill, Chicago: Press of the American Medical Association, 1927, p. 8. Italics in the original.

[19] Wilbur, op. cit., p. 9.

[20] Billings, op. cit., p. 357.

[21] ibid.

[22] W. L. Sutton, “Appendix” to the Second Annual Report to the General Assembly of Kentucky Relating to the Registry and Returns of Births, Marriages, and Deaths, From January 1, 1852 to December 31, 1853, Legislative Document No. 1, Frankfort: A. G. Hodges, 1854, p. 136.

[23] ibid., p. 140.

[24] Billings, op. cit., p. 360.

[25] Smillie, op. cit., p. 191.

[26] Billings, op. cit. p. 364, and Raymond Pearl, Introduction to Medical Biometry and Statistics, Philadelphia: W. B. Saunders Company, Third Edition, Revised and Enlarged, 1940, p. 54.

[27] “New York’s First Death Certificate,” The American Cemetery Magazine, November 1981, p. 22.

[28] Smillie, op. cit., pp. 525-526.

[29] Billings, op. cit., p. 365.

[30] Why Should Births and Deaths Be Registered?, op. cit., p. 3.

[31] Wilbur, op. cit., p. 17.

[32] Why Should Births and Deaths Be Registered?, op. cit., p. 3 and 9.

[33] Sec. 8, Model Law found in ibid., p. 27.

[34] ibid., Sec. 12, p. 31.

[35] ibid., Sec. 22, pp. 44-45.

[36] ibid., Sec. 22, p. 45.

<p[37] billings,=”” op.=”” cit.,=”” p.=”” 366.<=”” p=””>

[38] See Ron Hamowy, “The Early Development of Medical Licensing Laws in the United States 1875 – 1900,” delivered at the 6th Annual Libertarian Scholar’s Conference, Princeton Univ., October 1978, and which was published in 3 JOURNAL OF LIBERTARIAN STUDIES (No. 1, Spring 1979), and which can be found at http://www.libertarianstudies.org/journals/jls/pdfs/3_1/3_1_5.pdf. Also see Chapter 4, “Medical Societies and Medical Licensing,” in William G. Rothstein, American Physicians in the Nineteenth CenturyAMERICAN PHYSICIANS IN THE NINETEENTH CENTURY, Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1972, pp. 63 – 84.

[39] Billings, op. cit., p. 366.

[40] James Rule, Douglas McAdam, Linda Stearns, and David Uglow, “Documentary Identification and Mass Surveillance in the United States,” 31 Social Problems (No. 2), December 1983, pp. 222-234 at p. 222 and p. 224.

[41] ibid., p. 224.

[42] Smillie, op. cit., p. 191.

[43] This point was made in personal correspondence from Aslam Effendi, a descendant of the Pathans in Pakistan and Afghanistan, who wrote “that in tribal society there is no bureaucratic system for recording of births” or deaths. [Email dated February 25, 2002.] Simon Cole makes a similar point in his book Suspect Identities: A History of Fingerprinting and Criminal Identification (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2001), p. 8: “In general, premodern societies already had an effective method of personal, and criminal, identification: the network of personal acquaintance through which persons were ‘known’ in the memories and perceptions of their neighbors [and relatives].”

[44] Why Should Births and Deaths Be Registered?, op. cit., p. 1.

[45] ibid., pp. 5-6.

[46] Robert Ringer, Restoring the American Dream, New York: Published by QED, 1979, p. 134 (from Chapter 4, “The Gourmet Banquet,” in the next to the last paragraph of the Section headlined “The Fate of the ‘Poor’ In A Free Society”.

[47] See Steven L. Nock, The Costs of Privacy: Surveillance and Reputation in America, New York: Aldine de Gruyter, 1993. Nock asks, “How are reputations established among strangers?” and then answers this question by discussing the role of credentials (“credit cards, educational degrees, driver’s licenses”) and ordeals (lie detector tests, drug tests, integrity tests”). Especially see pp. viii, 1-3, 14-15, 47-48, 51, 76-77, and 92-93.

[48] For greater elaboration see “Private Credentials,” Montreal: Zero-Knowledge Systems, Inc. (November 2000). This is a white paper available on Zero-Knowledge Systems’ website.

[49] For a discussion of this point see Rule, et. al., op. cit., p. 227.

[50] In 1998, the Social Security Administration began the “Enumeration at Birth” program, which “allows a parent to apply for an SSN for his/her newborn as part of the State’s birth registration process.” This program was started to ease enforcement of the January 1, 1998 IRS requirement that tax returns must have the Social Security number of all dependents claimed as exemptions. See U. S. Department of Health and Human Services, “Unique Health Identifier for Individuals: A White Paper,” at http://www.epic.org/privacy/medical/hhs-id-798.html at p. 12.

[51] For a general discussion of voluntaryism and anarchism see Carl Watner, I MUST SPEAK OUT: The Best of THE VOLUNTARYIST 1982 – 1999, San Francisco: Fox & Wilkes, 1999. Especially see p. 24 and pp. 47 – 48.

[52] Article 24 (2) of the United Nations International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (General Assembly Resolution 2200A (XXI) of December 16, 1966 states that “Every child shall be registered immediately after birth and shall have a name.” On December 14, 2001, at a United Nations refugee meeting in Geneva, Switzerland it was proposed that “Every person in the world would be fingerprinted and registered under a universal identification scheme to fight illegal immigration and people smuggling … .” Maria Hawthorne, “Refugees meeting hears proposal to register every human,” at http:www/smh.com.au/breaking/2001/12/14/FFX058CU6VC.html.

[53] Thanks to Claire Wolfe for suggesting this conclusion.

National Identification Systems: Preface


By Carl Watner

In the weeks and months that followed September 11, 2001, Americans heard more and more about the need for national ID. Amidst these calls for increased security, Wendy McElroy suggested I examine the morality and the practicality of these programs. Would giving each person in the United States a unique number for life actually make us safer or would it simply allow governments to track us from cradle to grave? Had these suggestions for monitoring individuals ever been made before? What were the precedents – both historical and philosophical? What were the assumptions, implications, and likely outcomes of such a system? Would they make us more secure from attack or would we simply become more visible to those who wanted to tax and control us?

National Identification Systems is more than a book about national ID. It is about all forms of government enumeration, from the census of antiquity – to government naming practices, fingerprinting, social security numbers, drivers licenses – to cutting-edge, biometric technologies, such as DNA, iris scans, or subcutaneous microchips capable of allowing those in charge to know where we are twenty-four hours a day via global positioning satellites. This book looks at the “big” picture of national ID: “what it is, how it has developed, and how it might potentially change our society.” It is also about those who have chosen to resist or oppose national ID schemes – from Gandhi’s satyagraha campaign in South Africa in 1906 to those Americans who refuse to be counted or carry a government number today. These “Essays in Opposition” are intended to honor those whose consciences and principles do not allow them to “roll over” and acquiesce.

As I began to research the topic of government enumeration it became readily apparent that this was a highly ideologically-charged subject – with most people believing that some sort of government intervention was a prerequisite to modern life. In fact, several potential contributors to this book refused to allow me permission to reprint their work because they were opposed to the ideological drift of this anthology. Never before has there been a book devoted to the idea that the logical outcome of government involvement in these areas (from government birth certificates to governmental databases and surveillance) is 1984-style population control. That is why national ID systems have been called a “trademark of totalitarianism.” While Americans might be able to avoid the abuses that such systems have brought about in other countries (national ID cards always seem to facilitate genocide, as one of our chapters points out), there remains the telling point that national ID and enhanced governmental powers always go hand in hand.

As in all intellectual efforts, this book could not have been assembled without help from numerous people. Foremost to be mentioned is Claire Wolfe, whose depth of knowledge, personal contacts, and editorial assistance I found invaluable. The two books that I continually consulted during my year-long work on this anthology were Jane Caplan and John Torpey’s, Documenting Individual Identity: The Development of State Practices in the Modern World, and Simon Cole’s Suspect Identities: A History of Fingerprinting and Criminal Identification. The Inter-Library Loan Departments at the Spartanburg County Public Library and Wofford College went far above and beyond the call of duty in helping me to locate hard-to-find materials, some of which are mentioned in Chapter 28, “For Further Reading.” I would like to thank the Center for Independent Thought and various subscribers to The Voluntaryist for their support of this project.

Readers, as you grapple with the questions presented by this book, please remember that I take responsibility for all its faults and errors. Whatever merit you find in its arguments, historical analysis, and conclusions belong to those contributors who were so generous in allowing me to use their work. I only hope that you, your children, or your grandchildren will one day offer thanks to those in the ranks of the opposition who saw fit to challenge government enumeration.

NONVIOLENCE: A REVIEW OF MARK KURLANSKY’S 2006 BOOK BY THAT NAME


By Ned Netterville

I seldom come across a book by an Earthling (voluntaryists and Austrian economists are from Mars or Venus, depending on their gender) that sends me to my feet pumping my fist like Tiger Woods when with talent and force of will he sends a forty-foot put curling into the cup. But that’s what I caught myself doing as I read Mark Kurlansky’s 2006 book, Nonviolence, subtitled Twenty-Five Lessons from the History of a Dangerous Idea. This is a must-read for anyone desiring world or local peace but perplexed by how to achieve it.


The clarion-clear message of this narrowly focused history of the use of violence versus nonviolence is that when it comes to throwing off forcible oppression, nonviolent resistance beats violence hands down. Yet so little is understood regarding its effectiveness and accomplishments that there is no word in any language for the opposite of violence beyond the negative, nonviolence. Kurlansky shows that failure to understand that nonviolence is an efficacious means and a potent force in the hands of peacemakers or the oppressed is a serious mistake benefiting only warriors and tyrants. The author points out, “it has always been treated as something profoundly dangerous” by the rulers of states. His concise history traces the concept of nonviolence among ancient people of various religions up to the recent past. He deduces from his examination that “Though most religions shun warfare and hold nonviolence as the only moral route towards political change, religion and its language have been co-opted by the violent people who have been governing societies.”


Kurlansky distinguishes between pacifism and nonviolence: “Pacifism is passive; but nonviolence is active. Pacifism is harmless and therefore easier to accept than nonviolence, which is dangerous… . Nonviolence, exactly like violence, is a means of persuasion, a technique of political activism, a recipe for prevailing.” And, I might add, nonviolence has a potent spiritual component that the initiators of violence cannot comprehend and have no means to counter.

Kurlansky’s narrative points to the almighty state as the ultimate villain in causing wars, although he doesn’t explicitly say so. He does say that when church and state combine, both become depraved. Jesus was both a pacifist and so dangerously nonviolent that the Roman Empire murdered him. His early followers adopted his ways, but when the Christian church was subsumed by the Roman Empire during Constantine’s reign, Christianity betrayed the teaching of Jesus. Augustine concocted a theory to justify war, and Christians have been warring ever since. Kurlansky refers to its amalgamation with Rome as “a calamity from which the Church has never recovered.” And he adds, “One of history’s greatest lessons is that once the state embraces a religion, the nature of that religion changes radically. It loses its nonviolent component and becomes a force for war rather than peace.”

Kurlansky’s narrative illuminates twenty-five lessons from the history of nonviolence, which he enumerates at the conclusion of the book, but there are certainly others to be found therein by the discerning reader. Here are a few of the enumerated lessons that have not already been mentioned:


———Nations that build military forces as deterrents will eventually use them.
———Practitioners of nonviolence are seen as enemies of the state.
———A propaganda machine promoting hatred always has a war waiting in the wings.
———People who go to war start to resemble their enemy.
———A conflict between a violent and a nonviolent force is a moral argument. If the violent can provoke the nonviolent into violence, the violent side has won.
——— The problem lies not in the nature of man but in the nature of power.
———The state imagines it is impotent without a military because it cannot conceive of power without force.
———All debate ends with an “enforced silence” once the first shots are fired.
———Violence never resolves. It always leads to more violence.
———Once you start the business of killing, you just get deeper and deeper without limits.
———Violence always comes with a supposedly rational explanation.
———Violence is a virus that infects and takes over.
———The hard work of beginning a movement to end war has already been done.

Here are a few other lessons extracted from Kurlansky’s work:


———Government propaganda makes war out to be a holy crusade for freedom.
———It is much easier to start a war than to stop it.
———A war will never end wars; it always leads to the next one.
———If one doesn’t stand up for what’s right, what’s wrong will never change.

I find only one flaw in Kurlansky’s brave book. He fails to notice the obvious connection between the violent nature of the state, which causes every war, and the predatory means by which the state obtains funds that are vital to its wars and to its very existence. I am referring, of course, to taxes, without which a state must whither and die. The collection of taxes requires the initiation of force, or threat thereof, against otherwise peaceful, harmless, innocent individuals. Force is but another word for violence, and violence begets only its kind–more violence. Directly and indirectly, then, taxes cause wars. No war has ever been fought without taxes or an equivalent other form of state plunder.

When Kurlansky writes that the hard work of beginning a movement to end war has already been done, he wasn’t referring to his book, but to the words and deeds of the practitioners of nonviolence, such as the Chinese rebel, Mozi (470 – 390 B.C.), Jesus, Gandhi, and Martin Luther King (among the most famous). With the publication of his book, Nonviolence, Kurlansky joins that illustrious group of workers who have shown us the whys, the how’s, and the ways of nonviolence.

Meeting the State Head-On


 

by Anonymous

[Author’s Note: This article was sparked by recently reading two older voluntaryist essays by Carl Watner: “Highway Tax vs. Poll Tax: Some Thoreau Tax Trivia” (Issue 71), and “Charles Lane: Voluntaryist”, the Introduction to A VOLUNTARY POLITICAL GOVERNMENT: LETTERS FROM CHARLES LANE.]

In Henry David Thoreau’s famous essay “Civil Disobedience” (which was originally titled “Resistance to Civil Government”), he wrote that he had paid no poll-tax for six years. [1] The poll-tax or head-tax, as it was sometimes called, has been part of human history since the times of the ancient Egyptians and Romans. It was basically a capitation tax levied in a fixed amount on each “taxable” person. In colonial America this often meant that the male “head of household pa[id] the tax on himself, his wife, his children sixteen years of age and older, indentured servants, and slaves.” (Rabushka, 15) The poll-tax was epitomized in Jewish law which collected one-half shekel from every man regardless of his wealth: “the rich shall not pay more and the poor shall not pay less.” (Exodus 30:11-16)

In the Massachusetts of Thoreau’s day, the poll-tax amounted to $ 1.50 per year. [2] The basis for its assessment was found in the State Constitution of 1780 “which provided that ‘the public charges of government’ should be assessed ‘on polls and estates in the manner that has hitherto been practiced’.” (Broderick, 613) As recounted in TAXATION IN COLONIAL AMERICA, Alvin Rabushka observed that the poll tax was collected in nearly all the North American colonies, and in many cases refusal to pay resulted in distraint of one’s property. [3] Although it was a standard source of revenue for both colonial and state governments, “low taxes, noncompliance, and arrears were a chronic fact of fiscal life.” (Rabushka, 868) In fact, Rabushka asserted that in Massachusetts at the time of Paul Revere’s ride on April 18, 1775, “the residents of Massachusetts had created for themselves a fiscal paradise.” (779)

So why did Thoreau and his friends, Bronson Alcott and Charles Lane, object to paying the poll-tax even though it was such a minimal amount? “It [wa]s for no particular item in the tax-bill” that Thoreau and friends “refuse[d] to pay it. (206) Much like voluntaryists today, they “simply wish[ed] to refuse allegiance to the State, to withdraw and stand aloof from it … .” (206) The Massachusetts Revised Statutes of 1836 stated that the poll-tax was to be assessed upon “each taxable person in the town, where he shall be an inhabitant the first day of May in each year.” (Broderick, 614) As Rabushka put it, “To reside was to pay.” (166) It had nothing to do with citizenship (Lane had been born in England and resided there until 1842). It had everything to do with simply being a person living in a particular place. Did they, by their very existence, owe taxes to the town government where they lived? According to the town of Concord and the State of Massachusetts, there was no legal way to avoid the tax, short of leaving the state permanently. Yet, they did not want to leave their homes or lose their property, but neither did they want to support the institution of government.

Thus the “inhabitants” of Massachusetts’ towns had to meet the poll tax head-on, much as people today are faced with confronting local, state, and federal income taxes. [4] Governments, then and now, take one’s very existence as evidence that one owes a tax. In “Resistance to Civil Government,” Thoreau wrote, “If there were one who lived wholly without the use of money, the State itself would hesitate to demand it of him.” (200) However, this is not true today, even if it were in Thoreau‘s time (which is doubtful). If there were such a person in today’s United States, the IRS or a state revenue department would still want to know 1) why that person hadn’t filed a tax return; 2) if that person had any taxable income; and 3) how that person lived without incurring a tax liability. It is just as nearly impossible to hide from the IRS as it would have been to hide from the town-constable in Thoreau’s day. (It might even be more difficult today with the advent of government identifiers, computers, and government-issued birth certificates.)

Thoreau’s refusal to pay the poll tax would be much like refusing to file or pay federal and state income taxes today. It pits the individual against the State. The IRS assumes that your very existence means that you owe taxes, or at least an explanation as to why you don’t. The IRS places the burden of proof on the individual taxpayer to show why no return is due and/or to prove why no tax is owed. In principle, the government assumes that everyone owes, and that it may take as much or as little as the President, members of Congress and the IRS agree on. In effect, what you think you ‘own’ is actually government property that the government lets you ‘rent.’ See what happens to you and your property if you don’t pay your ‘rent’ (i.e., taxes). Much like monarchs of old, the government grants people the privilege of keeping only as much as the government allows. Taxation is not theft, from the government’s perspective, because it is only taking what already belongs to it. The whole premise behind government taxation is essentially the idea that you and your property belong to the State; that the government ‘owns’ everything in the geographic area over which it exerts control.

People are enslaved if their bodies are owned by others; but they are also slaves if others control their property or the results of their labor. If the State may take one dollar out of what a man owns, then it may take up to his last dollar. Once admit the right of the State to tax, then the State becomes the owner of all property. As in most situations in life, it is best to resist at the beginning, and thus it behooves us to stand tall and firm against the State and resist head-on by refusing to file or pay taxes.

Endnotes

[1] See page 203 of Thoreau. Numbers within parentheses in the text are page numbers of a particular article or book referred to below.
[2] $1.50 would be 7.5% of a $ 20 gold piece, which contains slightly less than an ounce of pure gold. We can extrapolate that into today’s prices by taking 7.5% of gold at $ 1300 an ounce and arrive at approximately $ 97, which would have been collected once a year.
[3] Walter Harding (37) was the first to note that the town-tax collectors of Massachusetts were empowered to levy upon the goods and property of the person, and if these were insufficient to satisfy the tax, then the collector was authorized to “take the body of such person and commit him to prison, there to remain until he shall pay the tax and the charges of commitment and imprisonment, or shall be discharged by order of law.”
[4] The problem of avoiding sales tax, which is nearly ubiquitous on most purchases today, is not discussed in this article.

References

John C. Broderick, “Thoreau, Alcott, and the Poll Tax,” 53 STUDIES IN PHILOLOGY (1956), pp. 612-626.
Walter Harding, “Thoreau in Jail: Was It Legal?” 26 AMERICAN HERITAGE (August 1975), pp. 36-37.
Alvin Rabushka, TAXATION IN COLONIAL AMERICA, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2008.
Henry Thoreau, “Resistance to Civil Government,” in Elizabeth P. Peabody (ed.) AESTHETIC PAPERS, NEW York: G. P. Putnam, 1849, Article X, pp. 189-211.

Taxation Is Theft: A Constructive Explanation


By Spencer and Emalie MacCallum

 

How do we best explain the voluntaryist position and bring people to understand that taxation is theft? The philosopher Spencer Heath once remarked, when this question arose, that people cannot recognize atrocity until they can entertain in their minds an alternative. He gave the example of slavery in the ancient world. Virtually no writers of antiquity, although they may have urged that people treat their slaves and other livestock kindly, ever proposed the abolition of slavery. Slavery was accepted as the basic economy upon which society was established; it was not something that it made any sense to question. It was not until technology had developed to the point that people could entertain in their minds alternatives to slavery, that they could recognize slavery as atrocity.

The same now applies to taxation. Only when people can entertain in their minds alternatives to taxation will they be able to recognize it as theft. Hence it behooves us, rather than bashing taxation to no avail, to study and promulgate the alternative, free-market ways of financing public services — to show the alternatives that are now emerging. This will be a constructive approach, which all people can appreciate and, moreover, will be unlikely to antagonize folks in places of power.

[This article was prepared for the essay contest “How Do You Explain To People that Taxation is Theft?“. Spencer MacCallum is an American anthropologist, business consultant, and author.]

Stimulus Payment Returned



 

by Lloyd Licher

May 19, 2008 Letter to the Marin Independent Journal Newspaper

Stimulus Payment Returned

Editor:

I was hoping my stimulus payment would arrive in the form of a check, so I could have a ceremonial burning of it, similar to the one when I burned my Social Security card on July 4, 1968, vowing never to take any Social Security (and later Medicare) payments. But instead it was deposited directly into my checking account, thereby contaminating it until I wrote a return check to The Political State of The United States of America and sent it to Washington, D.C., along with a copy of this letter.

As a principled libertarian I feel compelled to state publicly why I took this action. I consider such payments fraudulent and therefore immoral, by my standards, because they come from either creating money out of thin air, thereby inflating and devaluing what money already exists, or from taxes exacted from other people. It does not represent what has been taken from me in taxes, by force (and therefore immoral), since such taxes have already been disbursed to others, and can only come from what was wrongly taken from others, or created out of thin air.

I realize that this is an extreme position to take and will meet with disfavor by most who learn of it, but I have control of only one person, myself, and can sleep peacefully on my pinnacle of principle, knowing I have not taken stolen goods.

My pinnacle has thrust through the broad cover of political deception under which most people reside because they were never taught critical thinking, or to question the coercive system that enslaves them. From up here I can see the grand concept of freedom and can only hope that everyone could know it as I do.

By,

Lloyd Licher

100 Sunnyside Ave., Corte Madera, CA 94925
924-0891 (home), or 446-2132 (office)

My Taxes



 

by Karl Hess

On April 15 [1969], I sent the following letter, accompanying my filled-out 1040 Form to the Tax Collector:

The Declaration of Independence of the United States of America establishes a bill of particulars in regard to intolerable infringements. abuses, and denials of political power which belongs to the people.

The Federal government of the United States of America today is guilty of exactly every sort of infringement, abuse, and denial stated as intolerable by the Declaration of Independence.

I cannot, in conscience, sanction that government by the payment of taxes.

Further, the Federal government of the United States of America has established as a principle, and ruthlessly by the power of its officials enforces as a practice, that it can demand the primary loyalty of the people, that it can exercise all political power on their behalf, that it can wage war without their approval, and that it can and should establish the standards of their behavior and the goals of their lives.

I could not in conscience sanction such a government by the payment of taxes.

Finally, the Declaration of Independence, in the clearest possible language, tells Americans that when a government become destructive of the ends of life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness that it is the right and duty of the people to abolish such government, to “throw off such government.”

It is in the spirit of that Declaration, and in comradeship with men everywhere who seek freedom and to throw off such government, that I now refuse to pay the taxes demanded by the government in the attached form.

[This letter originally appeared in THE LIBERTARIAN, May 1, 1969, p. 3.]

Jesus on Taxes


Excerpted from www.jesus-on-taxes.com (website no longer available) (pages 8-9).

This essay contains three hypotheses. The primary thesis is that, contrary to what most people have been led to believe by their church and government leaders, Jesus did not condone taxation nor endorse the concept of the nation-state when he said ‘render unto Caesar therefore the things which are Caesar’s.” If the essay succeeds in persuading some readers of that one point, we are confident those who read it with an open mind will be persuaded, our research, writing and prayers will be vindicated.

The second hypothesis is this: Jesus taught and lived by principles diametrically opposed to government and taxes. If that is true, then those who would live their lives according to the principles Jesus taught will neither collect, receive, nor voluntarily pay taxes, nor be involved with the state in any way that can possibly be avoided.

Finally, although Jesus died of his own volition in compliance with his Father’s will in order to save mankind from sin, which may be the most important fact to know about Jesus, our third hypothesis holds that it is likely and eminently logical to believe that Pontius Pilate crucified Jesus for teaching his disciples that taxation is condemned by God’s commandment, Thou shalt not steal. Pilate obviously didn’t kill Jesus to save mankind from sin, although Jesus died for that purpose. Did he die to save us from taxes? If, as this essay shows, taxes are sinful because they violate God’s Commandment, it follows as night follows day that indeed he did.

Is Taxation Theft?: An Exchange of Letters


 

[Editor’s Note: I wrote the following letters to J. Budziszewski, who is an Associate Professor in the Departments of Government and Philosophy at the University of Texas, Austin. Professor Budziszewski did not give permission to reprint his replies.]

October 30, 1999

Dear Dr. Budziszewski:
I first learned of your new book, The Revenge of the Conscience, when it was featured by the Conservative Book Club.
You made a powerful point about Expropriationism at pp. 92-93: expropriation [stealing] would be wrong even if each of its causes were good. In other words, the end does not justify the means. The pertinent passages from your book are as follows:

    But expropriation would be wrong even if each of its causes were good. Consider the following progression:

  1. On a dark street, a man draws a knife and demands my money for drugs.
  2. Instead of demanding my money for drugs, he demands it for the Church.
  3. Instead of being alone, he is with a bishop of the Church who acts as bagman.
  4. Instead of drawing a knife, he produces a policeman who says I must do as he says.
  5. Instead of meeting me on the street, he mails me his demand as an official agent of the government.

If the first is theft, it is difficult to see why the other four are not also theft. Expropriation is wrong not because its causes are wrong, but because it is a violation of the Eighth Commandment: Thou shalt not steal.
But how, one may ask, can government steal?… [I]s it wrong for the government to tax…? No, government may certainly collect taxes for the support of its proper work; that work, however, is not the support of all good causes, but merely punishing wrongdoers and commending rightdoers (1 Pet. 2:13-14)….
If government were to end its subsidy of good causes, wouldn’t these good causes suffer? Not necessarily; they might even thrive. Marvin Olasky has shown in The Tragedy of American Compassion that government subsidy itself can make good causes suffer, for in taking money by force one weakens both the means and the motive for people to give freely. But what if the causes did depend on the proceeds of theft? Should we do evil, that good may come?

I do not understand how you apply this reasoning to government taxation.
There will always be a few people, at least, who would not willingly and voluntarily contribute their money to our government, even if that government were devoted to its proper work. They might be conscientious objectors to taxation, or pacifists, or anarchists who do not consider that government has any proper work to do. So long as such objectors remain peaceful and do not initiate any violence against other citizens, is it not expropriation [stealing] when the government takes their money against their wills?
It does not seem to me that you can have it both ways. Either expropriation is wrong regardless of the cause for which the money is used (therefore taxation is theft in the cases in which the taxpayer would not willingly pay the tax) or the end does justify the means, which is the case you argue when you say that the cause of proper government justifies the expropriation.
Doesn’t the Eighth Commandment apply one standard of behavior to all – both taxpayer and government itself? It does not say, “Thou shalt not steal – except when the government requires money for its proper work“.
This letter is offered in the spirit of constructive criticism. I wish you would reconsider your defense of coercive taxation for government’s proper work. Please let me know what you think of my reasoning, even if you disagree.

Sincerely,
Carl Watner


November 12, 1999

Dear Professor Budziszewski:
Thanks for responding to my letter about expropriations, taxes, and the stealing commandment. I know it is difficult to envision proper government in the absence of coercive taxes, but I wish you would give it some more thought.
You emasculate the meaning of both theft and the stealing commandment when you argue that “there could sometimes be a sufficient warrant for the taking of wealth without consent.” One person’s good cause might be charity; another’s (such as your’s) might be having a proper government. But in neither case is the end a justification for using wrong means. To say that “he [a man] ought to approve the taking of his wealth for the support of the proper work of government” is the same as saying that the “good” cause of proper government justifies the taking of another’s wealth without consent (or at least the result is the same).
You affirm that stealing would be wrong even if its causes were good. [“Expropriation is wrong not because its causes are wrong, but because it is a violation of the Eighth Commandment: Thou shalt not steal.” p. 92]. Then, however, you contradict yourself by asserting that the “good” end of proper government justifies taxation. The question then becomes: Why do you make an exception for proper government? Is there some necessity about having a proper government which requires us to make an exception to the stealing commandment?
The Christian way of honoring the commandment would be 1) to persuade and educate those who refuse to contribute to proper government about why they ought to contribute to its support (in other words, convince them why they ought to contribute rather than permitting the government to steal from them), and/or 2) to contribute enough of their own money to make proper government possible. Instead, most Christians readily approve the placing of men in jail and/or confiscating their property against their will when they refuse to contribute. This initiation of violence is un-Christian and a violation of the stealing commandment.
At the very least you ought to concede that there is a valid justification for not paying all the taxes demanded of us because you admit that our existing government goes far beyond its proper bounds. Even under your own theory, the most that government has the right to demand from us and that we ought to rationally approve are the expenses necessary to operate a proper government. Therefore those who refuse to contribute their full share of taxes are justified in their partial tax refusal. Thus a person who pays enough of his taxes to cover his share of the expenses of a proper government is justified in not paying any more than this. Of course, no government I know of is willing to allow this.
Religious dissenters of the 18th and 19th Centuries were faced with the question of contributing taxes to State churches. Many a nonconformist was placed in jail or had his property distrained for failing to pay church rates. At first many people believed that State churches were just as much a necessity as proper government. However, after a great deal of struggle, most people in this country eventually came to the conclusion that churches ought to be voluntarily supported. We haven’t reached that point yet with respect to proper government, but the analogy between tax-supported churches and coercively supported government is very a propos. I am enclosing an article that I wrote a number of years ago about this parallel.
I would welcome your further comments.

Sincerely,
Carl Watner


November 20, 1999

Dear Professor Budziszewski:
Thanks for acknowledging my letter of November 12th, in which you briefly point out that the primary question involves “the proper meaning of theft,” and that it is “unrealistic” to expect “voluntary obedience to proper authority” (which I interpret to mean that you wouldn’t expect people to voluntarily pay their taxes). I understand that you are busy with other obligations and that a lengthy correspondence may be futile (I’ve had a few of those in my time!).
Nevertheless, I’d like to give you some more food for thought – without any expectation of a reply.
First – as regards the definition of theft: I am sure that you would agree that the actions of a criminal gang in extorting money may be classed as a form of theft (the taking of rightful property without the voluntary consent of the owner). And the actions of a legitimate government involve extorting money from the taxpayers (pay your taxes or have the money confiscated and/or go to jail!). Now the same actions cannot be a form of theft in one case and not a form of theft in the other, unless 1) you allege the taxpayer does not rightfully own the portion of his property the government is taking; 2) you allege the government has a prior claim to part of the taxpayer’s property; or 3) you change the definition of theft (when the government does something that would ordinarily be described as theft, you define it as taxation – therefore it is not theft). Unless you see all property rights as stemming from the State (therefore the State does not need the taxpayer’s consent to take its property back; [on the contrary, I see property rights as flowing from the self-ownership each person has in his or her self]), there is no basis for saying the taxpayer does not “own” all his property or that the State has a rightful claim to part of it. If the citizen “owns” all his property (which means he must voluntarily consent to yielding it up), then we are faced with the pons asinorum of political philosophy: “What distinguishes the edicts of the State from the commands of a bandit gang?” and “How can you define taxation in a way which makes it different from robbery?” As to the third case, I don’t think maintaining a double standard (having one standard for the individual and another for the State) is an honest way to solve the problem. The stealing commandment leaves no room for relativistic definitions.
Second – regarding the morality and practicality of taxation versus voluntary payment for services: Your discussion of expropriationism (pp. 91-92) in The Revenge of the Conscience led me to believe that you thought the moral arguments for obeying the stealing commandment were superior to any practical justifications. In other words, just because we cannot visualize how a thief or a government might survive if they were forced to honor the stealing commandment, there is no warrant for them to steal or to continue to steal. It is my belief that the moral and the practical normally go hand in hand. We can all live the best life possible if we do not steal, but the justification for not stealing is not that we can live a better life, but rather that we are honoring the stealing commandment and respecting other people’s property rights (property rights in themselves and in the things around them that they have come to own). Therefore, there is no justification for allowing the government to steal (tax) from us because we cannot see how the government would survive without the power of coercion to collect the tax. Historically, every service ever provided by government has been produced on the open market. Just because we need essential services, like schools, religious institutions, protection from criminals, food, and shelter, is no reason that the government must monopolistically and coercively provide them for us. I don’t see why it is unrealistic to expect government to survive by voluntarily collecting fees in return for the services it provides us – if we want them. That is how each and every non-criminal in society survives. Why should the institution of government be any different?
Enough said! I hope this discussion sticks with you as you think about and teach political philosophy. If you ever would like to re-open our correspondence, please do so. The article that I sent you about Church-State taxation was from a small bi-monthly newsletter that I have been editing for the last decade and a half. It is titled The Voluntaryist. I’d be happy to furnish you with a complimentary subscription at any time.

Sincerely,
Carl Watner

Homeschooling a Hope for America Book


 

Google
WWW Voluntaryist.com

 

HOMESCHOOLING A HOPE FOR AMERICA is a collection of articles taken from The Voluntaryist, a newsletter with a libertarian outlook which has been published since 1982. The anthology has been assembled by Carl Watner (from many of his past articles, as well as those of others), and contains an original Foreword by John Taylor Gatto.

This anthology argues against government education in a unique way. One who advocates voluntaryism opposes government schools, not because he opposes schooling but, because he opposes coercion, which is to be found in government taxation, compulsory attendance laws, and in the monopolization of public services. Most of us would agree that there should not be any state religion; that religion should not be supported by taxation; and that people should not be compelled to attend religious services. Why shouldn’t the principles of voluntaryism in religion apply to education?

All government depends on the cooperation and/or tacit consent of the majority of its citizens. When the state could no longer use government churches to legitimize its rule of the divine right of kings, some other institution had to be found that would induce consent among the masses. Government schools became the chosen instrument to produce good citizens for the state. Indoctrinate the young: then they will support the state for the rest of their lives.

America is at a cross roads of cultural and economic disintegration, yet voluntaryists believe that there is hope. It is to be found in home schooling. Rather than cursing the darkness, parents can light one small candle of wisdom and learning and pass it along to the next generation. “Ages of experience testify that the only way society can be improved is by the individualist method; … that is, the method of each one doing his best to improve one.” This is the quiet or patient way of changing society because it concentrates upon bettering the character of men and women as individuals. As the individual units change, the improvement in society will take care of itself. In other words, if one takes care of the means, the end will take care of itself.

Ordering Information –
Softcover, 247 pages. (**) postpaid to US addresses.
( (**) if outside the US).

Mail Federal Reserve notes, stamps, gold, or silver, but please No checks or money orders to:

The Voluntaryist
39520 Murrieta Hot Springs Rd.
219-69
Murrieta, CA  92563

Or you can send bitcoins to 1N9chGG4Dpp8Lw1eDye9wjiskAVqaiCi2Y, which you can click to email us your address.

To read Carl’s Introduction, “What Might Have Been – What Might Be,” to the anthology, click here.

I Must Speak Out Table of Contents


(articles are by Carl Watner unless otherwise attributed)

xi. Why I Write and Publish The Voluntaryist

Part I: Statement of Purpose
3. What We Are For?–What Do We Believe?
4. What Is Our Plan?
7. The Fundamentals of Voluntaryism
11. Cultivate Your Own Garden: No Truck with Politics
14. From the Editor: “Like a Voice Crying in the Wilderness”–A Restatement of Purpose
18. What We Believe and Why

Part II: Voluntaryist Critiques of the State
25. The Ethics of Voting , by George H. Smith
33. “If This Be Treason, Make the Most of It!”
35. The Myth of Political Freedom
37. The Case against Democracy: The More Things Change, the More They Remain the Same
41. Notes on War and Freedom, by Ramsey Clark
42. A Note to the Commissioner, by Anonymous
44. The Tragedy of Political Government
47. “Will Rothbards Free-Market Justice Suffice?”, by Murray Rothbard
49. On Keeping Your Own: Taxation Is Theft!
50. Who Are the Realists?, by Roy Halliday

Part III: Voluntaryist Strategies
55. Neither Bullets Nor Ballots, by Wendy McElroy
57. Methods, by Francis Tandy
61. Living Slavery and All That, by Alan P. Koontz
63. The Voluntaryist Insight: from “The Political Thought of Etienne de la Boetie,” by Murray N. Rothbard
69. The Power of Non-Violent Resistance, by Jerry M. Tinker
78. How Can We Do It?, by Robert LeFevre
82. A Way Out–Victory without Violence
83. Freedom Works Both Ways, by Dean Russell
85. Persuasion versus Force, by Mark Skousen
91. The Illegality, Immorality, and Violence of All Political Action, by Robert LeFevre
95. Thoughts on Nonviolence, by Karl Meyer
97. A Visit to Rhinegold, by Harry Browne
109. An Open Letter to Harry Browne from John Pugsley
122. Election Day: A Means of State Control, by Robert Weissberg
127. Consent, Obligation, and Anarchy, by A. John Simmons

Part IV: Voluntaryism as a Matter of Integrity and Conscience
139. The Decision Is Always Yours–Freedom as Self-Control
146. A Further Note on `Freedom as Self-Control`
147. To Thine Own Self Be True: The Story of Raymond Cyrus Hoiles and His Freedom Newspapers
159. The Case against T-Bills: And Other Thoughts on Theft, by John A. Pugsley
165. “I Dont Want Nothing from Him!”
167. The Day the World Was Lost, by Milton Mayer
171. “Voluntary” Contributions to the National Treasury: Where Does One Draw the Line?
176. “Drawing the Line,” by Blair Adams
177. Why Homeschool? Excerpts from Correspondence between Helen Hegener and Carl Watner
181. This Far: No More!, by Anonymous
183. A Definition of Freedom, by Julie Watner
184. “Vices Are Not Crimes”: Defending Defending the Undefendable
186. Libertarianism and Libertinism, by Walter Block
197. The Cunning of Governments and the Contributions of Citizens, by Fred E. Katz

200. Participation and the Lie, by Alexander Solzhenitsyn
202. Why I Refuse to Register (to Vote or Pay Taxes), by Anonymous

Part V: Voluntaryism vs. the American Government
207. A Plague on Both Your Houses
219. To All Patriots and Constitutionalists: Some Critical Considerations on the United States Constitution

223. Propaganda, American-Style, by Noam Chomsky
225. An Octopus Would Sooner Release Its Prey: Voluntaryism vs. Educational Statism
234. Who Controls the Children?
246. A Declaration of Personal Indepenence, by a Friend of Paine
250. Major Crimes of the United States Government: 1776-1993
264. “By Their Fruits Ye Shall Know Them”: Voluntaryism and the Old Order Amish
281. “Sweat Them at Law with Their Own Money”: Forfeitures and Taxes in American History
291. Whose Property Is It Anyway?
295. Is “Taxation Is Theft” A Seditious Statement?: A Short History of Governmental Criticism in the Early United States
306. “The Illusion Is Liberty–the Reality Is Leviathan”: A Voluntaryist Perspective on the Bill of Rights

Part VI: Voluntaryism in History
319. The Noiseless Revolution
326. “Health” Freedoms in the Libertarian Tradition
332. “Hard Money” in the Voluntaryist Tradition
343. Thinkers and Groups of Individuals Who Have Contributed Significant Ideas or Major Written Materials to the Radical Libertarian Tradition
349. “And Every Man Did What Was Right in His Own Eyes”: Voluntaryism in the Old Testament
355. Libraries in the Voluntaryist Tradition
359. Voluntaryism on the Western Frontier
366. Voluntaryism and the English Language
377. Weights and Measures: State or Market?
381. Voluntaryism and the Evolution of Industrial Standards

394. “One of Our Most Human Experiences”: Voluntaryism, Marriage, and the Family
405. “For Conscience`s Sake”: Voluntaryism and Religious Freedom
414. The Most Generous Nation on Earth: Voluntaryism and American Philanthropy
428. “Plunderers of the Public Revenue”: Voluntaryism and the Mails
442. “Beyond the Wit of Man to Foresee”: Voluntaryism and Land Use Controls
457. “Stateless, Not Lawless”: Voluntaryism and Arbitration
474. The Road to Hell Is Paved with Good Intentions: Voluntaryism and the Roads

National Identification Systems: Essays in Opposition – TOC


The long awaited book!

“This is more than a book about national ID. It is about all forms of government enumeration, from the census of antiquity, to government naming practices, fingerprinting, social security numbers, and drivers licenses, to cutting-edge biometric technologies such as DNA, iris scans, or subcutaneous microchips capable of allowing those in charge to know where we are twenty-four hours a day via global positioning satellites. This book looks at the big picture of national ID: what it is, how it has developed, and how it might potentially change our society. It is also about those who have chosen to resist or oppose national ID schemes – from Gandhi’s satyagraha campaign in South Africa in 1906 to those Americans who refuse to be counted or carry a government number. These “Essays in Opposition” are intended to honor those whose consciences and principles do not allow them to “roll over and acquiesce.”…

“Never before has there been a book devoted to the idea [of proving] that the logical outcome of government involvement in these areas (from government birth certificates to governmental databases and surveillance) is a 1984-style population control. That is why national ID systems have been called a ‘trademark of totalitarianism.”

—From “The Preface”

Table of Contents:

Carl Watner, Preface

Section I: History of government ID and citizen-tracking

      1. Jeremy Bentham & Luis Reyna Almandos, Men Ahead of Their Times
      2. James C. Scott, John Tehranian, and Jeremy Mathias, Government Surnames and Legal Identities
      3. Jim Fussell, Genocide and Group Classification on National ID Cards
      4. Carl Watner,The Compulsory Birth & Death Certificate in the United States
      5. Pamela Sankar, A National Fingerprint System for the United States
      6. Carl Watner, Drivers Licenses and Vehicle Registration in Historical Perspective
      7. Nicolas Werth, The Russian Card: The Propiska

cd

    1. Bob Moore, Population Registers in the Netherlands During World War II
    2. C. H. Rolph, The English Identity Card
    3. Carl Watner, A History of the Census

Section II: Contemporary Issues

    1. Charlotte Twight, Systematic Surveillance of Ordinary Americans
    2. Claire Wolfe, National ID: Our Line in the Sand
    3. Simon Davies, The Australia Card: Campaign of Opposition
    4. Robert Ellis Smith, The Social Security Number in America: 1935 – 2000
    5. Gregory Dicum, My National I.D. Card Is A Threat To Your Civil Liberties
    6. Hans Sherrer, How Computers Are A Menace to Liberty
    7. Carl Watner, Why I Oppose Government Enumeration

Section III: The Future and Resistance

  1. Calvin Kytle, Gandhi’s Story in South Africa
  2. Rose Wilder Lane, Give Me Liberty
  3. Scott McDonald, Resist Enumeration
  4. Patricia Neill, National I.D. for All Public Servants
  5. Claire Wolfe, An American Refusenik
  6. Blood Donor K, Red Tape
  7. Anonymous, Why I Refuse to Be Numbered
  8. Carl Watner, Slavery and National ID
  9. Sunni Maravillosa, ID Without Big Brother
  10. Claire Wolfe & Aaron Zelman, Epilogue: National ID and the Police State
  11. Carl Watner, For Further Reading

Now Available

National Identification Systems: Essays in Opposition
Edited by Carl Watner with Wendy McElroy; 308 pages, paperback.
(**) postpaid to US addresses. ( (**) if outside the US)

To pay for your order without Paypal, you may also submit a request and payment (Federal Reserve notes, stamps, gold, or silver, but please No checks or money orders) to the address below.

The Voluntaryist
39520 Murrieta Hot Springs Rd.
219-69
Murrieta, CA  92563

Or you can send bitcoins to 1N9chGG4Dpp8Lw1eDye9wjiskAVqaiCi2Y, which you can click to email us your address.

An Open Letter on Taxation to the Global Ethic Foundation


from Carl Watner

January 18, 2009

Doctor Hans Kung

Global Ethic Foundation

Waldhauser Strasse 23

72076 Tubingen

Germany

(email: office@weltethos.org)

Dear Doctor Hans Kung:

Re: Hans Kung and Karl-Josef Kuschel (eds.), A GLOBAL ETHIC: The Declaration of the Parliament of the World’s Religions, New York: Continuum, 1993.

I recently read your book and was glad to see its emphasis on non-violence, the Golden Rule, and the “fundamental demand [that] every human being must be treated humanely.” [p. 21] This includes the prohibitions that a person should not kill or steal. “Or in positive terms: Have respect for life!” [p. 25]

The purpose of this letter is to ask: How do you reconcile the directives of the Global Ethic with the institution of government, which relies on or resorts to force to collect its taxes?

As you realize all governments, whether democratic or totalitarian, collect at least part of their revenues coercively. Taxes are collected under the threat of the citizen going to jail, having his property confiscated, or both, if he or she does not pay the government the amount it claims is owed.

I hope that we both would agree that a robber is violating the global ethic when he steals from or kills a person in order to take their property. The purpose for which he intends to use the stolen property in no way affects how we judge the violence. It matters not whether he intends to use the stolen property for charitable purposes or for his personal use. Killing and/or stealing are wrong.

Question 1: Are not the actions of agents of the government violent in the same manner as that of the robber?

Question 2: Is not the Golden Rule applicable to this situation? Would not the agents of government prefer not to be robbed or killed themselves?

Question 3: Are not the agents of the government acting violently when they threaten and/or coerce the reluctant citizen? Are they not acting inhumanely toward the citizens?

Question 4: Is there not a humane way to collect money for the government? Is it not possible to remonstrate peacefully with the refuseniks: to explain to them the importance of paying taxes? Is it not possible to cut off some or all government services to those who will not pay their taxes? And in the very worst case, that they still insist on not paying, is it not possible that those who do see the importance of funding governments, dig deeper into their own pockets to make up the difference?

Question 5: Is there any possible justification for stealing, killing, or treating citizens inhumanely who refuse to pay their tax?

Question 6: Does not the government’s resort to violence in collecting taxes set a bad example, which some individuals in society might think is right to follow?

I have addressed these questions to family, friends, religious leaders, and have found that they generally apply a double standard to the actions of government agents despite the fact that the “Four irrevocable directives” of the Global Ethic apply to everyone equally. As Richard Maybury, in his book, WHATEVER HAPPENED TO JUSTICE?, explains: “This is what is meant by those five words in the (United States) Declaration of Independence ‘all men are created equal.’ No one gets any special privileges or exemptions from (these directives).” [p. 22] As you wrote in A GLOBAL ETHIC, “No one,” whether a citizen or government agent, “has the right” to “physically … injure, much less kill, any other human being.” [p. 25]

I wonder if you or one of your colleagues at the Global Ethic Foundation could discuss these questions relating to the conduct of government and its agents.

Sincerely,

Carl Watner

Box 275

Gramling, South Carolina 29348

U.S.A.

 

Introduction – Taxes No Better Than Slavery


by Carl Watner

 

 

 

[The following is the Introduction to the book Render Not. More information can be found here. It is available for purchase here.]

Slavery is wrong.
Taxation is a form of slavery.
Therefore taxation is wrong.
The implications that follow from this syllogism are the subject of this book.

Slavery is wrong. A slave is a person who is the property of another or others, such that whatever the slave produces can be taken by force or the threat of force.[1] The slave has no right of self-ownership, and those who exercise dominion over the slave always have the legal right to use coercion against him, but certainly have no natural right to do so. He who takes the life, liberty, or property of another without that other’s consent is stealing; and as the early abolitionist described it, man-stealing is just as wrong, if not worse, than property-stealing, because human beings hold a higher rank in existence than inert property matter.

Taxation is a form of slavery. A tax is a compulsory levy on a person subject to the jurisdiction of a government. Anyone who is taxed is a slave because his or her earnings and property are forcibly taken to support the State. Most individuals do not consent to taxation. Historically, the Romance languages, such as French, Spanish, and Italian, have tried to make the tax-payer “feel good” by euphemistically calling him a “contributor”.[2] “Customers” is the term that our own Internal Revenue Service uses to identify those from whom it extracts payments, using threats of force or actual force in some instances.

Therefore taxation is wrong. As Auberon Herbert, one of the contributors to this volume, pointed out decades before the passage of the 16th Amendment to the U.S. Constitution (on the basis of which Congress legislated a federal income tax): truth and consistency demand that if the State may forcibly take one dollar “out of what a man owns, it may take what it likes up to the last dollar … . Once admit the right of the [S]tate to take, and the [S]tate becomes the real owner of all property.” To those who wish to debate this point, I only ask: where in the federal Constitution is there any limitation on the amount that Congress may try to take from us?[3]

But, as Charles Adams, one historian of taxation, has observed: “without revenue, governments would collapse, society as we know it would disappear, and chaos would follow.”[4]

True: coercive political governments which depend on violence to sustain themselves with police and armed force would disappear. Yes, society as we know it today in the United States would change.

But would chaos follow? Not necessarily. If the opponents of taxation used revolutionary violence to abolish the State, then there would undoubtedly be some who would fight for the re-establishment of taxation But if taxation were to be abandoned as a result of a shift in pubic opinion and understanding, then, in the words of Murray Rothbard, we would simply achieve a peaceful “society without a state.” As Thomas Paine explained centuries ago: A “[g]reat part of that order which reigns among mankind is not the effect of Government. It has its origins in the principles of society and the natural constitution of man. It existed prior to Government, and would exist if the formality of Government” no longer existed.[5]

All history attests to the fact that if a service supplied by government is truly wanted, a voluntary way will be found to provide it. It may cost some people more than when the government supplied it; but the point is that if a true demand exists, some entrepreneur or some group of individuals will associate cooperatively to provide it. Any number of examples can be used to illustrate this point: Did religion disappear when churches lost their government support? Did people go without coined money when there were no government mints? Did people go shoeless because there were no government factories to produce footwear?

A number of contributors to Section VI of this anthology attempt to answer the question, “How would a society of individuals function without taxes?” But perhaps the even more important question is, “Does our governmentally-directed society based on coercive taxation really work all that well?” If we were to start out de novo would we actually entrust all our protective and defensive services to the members of one organization, and empower them to collect their revenues at the point of a gun? What kind of service could we expect from a monopoly that had no competition and a guaranteed income? Who would protect us from our guardians if they turned venal? Who would guard the guardians? Voluntary, consensual arrangements are always more flexible and less predictable than those imposed by coercive governments, which always perceive change as a threat to their dominance and sovereignty.[6]

Government taxation is a coercive activity that introduces force and violence into otherwise peaceful relationships. That is our primary reason for opposing taxation. It pits one man against another; one group against another group; upsets the natural market incentives that produce the greatest benefits for all. Although it is true that many who oppose taxation believe that a voluntary system will lead to a spectacular standard of living for the masses, that is not the reason for the opposition that inspires this book. We believe it is morally proper that a man keep the product of his labor; that he not be enslaved. If it is wrong for a slave owner to enslave a single person, then it is wrong for a group of individuals to do so. Majority rule cannot legitimize slavery or taxation. As R. C. Hoiles, founder of the Freedom Newspapers, was always keen to point out, there is only one standard of right and wrong, and that standard applies to the lone individual, to members of a group, and to the employees of the State.[7]

Conscientious objectors to taxation recognize that some goods and services are essential to human survival, but also realize they need not be provided by the government on a coercive basis. What we oppose is the coercion involved in collecting taxes. We oppose the means and take the position that the ends never justifies the means. Our opposition to taxation doesn’t concern itself with whether too much money is being collected, or whether that money is being spent wastefully. Rather, the focus is on the fact that any amount of money forcefully collected is stealing. It is no more proper for government agents to seize property than it is for you to rob your neighbor at gunpoint, even if you spend the money on something that you think will benefit your neighbor.

If some in our society think that certain government services are necessary, then let them collect the revenues to support those services in a voluntary fashion. We who oppose taxation may or may not support their efforts. It would soon be revealed which services are sufficiently desired. And if the people collecting the money to support these services do not, in their judgment, collect enough, then let them dig into their own pockets to make up the deficiency or do without. They do not have the right to spend other people’s money.

The articles in this anthology have been chosen because they discuss the historical, political, and philosophical relationships between taxation, slavery, and stealing. Robert Ringer, in his opening essay, describes taxation as a disgrace to the human race because it is a “violation of property rights, which means a violation of human rights.” He points out that he is not only opposed to the income tax, but to all the “subtle” and hidden taxes that politicians on every level of government have enacted. He further alludes to the tremendous amount of “stolen” time that taxpayers surrender as they fill out their tax returns and compute the amount of taxes they owe. Harry Reid describes these activities as “voluntary” because everyone (or everyone’s accountant) figures out the extent of his or her own tax liability. The interview with the Senator has been included because it demonstrates the gross absurdity of calling taxes, especially the federal income tax, a consensual activity. It only appears so because the American taxpayers are so brainwashed that most of them no longer perceive the government as a violent threat, but rather view it as an unending source of welfare benefits that someone else pays for.

Two articles by an anonymous author illustrate the inherent dangers in criticizing government authorities. If you were Commissioner of the Internal Revenue Service and received a letter from a disgruntled citizen comparing your organization to the Mafia wouldn’t you investigate that critic to make sure he or she was paying his or her taxes? The fact is that the United States government has prosecuted and imprisoned those who question the constitutionality of its unapportioned taxation of income. In my own article, “Is ‘Taxation Is Theft’ A Seditious Statement?,” I point out that judges in the federal courts have gone so far as to prevent defendants (alleged tax protesters) from presenting their constitutional arguments against income taxation. But as is apparent here, the U.S. Constitution has no special moral authority to convert taxation into non-theft. For those of our authors who embrace taxation as theft and slavery, Anonymous summarizes their opposition by writing: “I am going back to ‘the old, traditional standards of religion, ethics, common law,’ and common sense. I am refusing to act in a way that produces or contributes to evil.”

What you will not find here is the call for “tax reduction” or for declaring the federal income tax laws “unconstitutional.” The closest we come to that is Vivien Kellems’ chapter in which she attacks the federal withholding system as being “illegal, immoral, and unconstitutional” because it is not her responsibility, as an employer, to discharge the income tax liability of her employees by making deductions from their pay. Instead, you will find a moral clarity exuded by many of our authors. For example, Frank Chodorov declares that “taxation is robbery” and that no amount of verbiage “can make it anything else.” In conclusion, he notes that there can neither be a “good tax nor a just one” because “every tax rests its case on compulsion.” Mark Crovelli tackles the Catechism of the Catholic Church and writes that “theft is theft – even if the State does it.” His purpose is to harken back to the unadorned language of the 7th commandment that “offers a straightforward condemnation of the taking of other people’s property without their consent.” As he notes, the commandment “does not offer exceptions, such as “You shall not steal unless you are a government employee.”

Some of the contributors to this volume label themselves pacifists and war tax resisters. In Michael Benedetto’s essay on “The Origins of Conscientious Tax Objection” we find a review of the religious objections to war taxes. Juanita Nelson, author of “A Matter of Freedom,” (reprinted here) and her husband, Wally, began their tax resistance in 1949, but it was not until June 16, 1959 that Juanita “became the first woman in modern times to be apprehended by the federal government for opposition to war and war preparation.” Although she was eventually released, the government filed tax liens against her and in 1973, agents from the Internal Revenue Service attempted to seize two vehicles that she and her husband had parked at their home in New Mexico. “Each of them sat in front of a vehicle, and the agents finally left.”[8] Ammon Hennacy, another one of our contributors, was imprisoned during World War I for his refusal to be conscripted. Out of this experience, he became a Catholic, an anarchist, and a tax refuser. He, the Nelsons, and other war tax resisters certainly earn my greatest respect for having the courage and consistency to stick to their beliefs – even when the State has used force against them. Yet, to them and all other war tax resisters, I ask: What about excise taxes, real estate taxes, personal property taxes, use taxes, inheritance and estate taxes, social security taxes, and sales taxes? Are they not wrong, too? Do these taxes not go to support government? Are not all activities of government ultimately dependent on force, violence, and threats? Why limit your opposition to government wars and their funding? Are not the actions of the U.S. government in controlling its citizens in its own domestic venue similar in nature to its military operations abroad since both are predicated on the exercise of coercion?

Randolph Bourne, an early 20th Century intellectual, once observed that “war is the health of the state.”[9] Compulsion is its backbone; taxes are its lifeblood. The ultimate basis of State power is coercive taxation.[10] As Lysander Spooner pointed out in his essay, “Taxation,” (reprinted here) written before the United States Civil War, with money a government can hire armed men to plunder and punish those of its citizens who do not obey. The underlying premise of government taxation is that you and your property belong to the State.[11] Whatever you are allowed to keep is due to its generosity, and if you resist and want to keep more of your own property, you will be fined, jailed for contempt of court, or killed resisting arrest. Taxation is nothing but a polite euphemism for stealing – legitimized by the overpowering strength of the State. Thus it becomes our duty as individuals, and as inhabitants of the earth, to speak out – to make known our views about taxation. Regardless of how much or how little tax we pay, we can say: taxes are wrong.

We agree with the Jewish Zealot, Judas of Gamala, who over two thousand years ago said that the census tax imposed by the Roman occupiers of Palestine in 6 A.D. “was no better than introduction to slavery.”[12] Would Jesus Christ have agreed with the Jewish Zealots? When faced with the question, “Is it lawful for us to give tribute to Caesar, or not?” Christ refused to answer directly. Instead he said, “Show me a coin. Whose likeness and inscription has it?” “Caesar’s,” they replied. It was then that he exclaimed the famous lines: “Then render to Caesar the things that are Caesar’s, and to God the things that are God’s.” Render not unto Caesar is the conclusion of this book – for as Dorothy Day is reputed to have once said, “If we render unto God all the things that belong to God, there would be nothing left for Caesar.”[13]

One of the main purposes of this book is to encourage people to look at an old situation in a new way. Until individuals could recognize that there was a practical alternative to slavery, it was difficult for them to see slavery as the moral atrocity it was. To speak of doing away with taxation, today, brings forth the same reactions and reasons that Robert Higgs describes in one of the concluding chapters of this book. The defenders of slavery could not visualize how civilization, how law and order, could be maintained without slaves, and yet, society and civilization have survived. It is our position that taxation is just as abominable, as unjust, and as unnecessary as slavery. There are many voluntary ways to solve societal problems if only people would begin to free their minds from the constraints of government indoctrination and propaganda. Only a free mind is able to recognize the truth. Paraphrasing Alexander Solzhenitsyn, only a free mind is able to take that courageous step, and refuse to take part in falsehood. Only a free mind can recognize that “one word of truth outweighs the world.”[14]

End Notes

[1] Lesley Brown, (ed.), The New Shorter Oxford English Dictionary, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1993, See “slave,” Vol. II, p. 2893.

[2] Mario Pei, Double-Speak In America, New York: Hawthorn Books, Inc., 1973, p. 96.

[3] Auberon Herbert, “Some Reasons Why Voluntaryists Object To Compulsory Taxation In All Its Forms,” Section 27 (reprinted here). Even if there were such a limitation in the federal Constitution, of what value would it be? First and foremost, how can the Constitution possibly legitimize stealing and/or slavery? Second, and of lesser importance, what would prevent such a limitation from being amended, repealed, or ignored?

[4] Charles Adams, For Good and Evil: The Impact of Taxes on the Course of History, Lanham, Madison Books, 1993, pp. 1-2.

[5] See Murray Rothbard, “Society Without a State,” The Libertarian Forum, Volume 7, No. 1, January 1975, online at http://mises.org/daily/2429, and see Thomas Paine, Rights of Man (1792), Ch. 1, Bk. 2.

[6] Rothbard, op. cit. For historical examples of voluntaryism, see Carl Watner (ed.), I Must Speak Out: The Best of The Voluntaryist, 1982-1999, San Francisco: Fox & Wilkes, 1999.

[7] See Carl Watner, “To Thine Own Self Be True: The Story of Raymond Cyrus Hoiles and His Freedom Newspapers,” in Watner, op. cit., pp. 151-152. Originally printed in The Voluntaryist, Whole No. 18, May 1986.

[8] Ed Hedemann and Ruth Benn (eds.), War Tax Resistance: A Guide to Withholding Your Support from the Military, New York: War Resisters League, Fifth Edition, 2003, p. 96.

[9] Lillian Schlissel, The World of Randolph Bourne, New York: E. P. Dutton, 1963, pp. 246-250, and pp. 259-271. Excerpts reprinted in The Voluntaryist, Whole No. 39, August 1989. The fact is: there couldn’t be wars without taxation.

[10] David Beito, Taxpayers in Revolt, Chapel Hill: The University of North Carolina Press, 1989, p. 127.

[11] Anonymous, “Why I Refuse To Be Numbered,” The Voluntaryist, Whole No. 116, 1st Quarter, 2003, p. 1, 4th paragraph.

[12] Flavius Josephus, Selections from His Works, with an Introduction and Notes by Abraham Wasserstein, New York: The Viking Press, 1974, p. 179 (from The Antiquities of the Jews. Cited on the internet as Jewish Antiquities, 18.4-6). This description of the Roman tax is attributed by Josephus to Judas of Gamala (otherwise known as Judas the Galilean), the reputed founder of the Zealots who revolted against the institution of the poll tax by the Romans in 6 A.D. in Palestine. He is to be distinguished from the better known Judas Iscariot, one of the twelve apostles and the betrayer of Jesus.

[13] See the New Testament, Luke 20: 22-25 and Jeffrey F. Barr, “Render Unto Caesar: A Most Misunderstood New Testament Passage,” Posted on www.lewrockwell.com, March 17, 2010.

[14] I would like to thank Ned Netterville and Spencer and Emi MacCallum for their critical reading and suggestions on how to improve this introduction.

Was Lysander Spooner Mistaken?


 

by Carl Watner

In his short essay on “Taxation,” which was printed as the “Appendix” to his 1852 ESSAY ON THE TRIAL BY JURY, Lysander Spooner wrote

It was a principle of the Common Law … that no man can be taxed without his personal consent. The Common Law knew nothing of that system, which now prevails in England, of assuming a man’s own consent to be taxed, because some pretended representative, whom he never authorized to act for him, has taken it upon himself to consent that he may be taxed. That is one of the many frauds on the Common Law, and the English constitution, which have been introduced since Magna Carta. [p. 222]

The veracity of Spooner’s assertion that under the Common Law taxation requires individual consent came into question upon my reading of J. P. Sommerville’s book, POLITICS AND IDEOLOGY IN ENGLAND 1603-1640. At one point, Sommerville appears to agree with Spooner, for he writes

In the early seventeenth century … [t]o say that something was a man’s property, – or and this was by far the commoner usage – that he had property in something, was precisely to say that the thing in question could not be taken from him without his consent. To take property without consent was to steal, and thus to break the Eighth Commandment. [Chapter 5, Paragraph 6, p. 147]

In correspondence with Professor Sommervile, I asked him if it was his opinion that Englishmen of the 17th Century considered taxation without personal consent to be stealing. He replied

The usual argument in that period was that parliament (and especially the House of Commons) represent[ed] everyone in the country and that the consent of parliament therefore includes the consent of every individual. What parliament does, people said, was done by “common consent.” Laws (including laws instituting taxes) bound individuals even if they had not explicitly consented to them, because they had virtually consented through parliament.

It was clearly recognized in Section X of the Petition of Right (1628) “that … no man be compelled to make or yield any gift, loan, benevolence, tax, or such like charge, without common consent by act of parliament; … .” According to Professor Sommerville “The Petition outlawed benevolences, which were (theoretically) free gifts granted to the monarch by individuals, because monarchs can easily coerce (or persuade, or encourage) individuals to hand over cash. The Petition therefore said that even if an individual consents to giving the monarch money, the gift is illegal unless it has parliamentary endorsement.”

So accepting Professor Sommerville’s argument on face value, parliament was supreme. It could approve taxes even though not consented to by an individual; and it could annul a benevolence even though an individual had granted it.

Although Spooner offers no historical evidence to buttress his case, there is some modicum of support to be found in STUDIES IN MEDIEVAL TAXATION UNDER JOHN AND HENRY III (1914). As Sydney Knox Mitchell observed, “The source of modern taxation was the feudal aid, the voluntary contribution which the vassal made to relieve the wants of his lord.” [p. 346] However, this statement is followed by the acknowledgement that “There were certain aids which were not voluntary, but which were fixed by feudal law.” According to Chapter 12 of Magna Carta, these three payments were for ransom of the king, financial support in making the king’s eldest son a knight, and payments toward marrying the king’s eldest daughter. Such scutages were not dependent on individual consent, but rather on the “general consent” of the kingdom.

If as historians we accept THE NEW SHORTER OXFORD ENGLISH DICTIONARY definition of common law, which is “the part of English law … not fully prescribed by statute, purporting instead to be derived from ancient usage and judicial decisions,” then I think it is safe to conclude that Spooner was mistaken: it was not a principle of the English constitution or the Common Law “that no man can be taxed without his personal consent.” Yet, as voluntaryists we can agree with Spooner’s conclusion that if a “government can take a man’s money without his consent, [then] there is no limit to the additional tyranny it may practice upon him; for, with his money, it can hire soldiers to stand over him, keep him in subjection, plunder him at discretion, and kill him if he resists. And governments will always do this, as they everywhere and always have done … .” [“Appendix,” p. 222]

The proof is in the pudding. Taxation is robbery any way you consider it: without consent it is clearly stealing. On the other hand, would anyone ever ‘consent’ to taxation? Who would enter into an agreement whereby he or she in effect writes a blank check to be cashed by whomever has the most votes? Who would agree to an open-ended obligation to be determined by a legislative majority? Such an arrangement would effectively dispossess the taxpayers of any and all rights to their property since there would be no limit to how much tax could be assessed. If Spooner were here today and experienced taxation as we know it, he would clearly label it nothing more than sophisticated slavery – at its best – and communism – at its worst.

Appendix to AN ESSAY ON THE TRIAL BY JURY (1852)


 

“Taxation”

Lysander Spooner

 

It was a principle of the Common Law, as it is of the law of nature, and of common sense, that no man can be taxed without his personal consent. The Common Law knew nothing of that system, which now prevails in England, of assuming a man’s own consent to be taxed, because some pretended representative, whom he never authorized to act for him, has taken it upon himself to consent that he may be taxed. That is one of the many frauds on the Common Law, and the English constitution, which have been introduced since Magna Carta. Having finally established itself in England, it has been stupidly and servilely copied and submitted to in the United States.

If the trial by jury were re-established, the Common Law principle of taxation would be re-established with it; for it is not to be supposed that juries would enforce a tax upon an individual which he had never agreed to pay. Taxation without consent is as plainly robbery, when enforced against one man, as when enforced against millions; and it is not to be imagined that juries could be blind to so self-evident a principle. Taking a man’s money without his consent, is also as much robbery, when it is done by millions of men, acting in concert, and calling themselves a government, as when it is done by a single individual, acting on his own responsibility, and calling himself a highwayman. Neither the numbers engaged in the act, nor the different characters they assume as a cover for the act, alter the nature of the act itself.

If the government can take a man’s money without his consent, there is no limit to the additional tyranny it may practice upon him; for, with his money, it can hire soldiers to stand over him, keep him in subjection, plunder him at discretion, and kill him if he resists. And governments always will do this, as they everywhere and always have done it, except where the Common Law principle has been established. It is therefore a first principle, a very sine qua non of political freedom, that a man can be taxed only by his personal consent. And the establishment of this principle, with trial by jury, insures freedom of course; because: 1. No man would pay his money unless he had first contracted for such a government as he was willing to support; and, 2. Unless the government then kept itself within the terms of its contract, juries would not enforce the payment of the tax. Besides, the agreement to be taxed would probably be entered into but for a year at a time. If, in that year, the government proved itself either inefficient or tyrannical, to any serious degree, the contract would not be renewed. The dissatisfied parties, if sufficiently numerous for a new organization, would form themselves into a separate association for mutual protection. If not sufficiently numerous for that purpose, those who were conscientious would forego all governmental protection, rather than contribute to the support of a government which they deemed unjust.

All legitimate government is a mutual insurance company, voluntarily agreed upon by the parties to it, for the protection of their rights against wrong-doers. In its voluntary character it is precisely similar to an association for mutual protection against fire or a shipwreck. Before a man will join an association for these latter purposes, and pay the premium for being insured, he will, if he be a man of sense, look at the articles of the association; see what the company promises to do; what it is likely to do; and what are the rates of insurance. If he be satisfied on all these points, he will become a member, pay his premium for a year, and then hold the company to its contract. If the conduct of the company prove unsatisfactory, he will let his policy expire at the end of the year for which he has paid; will decline to pay any further premiums, and either seek insurance elsewhere, or take his own risk without any insurance. And as men act in the insurance of their ships and dwellings, they would act in the insurance of their properties, liberties and lives, in the political association, or government.

The political insurance company, or government, have no more right, in nature or reason, to assume a man’s consent to be protected by them, and to be taxed for that protection, when he has given no actual consent, than a fire or marine insurance company have to assume a man’s consent to be protected by them, and to pay the premium, when his actual consent has never been given. To take a man’s property without his consent is robbery; and to assume his consent, where no actual consent is given, makes the taking none the less robbery. If it did, the highwayman has the same right to assume a man’s consent to part with his purse, that any other man, or body of men, can have. And his assumption would afford as much moral justification for his robbery as does a like assumption, on the part of the government, for taking a man’s property without his consent. The government’s pretence of protecting him, as an equivalent for the taxation, affords no justification. It is for himself to decide whether he desires such protection as the government offers him. If he do not desire it, or do not bargain for it, the government has no more right than any other insurance company to impose it upon him, or make him pay for it.

Trial by the country, and no taxation without consent, were the two pillars of English liberty, (when England had any liberty,) and the first principles of the Common Law. They mutually sustain each other; and neither can stand without the other. Without both, no people have any guaranty for their freedom; with both, no people can be otherwise than free. [1]

By what force, fraud, and conspiracy, on the part of kings, nobles, and “a few wealthy freeholders,” these pillars have been prostrated in England [as in the rest of the world], it is desired to show more fully in the next volume, if it should be necessary.


[1] Trial by the country, and no taxation without consent, mutually sustain each other, and can be sustained only by each other, for these reasons:

  1. Juries would refuse to enforce a tax against a man who had never agreed to pay it. They would also protect men in forcibly resisting the collection of taxes to which they had never consented. Otherwise the jurors would authorize the government to tax themselves without their consent, a thing which no jury would be likely to do. In these two ways, then, trial by the country would sustain the principle of no taxation without consent.
  2. On the other hand, the principle of no taxation without consent would sustain the trial by the country, because men in general would not consent to be taxed for the support of a government under which trial by the country was not secured.

Thus these two principles mutually sustain each other.But, if either of these principles were broken down, the other would fall with it, and for these reasons: If trial by the country were broken down, the principle of no taxation without consent would fall with it, because the government would then be able to tax the people without their consent, inasmuch as the legal tribunals would be mere tools of the government, and would enforce such taxation, and punish men for resisting such taxation, as the government ordered.

On the other hand, if the principle of no taxation without consent were broken down, trial by the country would fall with it, because the government, if it could tax people without their consent, would, of course, take enough of their money to enable it to employ all the force necessary for sustaining its own tribunals, (in the place of juries,) and carrying their decrees into execution.

On the Ownership of Ideas


 

by Carl Watner

Introduction

In my article (THE VOLUNTARYIST, Whole No. 166) on the historical development of copyright, I explored whether or not copyright protection of an author’s output was the result of the natural evolution of the common law. I concluded that copyright was not a voluntary phenomenon, but rather one brought about in the English-speaking world by government legislation in early 18th Century England. The point of my investigation was to see if there was any historical basis for claiming that intellectual property might be subject to ownership in a voluntaryist society. What I did find to partly buttress the case for ownership was the fact that authors’ moral rights to their intellectual property have existed since antiquity.

As I wrote in the Addendum to my copyright article, there are two opposing ‘camps’ within the libertarian movement with regard to the question of intellectual property (IP) rights. Lysander Spooner (1808-1887) and Andrew Joseph Galambos (1924-1997) represent those who favor the recognition of intellectual property rights, while Benjamin Tucker (1854-1939) and Stephan Kinsella (b. 1965) represent those who claim such rights would not and should not be respected. Those on the Galambos side of the fence advocate a common law system which would recognize and protect perpetual property rights in intellectual property. They reject state-sanctioned copyrights and patents and would reach their goal by voluntary means rather than by government legislation. Protection of intellectual property rights would come “from social pressure (the community’s sense that ideas are property, that it is wrong to steal, and that copying without permission is stealing someone’s property) and then from the private judicial system, which would be restitution-based.”

Since Galambos believed “that there must be protection of intellectual property for there to be a durable [and flourishing] voluntary society,” he proposed a dual program to attain full IP protection. “Innovators would disclose their innovations to a private registration company, and the innovations would then be made available for use … first by a process of negotiated terms and payment amounts, and later by releasing them to wide[r] distribution, with payments for use in amounts set by the users. As a result, ideas would not “be locked away forever.” [1] The amounts of royalty payments to authors, inventors, and their heirs would always be limited by competition from independent innovators (and their heirs), from producers of different, but parallel, products or services, and from competition for the users’ dollars. Competition would work in establishing the price of ideas, just as it does in the pricing of tangibles and land. [2]

Those on the Kinsella side of the fence argue that ideas cannot and should not be owned. They claim that there is no basis in libertarian homesteading theory for protecting or recognizing IP rights because IP is not a scarce, tangible product, and can be used by many people at the same time without conflict. Kinsella also objects to the fact that “a system of property rights in ‘ideal [i.e. intangible] objects’ necessarily requires violation of other individual property rights, e.g., to use one’s own tangible property as one sees fit.” [3]

The catalyst for my original article on copyright was Tom Bell’s book, INTELLECTUAL PRIVILEGE: COYRIGHT, COMMON LAW, AND THE COMMON GOOD (2014), which I received as a review copy in June 2014. A few months later, a subscriber and former Galambos student, Richard Boren and I began a long series of email exchanges on the topic of IP. In fact, Richard prepared a lengthy explanation of the property ideas of Andrew J. Galambos, titled “For Intellectual Property” which is to be posted on the voluntaryist site (www.voluntaryist.com), along with other pro-IP and anti-IP essays. Richard had attended a large number of Galambos’ courses, including V-201, the one devoted to IP. As a result of my correspondence with Richard, I began to better understand Galambos’ point of view on IP. My discussions with Richard also prompted me to re-read Lysander Spooner’s work, THE LAW OF INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY (1855), and allowed me to fulfill the promise I made at the conclusion of my “Addendum,” namely to analyze the arguments for and against the ownership of IP.

After a great deal of thought I came to the conclusion that Spooner and Galambos were correct: people in a truly voluntaryist society would eventually come to recognize property in ideas. How would this come about in the absence of the nation-state? This is difficult to answer since the nation-state has been with us for hundreds of years, but the same insurance companies that we would expect to play a pivotal role in a voluntaryist society would probably offer title insurance for IP (much as they offer title insurance for real estate today). Galambos’ proposed method of having competitive registration bureaus and payment of innovation fees might be one possible way of handling IP. However, just as there are numerous nuances in the way we buy, sell, lease, rent, and rent-to-own real property, there undoubtedly would be many different ways of ‘owning’ intellectual property in a state-free world.

Some thinkers might freely license the use of their ideas or give them away for free; others might be secretive and seek as much monetary profit as possible, but the point is that respect for property would be 100% consistent across the spectrum. Just as you want to pay for things when you go into a store, you would want to pay the inventor of a great idea for the benefits he brings you. It is one way of expressing gratitude to those who are responsible for helping to create progress and civilization. A societal ethos would exist which would respect property in both tangible and intangible things.

And just as I believe that the moral and practical go hand-in-hand, I believe, like Galambos, that such a society would be the most flourishing, productive, and philosophically consistent. As hard as it is for non-libertarians to understand how the roads might be built or how people might be protected from criminals in a libertarian society, it is probably just as difficult to imagine how ideas might be owned, bought, and sold in a voluntaryist one. The answer to the question, “How might ideas be owned and protected?” is not critical at this point. Owners of intellectual property will figure things out, just as owners of the roads will figure out how to get them built. The question before us is, “Should ideas be subject to private ownership?” not, “What non-coercive methods can be envisioned to protect them?”

What Is Intellectual Property?

Intellectual property rights in a state-free society may be defined as claims to intangible things. In our statist world, they are represented by such legal concepts as copyrights, patents, trademarks, and trade secrets. “Intellectual property rights are rights in ideal objects [intangibles], which are distinguished from the material substrata in which they are” actually found. [4] “A patent is a [government-established] property right in” an invention, such that others may not “manufacture, use, or” sell copies of the concrete item which has been “invented.” [5] Copyright refers to a creator’s right to control the reproduction of concrete objects which embody the ideal object which he or she has created. As copyright owner, an author may rightfully exercise control over those who desire to copy his work once it has been made public. The rightful owner of paper and a printing press may not “use his own property to create another copy of [the author’s] book. Only [the author] has the right to copy the book (hence, ‘copyright’).” [6]

Should Ideas Be Owned?

The first hurdle in outlining a defense of intellectual property rights is to establish that ideas should, in fact, be treated as property. If they are not property, then there is nothing to “own.” As Kinsella observes:

The problem with the natural rights defense of IP … lies in the argument that because an author-inventor “creates” some “thing,” he is “thus” entitled to own it. The argument begs the question by assuming that the ideal object is ownable in the first place; … . [7]

Kinsella argues that it is the scarcity of tangible goods – “the fact that there can be conflict over these goods by multiple human actors” – that gives “rise to the need for ethical rules” or property rights to govern [their] use. [8] “The function of property rights is to prevent interpersonal conflict over scarce resources by allocating exclusive ownership of resources to specified individuals (owners).” [9]

[G]iven the origin, justification, and function of property rights, … they are applicable only to scarce resources. Were we in a Garden of Eden where land and other goods were infinitely abundant, there would be no scarcity and, therefore, no need for property rules; property concepts would be meaningless. The idea of conflict, and the idea of rights, would not even arise. For example, your taking my lawnmower would not really deprive me of it if I could conjure up another at the blink of an eye. Lawnmower-taking in these circumstances would not be “theft.” Property rights are not applicable to things of infinite abundance, because there cannot be conflict over such things. … [P]roperty rights can apply only to scarce resources. The problem with IP rights is that the ideal objects protected by IP rights are not scarce; and, further, that such property rights are not, and cannot be, allocated in accordance with the first-occupier homesteading rule, … . [10]

Contrary to Kinsella, Spooner and Galambos argue that ideas should be owned. Although neither Spooner nor Galambos based their arguments on scarcity, the fact of the matter is: good ideas are scarce. Poor ideas may be abundant, but really great and important ideas are scarce. All ideas are the result of the mental effort and creative thinking by the individuals who enunciate them. If one takes a Lockean approach to the establishment of property rights, it is the exertion of human energy and labor upon tangible or corporeal objects which connects a human actor to the act of owning something. Similarly, it is the act of creating a new idea that entitles its creator to ownership. Good ideas are valuable to those who originate them and to those who choose to utilize their effects. As Spooner wrote in his A LETTER TO SCIENTISTS AND INVENTORS, “[K]nowledge is [the ultimate] wealth.” [11]

Scarcity is a background feature of the human condition. You cannot stand in the spot I am occupying. Nor is it necessary that there be potential conflict between human actors in order to establish “ethical rules” or “property rights” in either real property or intellectual property. There are many types of property, such as movie theaters, concert halls, or cruise ships, which numerous people can use at the same time without interfering with one another, or with the rightful owner. [12] However, they are still respected as private property. Even in the Garden of Eden there would be a need for private property rights. In the Garden of Eden “my” lawnmower is still “my lawnmower.” It may have sentimental value; it may be marked in a certain way; it may cut in a certain way that no other lawnmower can duplicate. Lawnmower-taking in the Garden of Eden would indeed be theft because it would be the taking of property without the consent of the owner, even if that owner could conjure up another in an instant.

Kinsella continues his argument by pointing out that IP rights actually undercut the traditional libertarian homesteading principle. “[A]ccording to Lockean-libertarian homesteading, it is the first occupier of a previously unowned scarce resource who homesteads it, i.e., becomes its owner.” [13] To Kinsella, the problem with IP rights is it destroys the homesteading principle because it allows the owner of an idea to control how others use their already justly-owned property. “For example, by inventing a new technique for digging a well, the inventor can prevent all others in the world from digging wells in this manner, even on their own property,” even with their own well-drilling equipment. Similarly, “the first man to invent a house … would have a right to prevent others from building houses on their own land, with their own logs, or to charge them a fee if they do … .” [14]

Spooner vs. Kinsella

Spooner and Galambos would argue that Kinsella is wrong. First of all, Kinsella insists that it is not the labor of the homesteader which entitles him to ownership; but rather the homesteader’s first occupation which makes him become the original owner of a piece of property. But what, exactly, is Kinsella’s point? Doesn’t occupation require labor by the first owner/occupier? Without labor how would a homesteader occupy his or her property?

Kinsella then argues that owning an idea restricts how others may use their property: the person who wants to bore a well – using the technique invented and owned by someone else – may not legitimately do so unless they have the consent of the owner of that technique. Now both Spooner and Galambos allow that the person who wants to drill the well may independently come up with the same idea him or her self. If that is the case then there is no conflict between the two independent owners. Each owns his idea and may charge for it, give it away, or do as they choose with it.

It is said that two men sometimes make the same invention; and that it would therefore be wrong to give the whole invention to one. The answer to this objection is, that the fact that two men produce the same invention, is a very good reason why the invention should belong to both; but it is no reason at all why both should be deprived of it. If two men produce the same invention, each has an equal right to it; because each has an equal right to the fruits of his labor. Neither can deny the right of the other, without denying also his own. The consequence is, that they must either use and sell the invention in competition with each other, or unite their rights, and share the invention between them. … Each holds the whole invention by the same title – that of having produced it by his labor. Neither can say that the title of the other is defective, or in any way imperfect. Neither party has any right, therefore, to object to the other’s using or selling the invention at discretion. And each, therefore, can lawfully and freely use and sell the invention, (and give a good title to the purchaser,) without any liability to answer to the other as an infringer.

– Lysander Spooner, THE LAW OF INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY (1855), pp. 68-69.

However, Kinsella objects because “ownership” of that well-drilling technique could prevent others from using that idea. Spooner and Galambos agree. In a voluntaryist society people will go out of their way to respect the property rights of others. They will want to pay for the benefit they receive from a clever well-drilling technique. Kinsella’s objection that some people would be prevented from using their own property to duplicate the well-drilling technique is also true, but that same objection could be directed against ownership of real property. There are already many instances where my property rights in tangibles prevent you from using your property as you wish. A “No Trespass” sign legitimately prevents you from driving “your” car onto “my” driveway. If I refuse to sell you “my” car, you may not use “your” money to buy it. If I will not consent to let you copy “my” book, then you may not use your paper, ink, and photocopier to reproduce it.

Kinsella summarizes his critique of IP rights by noting that IP advocates are trying to treat dissimilar things – “nonscarce, infinitely reproducible patterns of information and physical[ly] scarce objects” – “with the same rules. They take property rules designed precisely to allocate ownership of scarce physical objects in the face of possible conflict and try to apply them to information patterns. In so doing, they end up imposing artificial scarcity on that which was previously nonscarce and infinitely reproducible.” [15]

Spooner and his LAW OF INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY

In his book, THE LAW OF INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY (1855), Spooner anticipated many of the arguments set forth by Kinsella. Spooner argued that there was no real difference between producing physical wealth by means of physical labor and ideas by mental effort.

All that labor, which we are in the habit of calling physical labor, is in reality performed wholly by the mind, will, or spirit, which uses the bones and muscles merely as tools. Bones and muscles perform no labor of themselves; they move, in labor, only as they are moved by the mind, will, or spirit. It is, therefore, as much the mind, will, or spirit, that lifts a stone, or fells a tree, or digs a field, as it is the mind, will, or spirit, that produces an idea. There is, therefore, no such thing as the physical labor of men, independently of their intellectual labor. … A man’s rights … to the intellectual products of his labor, necessarily stand on the same basis with his rights to the material products of his labor. [16]

In response to Kinsella’s contention that it is the physical scarcity of tangible goods that necessitates property rights in order to avoid violent confrontations between would-be users of those goods, Spooner argues that “the right of property … originates [not in the fact of potential conflict among men, but rather] in the natural right of every man to the benefit of his own labor.” [17]

If this principle be a sound one, it necessarily follows that every man has a natural right to all the productions and acquisitions of his own labor, be they intellectual or material. If the principle be not a sound one, then it follows, necessarily, that there are no rights of property at all in the productions or acquisitions of human labor. [18]

To argue that an idea can be used by two people at the same time ignores the fact that “the idea has been produced by one man’s labor, and not by the labor of all men; … .” [19] If an idea which is “the product of one man’s labor, can be made free to all mankind, without his consent, then, by the same rule, every other commodity, the product of individual labor, may be made free to all mankind, without the consent of the producers. And this is equivalent to a denial of all individual property whatsoever, in commodities produced or acquired by human labor.” [20] Spooner then asks if the right of property is destroyed (by not recognizing ideas as property)

what principle … [is offered], as a substitute, by which to regulate the conduct of men, in their possession and use of all those commodities, which are now subjects of property? It substitutes only this, viz. : that men must not come in collision with each other, in the actual possession and use of things. [21]

Now, since this actual possession and use of things, can be exercised, only by men’s bringing their bodies in immediate contact with the things to be possessed or used, it follows that the principle laid down, of men’s avoiding collision in the possession and use of things, amounts to but this, viz.: that men’s bodies are sacred, and must not be jostled; but nothing else is sacred. In other words, men own their bodies; but they own nothing else. Every thing else belongs, of right, as much to one person as to another. And the only way, in which one man can possess or use any thing, in preference to other men, is by keeping his hands constantly upon it, or otherwise interposing his body between it and other men. These are the only grounds, on which he can hold any thing. If he take his hands off a commodity, and also withdraw his body from it, so as to interpose no obstacle to the commodity’s being taken possession of by others, they have a right to take possession of it, and hold it against him, by the same process, by which he had before held it against them. This is the legitimate and necessary result of the doctrine [that ideas are not property and may be used at will by anyone and everyone].

On this principle a man has a right to take possession of, and freely use, any thing and every thing he sees and desires, which other men may have produced by their labor – provided he can do it without coming in collision with, or committing any violence upon, the persons of other men.

This is the principle, and the only principle, which the objection offers, as a rule for the government of the conduct of mankind towards each other, in the possession and use of material commodities. And it seriously does offer this principle, as a substitute for the right of individual and exclusive property, in the products and acquisitions of individual labor. The principle, thus offered, is really communism, and nothing else.

If this principle be a sound one, in regard to material commodities, it is undoubtedly equally sound in relation to ideas. But if it be preposterous and monstrous, in reference to material commodities, it is equally preposterous and monstrous in relation to ideas for, if applied to ideas, it as effectually denies the right of exclusive property in the products of one’s labor, as it would if applied to material commodities. [22]

Spooner then points out that “if it be acknowledged that a man have an exclusive right of property in the products of his labor, because they are the products of his labor, it clearly makes no difference to this right, whether the commodity he has produced be, in its nature, capable of being possessed and used by a thousand persons at once, or only by one at a time. That is a wholly immaterial matter, so far as his right of property is concerned; because his right of property is derived from his labor in producing the commodity; not from the nature of the commodity when produced.” [23]

A man’s exclusive right of property in – or, in other words, his right of absolute dominion over – any one of these various commodities, depends entirely upon the fact, that such commodity was either a product or acquisition of his own labor, (or of the labor of some one, from whom, either mediately, or immediately, he has derived it, by purchase, gift, or inheritance;) and not at all upon the fact, that such commodity can, or cannot, be possessed and used by more than one person at a time, without collision. [24]

Finally, Spooner concludes that “if it once be conceded that labor and production” establish private ownership, then men have “absolute rights … as against all other men” in their property, whether they be ideas or tangible commodities.

[T]here is no middle ground between the principle, that labor and production give the producer no rights at all, over other men, in the commodity he produces; and the principle, that they give him absolute rights over all other men, to wit, the right of exclusive property or dominion. There is, therefore, no middle ground between absolute communism, on the one hand, which holds that a man has a right to lay his hands on any thing, which has no other man’s hands upon it, no matter who may have been the producer; and the principle of individual property, on the other hand, which says that each man has an absolute dominion, as against all other men, over the products and acquisitions of his own labor, whether he retain them in his actual possession, or not. [25]

Why Respect the Property of Others?

In his 1882 essay, “Natural Law,” Spooner elaborated on what he called “the science of justice.” Although Spooner’s predecessors in the study of natural law had probably never considered the case of intellectual property, those theorists of the 16th and 17th Centuries had addressed another very pertinent question: Does a person, apart from promise or contract, have any obligation to refrain from using that which has already been appropriated by someone else, so long as he may take possession without coming into physical conflict with the first owner/user? [26] This is the great question of what is mine and what is thine: whose property is it?. As F. A. Harper explained in his LIBERTY, A PATH TO ITS RECOVERY, there are three possibilities with respect to ownership:

  1. Each person may have whatever he can grab.
  2. Some person other than the one who produces the goods and services may decide who shall have the right of possession or use.
  3. Each person may be allowed to have whatever he produces. [27]

These dichotomies are as applicable to the ownership of ideas as they are to real and tangible property. Although historically intellectual property has not generally or consistently been respected by governments or members of civil society, there is evidence that property, in all its myriad forms, could and would be respected in the absence of the state. For example, there was no governmental presence (such as army or police) on the overland trail to California during the mid-19th Century, but property rights were still largely respected. Such behavior was a taught, learned, and an accepted custom of the overwhelming majority of the emigrants. Even under the most life-threatening conditions of Death Valley, property in water was respected. [28] As Rose Wilder Lane put it in THE DISCOVERY OF FREEDOM:

The only safeguards of property seem to have been possession of the property, individual honesty, and public opinion. Well, cabins were never locked on the American frontier where there was no law. The real protection of life and property, always and everywhere, is the general recognition of the brotherhood of man. How much of the time is any American within sight of a policeman? Our lives and property are protected by the way nearly everyone feels about another person’s life and property. [29]

Conclusion

Why do we respect other people’s property? Why should we respect someone’s property that has been left unattended, when there is no chance of being caught if we filch it? Ultimately, each of us has to answer these questions for ourselves. To be consistent and non-hypocritical we should follow the Golden Rule. We never want our property stolen. If we expect others to respect our property then we need to respect their property. The thief is always the hypocrite. He never wants “his” property stolen, but he is always prepared to steal the property of others when he thinks he can get away with it. We want the efforts and results of our labor to be respected. Otherwise, why should we produce more than we can quickly use or store for a short period of time?

If ideas are not property, then what are they? Why else do we (and even its opponents, such as Kinsella) refer to them as intellectual property? It is certainly possible to imagine that respect for the intellectual property of others could become a learned practice and an accepted custom in a state-free society. People in such a society would come to recognize the justice and legitimacy of owning ideas. Non-coercive practices would evolve, just as voluntary and customary ways of treating real estate and tangible property have developed over the centuries.

A world without widespread respect for private property would indeed be nasty, brutish, and one with few amenities. We would be better off in a world with private property in both tangibles and intellectual property, but it would not be a perfect one. Criminals will always be with us. As Richard Boren, put it: Galambos did not believe nor does “any rational person believe[…] that we will have a perfect state-less world. What we are striving for is a world with the fewest imperfections as possible. … [A] world where real and intellectual property are respected will produce the fewest imperfections.” [30] That is why I think that the ownership of ideas is a target towards which we voluntaryists should aim.

End Notes

[1] Richard Boren in personal communications of September 2014 and May 2015. For an elaboration see Richard Boren, “For Intellectual Property: The Property Ideas of Andrew J. Galambos.”
[2] See Chapter 13, “Competition and Monopoly,” in Robert LeFevre, THE FUNDAMENTALS OF LIBERTY, Santa Ana: Rampart Institute, 1988, pp. 193-199.
[3] N. Stephan Kinsella, “Against Intellectual Property,” 15 THE JOURNAL OF LIBERTARIAN STUDIES (2001), pp. 1-53 at p. 44.
[4] ibid., p. 3.
[5] ibid., p. 4.
[6] ibid., p. 8.
[7] ibid. p. 28.
[8] ibid., p. 19.
[9] ibid., p. 20.
[10] ibid., pp. 21-22.
[11] Lysander Spooner, A LETTER TO SCIENTISTS AND INVENTORS, ON THE SCIENCE OF JUSTICE, AND THEIR RIGHTS OF PERPETUAL PROPERTY IN THEIR DISCOVERIES AND INVENTIONS, Boston: Cupples, Uphman & Co., 1884, Section II, p. 6, in Charles Shively, editor, Volume 3, THE COLLECTED WORKS OF LYSANDER SPOONER, Weston: M & S Press, 1971.
[12] Lysander Spooner, THE LAW OF INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY OR AN ESSAY ON THE RIGHT OF AUTHORS AND INVENTORS TO A PERPETUAL PROPERTY IN THEIR IDEAS, Boston: Published by Bela Marsh, 1855, p. 94 in Charles Shively, editor, Volume 3, THE COLLECTED WORKS OF LYSANDER SPOONER, Weston: M & S Press, 1971.
[13] Kinsella, op. cit. p. 32.
[14] ibid., pp. 32-33.
[15] Stephan Kinsella, “The Death Throes of Pro-IP Libertarianism,” Mises Daily, July 28, 2010, accessed May 17, 2015 at http://mises.org/library/death-throes-ip-libertarianism.
[16] Spooner, op. cit., THE, LAW OF INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY, p. 27.
[17] ibid., p. 77.
[18] ibid.
[19] ibid., p. 76.
[20] ibid.
[21] ibid., p. 77.
[22] ibid., pp. 77-79.
[23] ibid., p. 79.
[24] ibid., p. 81.
[25] ibid., p. 88.
[26] See Carl Watner, “The Proprietary Theory of Justice in the Libertarian Tradition,” 6 THE JOURNAL OF LIBERTARIAN STUDIES (1982), pp. 289-316 at p. 291.
[27] F. A. Harper, LIBERTY A PATH TO ITS RECOVERY, Irvington-on-Hudson, The Foundation for Economic Education, 1949, p. 28.
[28] John Phillip Reid, LAW FOR THE ELEPHANT: PROPERTY AND SOCIAL BEHAVIOR ON THE OVERLAND TRAIL, San Marino: The Huntington Library, 1980, pp. 355 and 362.
[29] Rose Wilder Lane, THE DISCOVERY OF FREEDOM, New York: The John Day Company, 1943. Reprinted by Laissez Fair Books, 1984, pp. 109-110.
[30] Richard Boren, email communication February 6, 2015, 11:49 AM.

Copyright Before (Statutory) Copyright: A Voluntaryist Perspective on a Statist Development


 

by Carl Watner

Would there be the equivalent of statutory copyright protection in a voluntaryist society? Would copyright as we know it today in 21st Century United States have developed in the absence of coercive government? While it is impossible to categorically answer “Yes” or “No” to such hypothetical questions, a study of history reveals several facts. First, statutory copyright developed in conjunction with the English government’s desire (from the time of the introduction of printing in England to the early 18th Century) to censor heretical and seditious publications. Statutory copyright was also generated by the demands of members of the Stationers’ Company to create a monopoly for themselves by using the government to protect them from competitors. Finally, despite many claims to the contrary, statutory copyright, as we know it today, did not evolve as a natural right under the umbrella of the English common law. As Lyman Patterson observed, statutory “copyright was not a product of the common law. It was a product of censorship, guild monopoly, [and] trade-regulation statutes, … .” [1]

As indicated in the Addendum at the end of this article, both libertarians and statists have written volumes about both the propriety and/or illegitimacy of ownership of intellectual property. Although I offer the following definition of intellectual property rights, the discussion in this article is confined to copyright because the history of statutory copyright is well-researched and it has received the most attention from commentators. Intellectual property rights may be defined as claims to intangible things. “Intellectual property rights are rights in ideal objects, which are distinguished from the material substrata in which they are” actually found. [2] Copyright refers to a creator’s right to control the reproduction of concrete objects which embody the ideal object which he or she has created. Under statutory copyright an author may rightfully exercise control over those who desire to copy his work once it has been made public. The rightful owner of paper and a printing press may not “use his own property to create another copy of [the author’s] book. Only [the author] has the right to copy the book (hence, ‘copyright’).” [3]

The Author’s Right Throughout History

In Western civilization, by the 1st Century B.C., the “[c]opying and duplication of manuscripts had [become] … a profitable business.” [4] Although no ancient law ever embraced the concept of intellectual property rights, “public opinion [usually] ‘stigmatized’ plagiarism as a crime.” [5] Historical “sources provide much evidence for [concern with] literary theft or plagiarism. Literary theft involve[d] affixing one’s own name to someone else’s writings or inserting someone else’s writings within one’s own text without acknowledgement. What was being stolen in the ancient world was credit, honor, and reputation, rather than property.” [6] As passed down through the centuries, the moral rights of the author came to embrace: 1) the right of paternity (the right to be identified as the author of a work); 2) the right of integrity (protection against unauthorized changes or mutilations of one’s text); and, 3) the right to withhold publication. The first two “moral rights of authorship have always been regarded as inalienable and perpetual” in contrast to the limited rights created under statutory copyright. [7] As one observer put it, “Opposition to [statutory] copyright in the narrower sense does not imply opposition to the moral rights of authorship, which are ancient legal concepts. … [T]he right to control the reproduction of creative works” was never “regarded as implicit in the concept of authorship” prior to the invention of printing. [8]

The concept of authorship as we know it today evolved over many centuries. “The identity of the scribe, compiler, commentator, or author of a manuscript was … unimportant to the medieval reading public. … No attempt was made to identify the author or scribe of a medieval text, or even its title. Manuscripts were referred to by the opening words of the text, following a tradition that dated back to the cuneiform clay tablets [of] Babylonia.” [9] “In the Middle Ages the owner of a manuscript was understood to possess the right to grant permission to copy it, and this was a right that could be exploited, as it was for example, by those monasteries that regularly charged a fee for permission to copy one of their” codices. [10]

One of the earliest documented disputes over the copying of a monastically-owned parchment involved a warrior-monk, Colmcille (also known as St. Columba [521-597 AD]), and Finnian of Moville, who had brought the first copy of the Vulgate to Ireland “after a visit to Rome” around 550 A.D. “The Vulgate was the definitive Latin translation of the Bible done by St. Jerome about 100 years earlier.” [11] When Colmcille visited Finnian at his Irish monastery, he surreptitiously attempted to copy the text. He was discovered by Finnian who demanded the copy which Colmcille had made without his permission. This led to a lengthy dispute between the two men, which became known as the “Battle of the Book.” Ultimately, it was determined by Ireland’s Brehon law that Colmcille had no right to copy the parchment, even though he offered the following modernistic argument:

I haven’t used up Finnian’s book by copying it. He still has the original and that original is none the worse for my having copied it. Nor has it decreased in value because I made a transcript of it. The knowledge in books should be available to anybody who wants to read them and has the skills or is worthy to do so; and it is wrong to hide such knowledge away or to attempt to extinguish the divine things that books contain. It is wrong to attempt to prevent me or anyone else from copying it or reading it or making multiple copies to disperse throughout the land. In conclusion, I submit that it was permissible for me to copy the book because, although I benefited from the hard work involved in the transcription, I gained no worldly profit from the process, I acted for the good of society in general and neither Finnian nor his book were harmed. [12] This episode exemplifies the fact that during the Middle Ages, and up to the time of the invention of moveable type (circa the mid-1400s), each owner of a manuscript had the right to control its reproduction. “When the first printers began their work” they, too, had to pay for the “privilege” of copying parchment manuscripts. However, a “monastery which had received compensation from a printer in Venice for the use of a particular parchment, felt itself under no obligation to decline a similar application from rival printers in Lyons or Basel.” Printers had no way to prevent this unless “they found the means to purchase the manuscript outright.” [13] Since this was often impossible to accomplish, printers sought special protection (in order to monopolize their sales) from their local governments, which themselves desired to encourage the fledgling printing industry, as well as to control its output.

Printing “Privileges” and Copyright

Thus emerged “the earliest genuine anticipations of [statutory] copyright.” These were known as printing “‘privileges’ and first appeared in fifteenth-century Venice.” These “privileges” were exclusive rights issued by the Venetian state “to individuals for limited periods of time to reward them for services or to encourage them in useful activities. … The first and most famous ‘privilege’ was a monopoly on printing itself granted in 1469 to John Speyer, the man who probably introduced printing to Venice.” [14] Speyer’s “privilege” expired after a number of years, but it was followed by Venetian decrees which granted to various other printers the right to produce all books of a given class or in a particular language, or the right to print the work of some author of a past generation or the right to print some ancient classic. Such “privileges” were not granted unless the texts were approved by the government and/or the ecclesiastical censors. [15] This form of government monopoly not only prevented other printers from printing these classes of protected books, but attempted to limit the spread of heretical and seditious ideas. In 1501, aware of the fact that printing (as opposed to hand copying) led to a more rapid and widespread circulation of often dangerous ideas and information, “Pope Alexander VI issued a bull against the unlicensed printing of books and in 1559, the Index Expurgatorious, or LIST OF PROHIBITED BOOKS, was issued for the first time.” [16]

A similar pattern of government and church protection followed in England. “During almost the whole of the period from 1557 to 1709, a time of continuous religious struggle, censorship was a major policy of the English government.” [17] Government and religious leaders were concerned that liberal and critical ideas in newly published “books could corrupt the people into questioning the integrity of the state.” [18] As the menace of printing spread, the English Crown used its sovereign powers to license both printers and the books they printed. “The charter of the Stationers’ Company … granted its members (the leading publishers in London) an officially state-sanctioned monopoly over the printing of books, and provided for the burning of prohibited books and the imprisonment of anyone printing unauthorized books.” [19] The right to print was limited to members of the printers’ guild, and in 1586, the Star Chamber (a special prosecutorial and enforcement arm of the government) issued a decree to curtail the “enormities and abuses among the contentious and disorderly persons” who were printing and selling books. [20] Although the powers granted to the Stationers’ Company provided its members with great economic benefits, its primary purpose was “the establishment of a more effective system for government surveillance of the press.” [21]

Originally formed as a private organization in 1403, the Stationers’ Company received its Royal Charter in 1557. Although its agents “were legally empowered to seize ‘offending books’ that violated the standards of content set down by the Church and State,” the Stationers’ Company also offered its members an extended monopoly over works entered into its Register. The Stationers’ Register was a record book which allowed members of the Company “to document their right to produce a particular printed work.” The Stationers’ copyright (though it was not originally referred to as such) was granted by the Company to members who paid a fee to register their right to publish a given work. [22] It was a private affair of the Company and was strictly regulated by Company ordinances. “The scope of the copyright was the right to publish a work, and no more, for the stationers’ copyright was literally a right to copy.” The stationer’s right to print a given work “was deemed to exist in perpetuity.” Authors, not generally being members of the Company “were not eligible to hold [a] copyright.” [23] An author’s work “could be copied and recopied without his permission.” William Shakespeare (1564-1616), for example, “made his bargain with a printer, and if he parted with his manuscript for a price he surrendered all further rights in it.” His only control as an author was as the owner of the manuscript he had written. “He did not sell the right to print to the stationer; he sold the manuscript. Once the manuscript was sold, all his rights in the work ceased.” [24]

Copyright and the Common Law

The common law played no part in these historical developments. It took about 50 years for the English Crown to “catch-up” with the new technological development of moveable type. By 1530, Henry VIII had regulated foreign printers, issued his first list of prohibited books, and began licensing books and printers. There was continual government regulation of the press until the expiration of the Licensing Act of 1694. At that time, the Stationers’ Company began its struggle to incorporate its version of private copyright into national law. Given the cessation of government control over printing, what did the common law say about an author’s right to control the copying of his work? The common law of this era (1694-1710) did not recognize an author’s legal right or standing to restrict the copying of his or her work. [25] Finally in 1710, the first piece of modern legislation to embrace the basic elements of statutory copyright, as we know it today, was passed by Parliament. Known as the Statute of Anne it allocated to authors, or to the lawful buyers of their manuscripts, an exclusive right of publication that lasted fourteen years. If the author was still living at that time, his copyright protection was extended to a second term of 14 years, after which his work fell into the “public domain.” [26]

After the passage of the Statute, the Stationers’ Company continued to attempt to incorporate its version of perpetual private copyright into law primarily to protect the competitive position of its own members. Numerous lawsuits were instituted and adjudicated after the passage of the Statute of Anne in an effort to determine whether the common law had ever recognized an author’s intellectual property right in his work, and, if so, whether this right continued in perpetuity. In the case of Millar v Taylor in 1769, the majority of judges on the King’s Bench decided “the author, as the first producer of a work, has a right in that work prior to any statutory rights that may have been granted through a copyright statute. This right, like any other property right is perpetual, cannot be taken away by the state and is defensible in the common law.” [27]

Another lawsuit known as Donaldson v Beckett reached House of Lords in 1774 on appeal. The direct question was whether or not to overturn an injunction against the Scottish bookseller, Donaldson, who “specialised in printing books no longer protected by [the Statute of] Anne.” (Beckett led a group of English booksellers who had bought the expired statutory copyright to the work in question.) The injunction against Donaldson was removed since a majority of peers in the House of Lords held that the “copyright as a statutory right takes precedence over any other rights that an author may have.” [28] This decision voided the holding in Millar v Taylor, which had upheld an author’s perpetual common law copyright in his work. Much confusion has been generated by the fact that the Law Lords, an advisory group to the House of Lords, agreed with the finding in Millar v Taylor that “authors did have a common law right, and that it continued” after the expiration of an author’s statutory copyright under the Statute of Anne. Despite these conflicting legal opinions, the injunction against Donaldson was removed and what had been alleged to be the common law’s perpetual copyright (under Millar v Taylor) was voided by Parliamentary legislation. [29]

The only evidence in favor of the allegations that copyright had existed at common law were arguments echoed by the Stationers. But how could it be maintained that an author’s copyright was recognized at common law when for over 300 years there had been nothing but government intervention in the field of printing? [30] As Lord Camden in the Lords’ debate over Donaldson v Beckett observed, all the arguments in favor of common law copyright “were founded on patents, ‘privileges,’ Star-chamber decrees, and the by-laws of the Stationers’ Company; all of them the effects of the grossest tyranny and usurpation; the very last places which I should have dreamt of finding the least trace of the common law.” [31]

Some Alternatives to Statutory Copyright

So, given that there was no historical development of an author’s copyright in his work under the common law, how might an author attempt to protect and market his work in a voluntaryist society? For one answer to this question, we might look at the role of the haskamah in Jewish history. The first haskamahs appeared in the early 1500s. They were printed in the front or back of a book as a sort of imprimatur given by a well-known scholar or rabbi to a book or treatise. This eventually evolved into a method used by late-medieval, European-Jewish communities to promote learning by encouraging the printing of books, and as a “precaution ensuring that nothing would be printed to which the local Christian authorities might object.” [32] Although the majority of Jewish theorists uphold the concept of intellectual property and endorse the idea that copyright infringement is “a violation of the Torah’s prohibition against stealing” the haskamah represented a time-limited version of printer’s copyright. [33] As the ENCYCLOPAEDIA JUDAICA explains it, “it became customary to preface books with approbations containing a warning against trespass in the form of an unauthorized reprint of a particular book within a specified period.” This was in the nature of a protection of printer’s rights and sometimes only extended to the country where the book was printed; but often “extended the operation of the ban to printers everywhere. In most cases the period of prohibition varied from three to 15 years, but was sometimes imposed as long as 25 years.” These prohibitions were “mainly justified on grounds of the printer’s need for an opportunity to recover his heavy outlay through the subsequent sale of the printed product, … .” [34] Those who refused to respect the haskamah could be excommunicated and banished from the local community.

As one vocal libertarian critic of intellectual property rights has written, “it is difficult to predict what extensive contractual regimes, networks, and institutions will arise,” in the absence of the state. “Various enclaves or communities may well require their customers, patrons, or ‘citizens’ to abide by certain I[ntellectual] P[roperty]-like rules.” [35] Although the haskamah is just one example of how a voluntary community of believers handled the problem, there are at least a few other historical examples of how authors and printers might be compensated in a free society. “During the nineteenth century, there was no copyright protection for the publishers of foreign books in America, yet American publishers deemed the right of first publication sufficiently valuable to justify the voluntary payment of royalties to British authors in order to secure a first edition. In fact, English authors often received more from the sale of their books by American publishers than from their British royalties.” [36]

“In addition to being first on the market, there are other means available to a Publisher to secure his position without copyright protection. The contract with the author may reserve exclusive rights to new introductions, additions, and revisions by the author to subsequent editions issued by the first publisher. Moreover, the first publisher can obtain prepublication orders from interested groups and individuals, a business method which [has been] used [in the past (1966)]. Finally, the authorization of the first edition by the author may be a marketable asset, at least among those readers who strongly believe in the right of an author to the fruits of his creation. This device [was] used to promote an authorized soft cover edition of the LORD OF THE RINGS trilogy of J. R. R. Tolkein, which [wa]s in competition with a copied edition that p[aid] no royalties to Mr. Tolkein.” [37] Another 21st Century innovation is the Creator-Endorsed Mark, which is offered as an alternative to statutory copyright. “The Creator-Endorsed Mark is a logo that a [publisher or] distributor can use to indicate that a work is distributed in a way that its creator endorses – typically, by the distributor sharing some of the profits with the creator.” Lacking any statutory copyright protection, “someone could distribute the work without the author’s permission and without the Creator-Endorsed” logo, but probably at least some members of the consuming public would prefer to support the author by purchasing an author-endorsed edition. [38]

If any type of author’s copyright is to survive in a voluntaryist society it is most likely to be based upon very clear and unambiguous agreements. As Wendy McElroy put it, she is an advocate of free market copyright that is enforceable by virtue of an explicit contract. “I am not anti-copyright. I am anti-state.” [39] Nevertheless, it seems totally unlikely that “private contract” could “be used to recreate” the effects of modern statist laws. [40] “Purchasers can be bound by contracts with sellers to not copy or even re-sell the thing.” [41] However, what of the obligations of third parties who have no contractual relationship with the author or purchaser? Are they bound “not to copy,” and, if so, on what basis could they be held liable for breach of contract? Perhaps public opinion, as in all manners, could be organized to weigh in on the issue. What position might insurance companies take (on enforcement of ‘no-copy’ contracts), and how might a boycott campaign affect those 3rd parties who refused to honor authors’ rights?

Regardless of what contractual alternatives might arise in the absence of statutory copyright, the fact of the matter is that “for at least three thousand years, musical and literary works have been created in pretty much every society, and in the complete absence … of any kind of [statutory] copyright protection.” [42] Authors do not enjoy the protections afforded by statutory copyright in a state of nature. “Copyright depends on state power.” [43] As we have seen, “Copyright emerged in different European countries only after the invention of the printing press.” It did not originate “to protect the profits of authors from copyists or to encourage creation, but rather as an instrument of government censorship. Royal and religious powers arrogated to themselves the right to decide what could and could not be safely printed.” [44] Statutory copyright, as we know it today, did not evolve from the common law. It is a statist development that clearly emerged “from the exercise of state power.” [45]

Author’s Addendum:

As readers may know, there are two opposing ‘camps’ within the libertarian movement with regard to the question of intellectual property (IP) rights. Lysander Spooner (1808-1887) and Andrew Joseph Galambos (1924-1997) represent those who favor the recognition of intellectual property rights, while Benjamin Tucker (1854-1939) and Stephan Kinsella (b. 1965) represent those who claim such rights would not and should not be respected.

Those on the Galambos side of the fence favor something akin to what has been achieved by statutory protection of intellectual property but would reach this goal by means of contract rather than by government legislation. Protection of intellectual property rights would come “from social pressure (the community’s sense that ideas are property, that it is wrong to steal, and that copying without permission is stealing someone’s property) and then from the private judicial system, which would be restitution-based.” Since Galambos believed “that there must be protection of intellectual property for there to be a durable [and flourishing] voluntary society,” he proposed a dual program in attaining full IP protection. “Innovators would [first] disclose their innovations to a private registration company, and the innovations would be then made available for use … by a process of individually negotiated terms and payment amounts, and later by releasing them to wide[r] distribution, with voluntary payment for use.” [46] Ideas would not be “locked away forever,” as some of his critics claim.

Those on the Kinsella side of the fence argue that ideas cannot and should not be owned. There is no basis in libertarian homesteading theory for protecting or recognizing IP rights because IP is not a scarce, tangible product, and can be used by many people at the same time without conflict. As Kinsella concludes, “a system of property rights in ‘ideal objects’ necessarily requires violation of other individual property rights, e.g., to use one’s own tangible property as one sees fit.” [47] A right to copy prevents an innocent owner from using his paper and printing press in reproducing certain documents. Furthermore, there is no practical reason for IP rights because several thousands of years of history show that literary and musical works have been produced without their creators being statutorily protected.

But the fact of the matter is: we cannot know how IP rights (if they are to exist at all) would develop in the absence of the State because the nation-state has permeated the lives of mankind for the last 600 years. It is only in the last 150 years that the idea that private defense agencies could supersede the State has surfaced, so there is no reason to expect a quick and easy answer to the IP question. I would expect that the same insurance companies that would play such a pivotal role in a voluntaryist society would figure out how to insure some forms of IP. The purpose of this article has been to inquire as to whether IP rights ever existed historically and customarily at common law. A future article will have to undertake the task of comparing and analyzing the pro and con arguments for and against IP rights.

End Notes
[1] Lyman Ray Patterson, COPYRIGHT IN HISTORICAL PERSPECTIVE, Nashville: Vanderbilt University Press, 1968, p. 19.
[2] N. Stephan Kinsella, “Against Intellectual Property,” 15 THE JOURNAL OF LIBERTARIAN STUDIES (2001), pp. 1-53, at p. 3.
[3] ibid., p. 8.
[4] Harold C. Streibich, “The Moral Right of Ownership to Intellectual Property: Part I,” 6 MEMPHIS STATE UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW (1975), pp. 1-35, at p. 5.
[5] ibid.
[6] Pamela O. Long, OPENNESS, SECRECY, AUTHORSHIP, Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 2001, p. 10.
[7] Julio H. Cole, “Patents and Copyrights: Do the Benefits Exceed the Costs?” 15 THE JOURNAL OF LIBERTARIAN STUDIES (2001), pp. 79-105 at p. 95.
[8] ibid., p.96.
[9] Robert K. Logan, THE ALPHABET EFFECT, New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1987, p. 212.
[10] Mark Rose, AUTHORS AND OWNERS: THE INVENTION OF COPYRIGHT, Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1993, p. 9.
[11] Ray Corrigan, “Colmcille and the Battle of the Book: Technology, Law and Access to Knowledge in 6th Century Ireland,” at oro.open.ac.uk/10332/1/G1K11_Colmcille_final.pdf, at p. 5 of the pdf. University College London Seminar, September 19, 2007, London, UK. Also see Stephan Kinsella, “First Alleged ‘Copyright’ Dispute: 560 AD, Celtic Ireland; Battle Ensues; 3000 People Die,” Mises Economic Blog, May 10, 2011 at http://archive.mises.org/16871/first-copyright-dispute-560-ad-celtic-Ireland-battle-ensues-3000-people-die/.
[12] Corrigan, op. cit., p. 6.
[13] Geo. Haven Putnam, BOOKS AND THEIR MAKERS DURING THE MIDDLE AGES, Volume II, 1500-1709, New York: Hillary House Publisher Ltd., 1962 (reprint of the 1896-1897 edition), p. 485.
[14] Rose, op. cit., pp. 9-10.
[15] Putnam, op. cit, pp. 486-488.
[16] “History of copyright law,” from Wikipedia, the free encyc-lopedia. See Section 2, “Early privileges and monopolies,” paragraph 1 at en.wikipedia.org/wiki/History_of_copyright_law.
[17] Patterson, op. cit., p. 6.
[18] Julius Jay Marke, “Copyright versus Intellectual Property,” UNIVERSITY OF TENNESSEE LIBRARY LECTURES, Lecture 28, 1976, p. 2.
[19] Edward Samuels, THE ILLUSTRATED STORY OF COPYRIGHT, New York: Thomas Dunne Books, 2000, p. 14.
[20] “History of copyright law,” from Wikipedia, op. cit., Section 2, paragraph 6.
[21] Rose, op. cit., p. 12.
[22] “Worshipful Company of Stationers and Newspaper Makers,” from Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia, Section 1, History, paragraph 3 and “Stationers’ Register,” from Wikipedia, paragraph 1.
[23] Patterson, op. cit., p. 5 and p. 9.
[24] Leo Kirschbaum, “Author’s Copyright in England before 1640,” 40 PAPERS OF THE BIBLIOGRAPHICAL SOCIETY OF AMERICA, 1946, pp. 43-80 at pp. 43-44.
[25] Lee Marshall, BOOTLEGGING, London; Sage Publications, 2005, p. 8, and Howard B. Abrams, “The Historic Foundations of American Copyright Law: Exploding the Myth of Common Law Copyright,” 29 WAYNE LAW REVIEW (1983), pp. 1119-1191 at p. 1138.
[26] Marshall, op. cit., p. 11 and Michele Boldrin and David K. Levine, AGAINST INTELLECTUAL MONOPOLY, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010 (first paperback edition), p. 30.
[27] Marshall, op. cit., p. 13.
[28] ibid., p. 15.
[29] For a contrary interpretation, see Lysander Spooner’s defense of intellectual property rights. Spooner noted that the decision in Donaldson v Beckett did “not stand as a decision that an author had not a perpetual copyright at common law; but only as a decision that, if he had such a right at common law, that right had been taken away by statute.” Lysander Spooner, THE LAW OF INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY (1855), reprinted in Charles Shively (editor), THE COLLECTED WORKS OF LYSANDER SPOONER, Weston: M & S Press, 1971, pp. 212-213.
[30] It is interesting to note that Lysander Spooner agreed that the common law had not been given a chance to set a precedent. He argued that if it had, then – on the basis of natural law – it would have upheld an author’s perpetual copyright in his work.
[31] Joseph Lowenstein, THE AUTHOR’S DUE: PRINTING AND THE PREHISTORY OF COPYRIGHT, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 2002, p. 21.
[32] “Haskamah,” in Volume 8, ENCYCLOPAEDIA JUDAICA, Second Edition, Detroit: Thomson Gale, 2007, p. 444 and pp. 451-452.
[33] Rabbi Nachum Menashe Weisfish, COPYRIGHT IN JEWISH LAW, Jerusalem: Feldheim Books, 2010, p. xxii.
[34] “Haskamah,” Volume 8, op. cit., p. 451.
[35] Kinsella, op. cit., p. 41.
[36] Robert M. Hurt, “The Economic Rationale of Copyright,” 56 AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW (1966), pp. 421-439 at p. 427.
[37] ibid., pp. 428-429.
[38] Stephan Kinsella, “The Creator-Endorsed Mark as an Alternative to Copyright,” Mises Economics Blog, July 15, 2010 at http://archive.mises.org/13286/the-creator-endorsed-mark-as-an-alternative-to-copyright/.
[39] Wendy McElroy, “The Basics of Copyright,” Daily Anarchist, September 1, 2012, at http://dailyanarchist.com/2012/09/01/the-basics-of-copyright/.
[40] Kinsella, “Against Intellectual Property,” op. cit., p. 34.
[41] ibid. p. 41.
[42] Boldrin and Levine, op. cit., p. 30.
[43] Tom Bell, INTELLECTUAL PRIVILEGE: COPYRIGHT, COMMON LAW, AND THE COMMON GOOD, Arlington: Mercatus Center, George Mason University, 2014, p. 71 and p. 75.
[44] Boldrin and Levine, op. cit., p. 30.
[45] Tom G. Palmer, “Intellectual Property: A Non-Posnerian Law and Economics Approach,” 12 HAMLINE LAW REVIEW (1989), pp. 261-304, at p. 267.
[46] Richard Boren, a student of Galambos, provided these quotes in personal communications, September 2014.
[47] Kinsella, op. cit., p. 44.

On Andrew Galambos and His Primary Property Ideas


 

by Alvin Lowi, Jr.
(Original version: March 31, 1998)

 

“Alvin Lowi first met Andrew J. Galambos in 1958 when he joined the technical Staff of Ramo-Wooldridge Corp. where Galambos was a principal astrophysicist for that company, which became TRW Space Technology Laboratories shortly thereafter. At the time, Lowi was a Ph.D. candidate in engineering at UCLA and Galambos generously tutored him in thermodynamics and other scientific subjects. Out of this collegial relationship arose a close person friendship and an intense mutual interest in developing a scientific approach to the understanding of social phenomena. By 1960, this rapport resulted in the founding of the Free Enterprise Institute and other related enterprises. Progress in the development of the details of “Volitional Science” failed to keep pace with the growing popularity of the mostly ideological lecture courses offered by FEI. Consequently, in 1969, Mr. Lowi relinquished his founder’s equity and terminated his position in FEI and his participation in the promotion of its ideological program.

“Since that time, Mr. Lowi has worked independently on the application of the scientific method to social phenomena. An unpublished monograph of his on this subject is referred to in this essay. He has contributed various articles and commentaries on the prospects of spontaneous volitional society, which appear on the world wide web under the auspices of the Tucson Center for Socionomic Research’s Cactus Club Dialog page. He has also written some critical reviews of politics and political government for the Economic Government Group which appeared in its “Don’t Vote” page [until the website ceased to exist]: “No Conceivable Reform” and “Abstention is not Apathy“. He is also a contributing author of “Technology and the Case for Free Enterprise,” an anthology edited and co-authored by economics professors Daniel Klein and Fred Foldvary, [which was] to be published by the University of Michigan Press in 2001.

“In this four-part essay, Mr. Lowi revisits some of Andrew J. Galambos’ ideas on intellectual property, or “Primary Property” as Galambos called it. Mr. Lowi freely admits his treatment is only as good as his memory after several decades of reflection and further research.”

– Stephen Clarke-Willson, Editor-Moderator, Above-the-Gararge.com and Volitional Science Group

Section 1

PREFACE

“Primary property” became the centerpiece of an ideological program launched by astrophysicist Andrew J. Galambos in 1961. The avowed purpose of this enterprise was to “build” a free society.[1]

Galambos claimed a scientific basis for his approach. However, the dearth of written material as well as the ideological context in which the subject was presented has inhibited students of Galambos in their further explorations of the subject and handicapped their attempts to make practical applications of it to their lives. Nevertheless, the concepts he presented were enthusiastically received. He developed considerable excitement among his more than 5000 former students resulting in a loyal following among the majority of them that persists to this day. This outcome is remarkable considering that his disclosures were solely oral and he became mentally impaired more than fifteen years ago. It is a testimonial to his pioneering intellectual leadership if not also to his charisma.

It would be risky enough to explore the particular subject of “primary property” if only because of its obscure and esoteric psychological nature. It is all the more so because Galambos cannot now be consulted in person, his audio-tapes are unavailable for independent study and he left no written disclosures on the subject.

Galambos further complicated the study by embedding the subject in an ideology having moral connotations, which to question may elicit an emotional rather than a rational response. As a result of the very misconceptions Galambos feared would arise regarding the meaning of his ideas on the subject, speculations abound and rhetoric tends to supersede substance in inconclusive arguments.

Collegial explorations of Galambos’ notion of “primary property” as a social phenomenon using scientific method are inhibited. Since scientific method was represented by Galambos to be his first, foremost and most fundamental consideration, it would seem appropriate to try to overcome these inhibitions.

No one alive is authorized to speak for Galambos on technical matters, and there is no text of his available to stand in his defense. Thus, I am left to my own devices to determine how to regard my recollections of his teachings. Therefore, I must take full responsibility for these contents. Hopefully, my observations will be more heuristic than critical, and my skepticism regarding some aspects of Galambos’ approach will not obscure my genuine admiration of the man and his work. I have no doubt that the subject matter of his teachings is as important as he represented, importance measured in terms of the advancement of myself, my fellows and our mutual posterity.[2]

GALAMBOS AND STATISM

In his original treatment of how human society works, which he presented systematically to the public for the first time in 1961, Andrew Galambos emphasized the workings of a free market economy under limited constitutional government. As the course developed, he discovered that the integrity of “private property” was the central feature of the existence and operation of a humane society in general and markets in particular. This new insight led him to observe that the word “private” was a superfluous adjective in the term “private property,” pointing out that property is private else it is not property. He also refined his definition and treatment of property in his discourses as follows:[3]

“Property consists of one’s life and all of its non-procreative derivatives.”

Galambos chose this abstract definition to suit his theoretical constructions, which eventually, he claimed, dispensed with political arrangements altogether.

A more operational or phenomenological definition tied to observational procedures would have been more in keeping with his avowed interest in making his studies scientific. Such definitions might have been suggested by anthropology. However, he disdained historical practices, preferring ideal abstractions instead. This stance would come to handicap his appreciation for the very humanity that his theories were meant to complement, and it also handicapped the development of his theory of authentic human action in contradistinction to animal behavior.

One of Galambos’ original supporters was patent attorney Billy Alvin Robbins, Esquire. Robbins attended the first offering of Course 100 in 1961. A polished lecturer and a competent engineer, Robbins became the second person to ever present that course to the public (in the San Fernando Valley in 1962) under the auspices of Galambos, dba the Free Enterprise Institute (FEI). Under the influence of Robbins and others like me and Richard Nesbit who also had prepared in the physical sciences, Galambos made further refinements in his treatment of property, taking particular account of the intellectual variety because of its crucial role in technological advancement, the impetus for social progress. Accordingly, Galambos derived from his definition (above quoted) three classifications of property: (1) “primordial” (one’s own life), (2) “primary” (his own ideas sometimes generalized to refer to one’s entire intellectual estate) and (3) “secondary” (tangible possessions obtained by non-coercive means).

When Galambos introduced the term “coercion” into his elaborated definition of property, he inadvertently embraced a logical circularity that resulted from his definition of coercion as “an intentional interference with property.” Consequently, he relied on “property” to define what was not property in order to define “property.” A further complication resulted from having to determine whether an interference with property was “intentional,” which is difficult if not impossible to observe. These anomalies were troublesome for some of his more conscientious students when they attempted to apply his concept of property in a scientific manner. They found they could not devise a suitable observational test to establish whether or not a particular claim to property as he defined it was authentic.

As a patent attorney, Robbins was keenly interested in property, particularly the intellectual variety. His concentration was on traditional common law practices that were familiar to him in his profession. Galambos did not trust those traditions to deal adequately with such an important matter. He associated them with the statutory practices that had come to dominate intellectual property protection everywhere in society. He stereotyped patent attorneys like Robbins as agents of the State and not contractual counsel to individual innovators. After all, as a member of the Bar, Robbins was an officer of the court and was under oath to be faithful to the “law of the land,” however concocted by the Legislature and interpreted by the Judiciary.

Perhaps because of his European heritage, Galambos did not appreciate that the Anglo-Saxon common law is the generally unwritten and evolving set of rules of jurisprudence that become binding by custom and then only as a result of immemorial usage and universal reception in a community. Thus, the “common law” is a natural phenomenon characterizing volitional human culture. Had Galambos known what Robbins knew, he would have realized that the property violations he abhorred derive primarily from statute law that comes down from the coercive power of the State to preempt the operation of common law among autonomous individuals. Moreover, he would have seen his property principle already at work in society as a feature of the common law phenomenon.

Robbins found an ample non-legal sphere within which his clients could find a measure of protection for their intellectual property. To him, an innovator’s protection would depend primarily on his own behavior and discipline expressed in a manner that could be recognized and respected by his community of peers.

For Robbins, prudence and competence would be the keys to the integrity of property. Whereas, Galambos adopted a moral approach in which “absolute” integrity of property was to be the sole criterion from which institutional sanctions could be justified.

Robbins conceded determination of ownership to a community consensus. By contrast, Galambos derived his authority from a “higher source.” Presumably, that source was nature as revealed by scientific method in the course of development of what he called “Volitional science.” Robbins’ and Galambos’ views on property would be reconciled eventually but not in the courses of the Free Enterprise Institute.

By this time, Galambos had developed an aversion to any State involvement in property protection. So he undertook to develop a theoretical approach “a priori,” which he formally introduced into the curriculum of Course 100 in 1962. Subsequently, he announced that a new course, V-201, entitled “The Nature and Protection of Primary Property” would be offered the following year. In this new course, Galambos would concentrate on “primary property” and would disclose a new theory he had invented for its protection.

While Robbins was presenting Course 100, he attended the first offering of V-201 in 1963 at which time Galambos made a critical and derogatory example of Robbins’ profession, alluding to a conspiracy with the State regarding intellectual property. This “faux pas” would have been bad enough without mentioning Robbins by name and position on the FEI faculty. Although Galambos was unable to demonstrate how his theory would work out in practice, he easily showed how the typical alliance between the legal profession and the government results in corrupt practices with respect to innovators thereby impugning Robbins integrity in public. Robbins was stunned by this unprovoked attack, but he was able to defend his approach to intellectual property protection based on common law practices, accusing Galambos of throwing out the baby with the bath water.

Galambos summarily dismissed Robbins argument, and he insinuated that Robbins, the attorney, was a party to “immoral” professional practices. Robbins was understandably distressed inasmuch as this adversity was unprovoked and uncalled for even if the State had tainted the practice of patent law.

Galambos’ attack on the patent profession was personally painful to Robbins. And it raised the question as to why he did not also jump on the accountants, corporation lawyers, stock brokers, physicians, engineers and bankers in the class whose professions are not only corrupted by the State but are created by it in many cases. After all, since Galambos taught that there was no such thing as a small infringement of property any more than there could be just a little pregnancy, why single out the patent profession for abuse.

Robbins was not the last to encounter Galambos’ accusations of complicity in “primary property theft.” He was just the first and most visible target because he was knowledgeable on the subject and the most likely person in Galambos’ audience to uncover a defect in his new theory. Regardless, this episode was to shape Galambos’ posture in his future expositions and dealings.

Robbins was an authority on common law property practices as well as statute law and his “defense” against Galambos’ attack was very instructive to all those listening. Galambos was unable to listen in the classroom setting so I attempted to mediate this controversy in private based on an appeal to scientific criteria in the belief that such arguments would take precedence in the situation. I was motivated to do this because Robbins was my patent attorney and I considered both he and Galambos to be my colleagues in the quest for learning more about society. However, my efforts were to no avail. Much to my chagrin, I was unable to reconcile the controversy by such civil means. Galambos steadfastly held to a moral (i.e. righteous) as opposed to a scientific (i.e. realistic) position. Robbins had a successful patent law practice, which he was not about to abandon. In the end, Robbins resigned from the faculty of FEI. He also withdrew his patronage of Galambos’ ideological program taking considerable goodwill with him.

TWO VIEWS OF PROPERTY IN IDEAS

Robbins had the credentials for contributing to the theory of primary property and its protection. He had already distinguished himself in this field by obtaining the first patent (not merely a copyright) ever granted by the U.S. Patent Office covering a computer program. Prior to Robbins work, software had not been recognized as an invention. Robbins defended his client’s claims with some ingenuity of his own. He showed that a special-purpose computer is created from a general-purpose computer when a special program or algorithm is installed in it. As a result, his client was the first to be recognized by the public as a software inventor. This insight of Robbins’ would come to have special significance for me in understanding how intellectual property invested in land and natural resources results in creating new forms of property.

Robbins’ approach was most relevant to my efforts to commercialize an invention I was working on at the time. Curiously, Galambos was receptive to some of what I had learned from Robbins. For example, the “proprietary notice,” presented to enrollees of Free Enterprise Institute courses for the first time in 1964, was an adaptation of Robbins’ form of an inventor’s disclosure agreement.

Subsequently, Robbins taught a course at UCLA emphasizing the importance of property in contracts and how to treat intellectual property in them.[4] His approach was technical rather than ideological or moral. The information proved to be a valuable guide not only to personal behavior but also for understanding the fate of ideas in society here and now. I found the existing common-law institutions emphasized by Robbins to be relevant and practical for safely commercializing my inventions in the world as it is.

On the other hand, Galambos’ abstract social inventions for the protection of “primary property” could be implemented, if at all, only through ideological promotion. Such efforts would have to take precedence over all my other goals in life. Even then, there was substantial doubt that this effort would produce a practical alternative to the common-law methods of intellectual property protection. This dilemma impressed me with the difficulties of inventing social institutions in the abstract and then trying to mold humanity by ideological means to fit them into a synthetic structure. To me, this approach was like putting the cart before the horse in the sense that it implied the existence of a mature technology (the cart) without evidence of a science (the horse).

Galambos was able to cut heroic social conceptions out of whole moral cloth, and he was increasingly intent on trying to reduce them to practice. However, his approach boiled down to a programmatic dedication to synthetic contrivances. His program became inconsistent with the methods of natural science and technology he taught so well and was so well prepared to practice. Consequently, Galambos’ students now find themselves confronting certain dilemmas that can be resolved only by resort to humility and skepticism coupled with further innovation, experimentation and study as originally advocated by Galambos. Curiously, the synthetic approach to which Galambos came to devote his powerful mind raises the same questions encountered with any “public policy,” namely, who’s in charge and how did he get his authority?[5]

As he had taught earlier on, Galambos showed how the scientific method provides the only tools applicable for coping with societal insufficiencies and uncertainties. Any new hypothesis is likely to raise dilemmas in applying it to the real world and had Galambos remained faithful to his original scientific approach, the dilemmas that arose in his ideological program would have been at least rational ones rather than the acrimonious moral issues they subsequently became.

A comparison of Galambos’ and Robbins’ approaches to the subject of “intellectual” or “primary” property is instructive. Galambos, the physicist and social theorist, grudgingly used conventional methods of intellectual property protection while introducing his idealized method through verbal discourse, personal example and exhortation. Although he was reluctant to sanction application by others, he fully expected his mechanistic system would eventually succeed as the method of choice in society on the strength of ideological persuasion based on abstract moral arguments.

Robbins, the engineer and patent attorney, recommended common law practices because they were familiar and already widely practiced evidencing social acceptance of intellectual property based on long-standing practicality rather than moral exhortation or government edict. He expected refinements in the actual practices might well occur along the lines envisioned by Galambos as people became more knowledgeable and appreciative of the practice.

Robbins believed innovators could be adequately served by mastering and refining the evolutionary phenomenological practices with which he was familiar. By contrast, Galambos disdained what he knew of those methods in favor of the revolutionary but untested mechanisms he had invented.

References and Notes

1 Astrophysicist/scholar/teacher/entrepreneur, Andrew J. Galambos (aka Joseph A. Galambos) was a colleague of the author’s when both were members of the technical staff of Ramo-Wooldridge, later to become TRW Space Technology Laboratories. This was during the formative period of the aerospace industry when most engineers did not know the difference between an airplane and an artificial earth satellite. There, Galambos, a highly regarded astrophysicist, presented a popular noon-time lecture series to other technical staff members which he called “Astronomy, Astrophysics and Astronautics” (1957-59). Subsequently, he offered similar lecture courses to his students and to the public during a brief tenure as a professor of physics, mathematics and astronomy at Whittier College. This led to his founding The Free Enterprise Institute in Monterey Park, CA, in 1960, through which he developed and presented similar courses subject to tuition including his memorable “Course 100,” entitled “Capitalism–The Key to Survival” (preserved on audio tape). The author was first a student and then a lecturer, having taught this course during 1962-64 under the strict supervision of Galambos. As a result, the author developed both an appreciation for and a divergence from Galambos’ ideas which readers familiar with this background will surely recognize.

2 Alvin Lowi, Jr.,”A Recollection of My Acquaintanship with Andrew Joseph Galambos,” unpublished manuscript available from the author, 2146 Toscanini Drive, Rancho Palos Verdes, CA 90275, December 25, 1995.

3 Andrew J. Galambos, “What is Property?” Thrust for Freedom, Number 2, The Liberal Publishing Co., Inc., Los Angeles, 1963.

4 Billy A. Robbins, Byard G. Nilsson and Robert Berliner, “Patenting and Marketing Ideas,” Business Administration Extension Course No. 898, University of California, Los Angeles, Spring Term, 1972.

5 Alvin Lowi, Jr., “Scientific Method–In Search of Legitimate Authority in Society,” unpublished manuscript available from the author, December 25, 1996 (revised March 8, 1998). See especially p.55 and following.

Section 2

PROPERTIES OF IDEAS VERSUS IDEAS AS PROPERTY

Galambos’ concern for the protection of what he called “primary property” was understandable and his arguments compelling. He noted that the ideas comprising this form of property, once disclosed, can never be recovered and that no disclosure, no matter how skillfully rendered, can assure that the ideas expressed will be apprehended accurately and recalled with fidelity. Thus, he was apprehensive of the fate of an innovator and his works in the population at large while at the same time, insistent that the innovator must be secure in his role and position for any human justice to prevail and social progress to occur.

“Primary property,” as contemplated by Galambos, consists of ideas, conceptions, theories, hypotheses, premises, principles, assumptions, know-how, esthetic works, verbal works, literary works, musical works, mechanisms, processes, methods, enterprises and other suggestions of causes or order imagined by humans. Other than one’s biological life, land and natural resources, primary property according to Galambos, is the precursor to all the creative works of man. This characterization also makes it clear that every human is an innovator, i.e. a creator of “primary property,” at some time or other. It follows then that every man is a vital factor in the creation of his own environment as well as the environment of others.

Articulateness or intelligibility in communication, being what it is, varies widely among individuals. Obviously, the less articulate among us will be disadvantaged in asserting their claims to their innovations, just as the less resourceful and lesser prepared persons in the population will naturally have less access to social benefits–sad but true.

To prescribe the metes and bounds of ideas is a difficult problem even for a skillful writer. That feat is virtually impossible in verbal discourse even for the most eloquent orator. Not only is the communication of ideas challenging, to do so adequately for the purpose establishing them as property in society is more so.

Ideas can be visualized with integrity only in the mind. However, as long as they remain in that abstract domain, they never behave as property in the sense of keeping accounts and making social history. Since we can observe that “property” in some form or other does make creative social history, we are encouraged to believe that property has an intellectual component that is not altogether abstract, where abstract means having an existence apart from the senses.

The kind of “property” Galambos defined as “primary” is wholly intangible, i.e. abstract. It can exist solely in the mind of the beholder. Originally, it is “property” only in the sense that it is “A PROPERTY” of the human mind, a very obscure and esoteric subject. Such “property” only becomes observable when it produces a tangible manifestation. The manifestation may or may not be true to the original conception and the original conception may have been “learned” or suggested by another such that neither originality nor authenticity can be tested by observation. Thus, “primary property” as contemplated by Galambos is metaphysical and must be so distinguished from other forms of “property.” Curiously, “primary property” never loses its metaphysical character even when embodied in tangible works like writings, music or artifacts. It remains a creation of the mind that originated it regardless of any physical or social effects it motivates.

As far as is known, contrary to advocates of mental telepathy, ideas may be propagated among humans only as a result of their tangible expressions. Actually, what propagates is a facsimile of the original idea which, when apprehended and taken to mind by others, becomes their surrogate for the original idea. There are possibly as many such surrogates as there are people but there is only one original. Since such surrogates are the creation of those who hold them to mind, the question arises as to whether such proxies do not in some way become the separate primary property of the beholder. “Independent” conceptions also occur and they may seem identical. Close examination of their tangible manifestations where possible usually reveals distinguishable differences suggesting that true independence is highly unlikely. That it should be so is understandable in terms of the infinite variation in the genetic and memetic makeup of human beings.

Galambos pointed out that primary property is embedded in all other forms of property. This observation raises a serious question for “volitional science,” the name he gave to his studies: How can primary property be disembodied from the tangible varieties? Until that question is answered, “primary property,” as Galambos contemplated it, is an imponderable from a scientific standpoint. Neither neurology nor psychology can illuminate this subject as yet.

To get around this problem in order to proceed with his approach to social science, which he called “Socionomic,” Spencer Heath bundled all the social aspects of “property” into what he called “the subject matter of contracts.”[6] This may seem like an oversimplification but, among other things, it solves, at least potentially, one critical problem regarding “primary property,” namely disclosure. Disclosure would seem to be the first step in realizing the potential social consequences of “primary property.” Presumably, this is how land and natural resources can be brought under proprietary administration.

Heath had anticipated Galambos’ “integrity of property” idea by some number of years.[7] However, in contrast to Galambos, Heath did not attribute any special moral significance to “property.” Thereby, he was able to pursue his scientific quest without distraction from premature or irrelevant moral issues. I would characterize Heath’s approach as anthropological in which common law figures prominently.

INNOVATION AND INNOVATION-TRANSFER

It is instructive to examine the meaning of Galambos’ concept of “primary property” in terms of the fate of an innovator in society. For this purpose, Galambos’ definition of an innovator should be used, namely “one who is a creator of primary property.” Galambos himself represents a case in point.

Consider Galambos’ claim that he is the owner of some ideas other people may hold dear in their minds. Can they be sure that the ideas they contemplate are indeed the same as Galambos’ after they had struggled to apprehend them during and after verbal discourse? Obviously, they did not get them by organ transplantation. They got them by putting some intellectual effort of their own into powering their own imaginations whereby they also became creators, if only in a minor way. In other words, they learned them and thereby made them “theirs” in some sense.

The teacher “teaches.” The student “learns.” In the process, the question arises whether some kind of ownership authority is passed. If the recipients of the information are in doubt as to their proper prerogatives, how can an innocent bystander accredit or discredit the authenticity of a teacher’s claim to exclusivity when there is no way of observing either the subject matter or the industry involved in its creation and transfer.

Galambos explicitly claimed ownership of “his” ideas when he made his disclosures in his classes. He was also careful to inform all within earshot that he was standing on the shoulders of giants and he admonished them to do likewise. In acknowledging his intellectual antecedents, Galambos demonstrated the sort of gratitude he deemed proper and which is practiced to a high degree in academia. His practices also revealed a curiosity of ownership as commonly understood and expressed in the common language. As pointed out by anthropologist Spencer Heath MacCallum, the etymology of the word “own” is the same as for the word “owe.” So to own is also to owe in our culture. However, Galambos raised this idea to a higher level of consciousness than any of his predecessors, albeit not without controversy.

But how does Galambos express his ownership after a disclosure? Is he not limited to the attempt to persuade others to behave mentally and otherwise according to his wishes regarding the “transplanted” ideas? To take a coercive approach to having his way would have been anathema. As a result, the acquisition of ownership of ideas by autonomous other persons comes into question unless they would somehow forfeit that aspect of their inheritance and become puppets. I resist the notion that Galambos had this perverse intent and I doubt that anyone who entered into the FEI disclosure agreement or signed the proprietary notice as a condition of hearing the course had any such an intention.[8]

Indeed, Galambos himself has said that none of his students could understand what was to be expected of him in regard to “primary property” practice prior to his having completed the course in its entirety. Even then, he was not optimistic for a rational outcome. Yet, he bravely offered a tuition refund to any enrollee who had the courage to stand up and say he did not get his time’s-worth from attending all the lectures. Although this rarely happened, Galambos was known to be true to his word.

Perhaps it was Galambos’ pessimism that prevented him from following up on his proprietary notice with contractual negotiations to perfect a coherent “meeting of the minds” with his students whereby the benefits of application and extrapolation would be mutually agreeable. Of course, this would have required that he specify which of his ideas he had reserved for his exclusive use; which were available for exclusive license to others on negotiated terms; and which all signees to the proprietary notice were free to use under an automatic non-exclusive license giving recognition to him on the honorable and subjective value basis that he taught.

Galambos’ exposition of this procedure was eloquent as well as ingenious. He made it seem simple enough to practice by setting forth a system for what he called “primary bookkeeping.” However, as it turned out, his approach to the administration of such a procedure was fraught with difficulties, not the least of which was the demand on his limited time and patience, never mind the same on others. For whatever reason, this procedure was never actually reduced to practice in the administration of the Free Enterprise Institute. It was not even practiced by dedicated members of a cadre of believers Galambos referred to as his “moral island.” If Galambos himself practiced primary bookkeeping as he preached, evidence of it has not thus far been turned up in his archives, although his estate trustees say they are actively looking for such and anticipate negotiating royalty settlements on his behalf regardless.[9]

Galambos’ Estate Trustees express the following policy regarding his intellectual estate:[9]

“…the use (not disclosure) of Prof.’s ideas in one’s own business has always been encouraged; the public use of his ideas becomes ARD [automatic remoteness dilution] upon the complete [italics added] publication of Book 1. Volume 1 of Book 1 consists of the V-50 lectures… Volumes 2 through 4 (estimated) shall consist of the V-201 lectures and master index…”

According to this policy statement, neither disclosure (presumably even a bibliographic reference) nor business application is authorized prior to some indefinite future publication of the transcriptions of his lectures even though business use is said to be encouraged. If this policy is faithful to Galambos’ wishes, it represents a prohibition now and a “Catch 22” later whenever the books are published, if ever. However, the trustees add:

“I cannot say yea oder [sic] nay as to a publishing arrangement [regarding Alvin Lowi, Jr.’s unpublished works]–there is nothing to preclude a joint agreement. In any event, I would be most interested in pursuing this with you.”

It would seem from this latter statement that Galambos left his trustees with a good deal of discretion as to how they would execute his primary property theories. If so, he kept all discretion to himself, now expressed through his estate charter, and left none for his students. I seriously doubt Galambos intended to establish such a double standard. Thus, if the trustees’ understanding of his theories is trustworthy, this dilemma must be attributable to a defect in his theory.

References and Notes

6 Spencer Heath, “Citadel, Market and Altar–Emerging Society–Outline of Socionomy, the New Natural Science of Society“, The Science of Society Foundation, Baltimore, MD, 1957. (c/o Heather Foundation, P.O.Box 180, Tonopah, NV 89049).

7 Heath set forth the grand alternative to politics in principle in a 1936 pamphlet entitled “Politics versus Proprietorship” (c/o Heather Foundation, P.O.Box 180, Tonopah, NV 89049).

8 I acquired some authority in this matter as a result of my involvement in the initiation of that practice and by contributing to the original draft of that disclosure instrument.

9 Charles W. Hayes, CPA, Co-Trustee of the Andrew J. Galambos and Suzanne J. Galambos Natural Estates Trust, Letter to Alvin Lowi, Jr. dated January 19, 1998.

Section 3

CONTRACTUAL DISCLOSURE: A CONTRACTUAL DILEMMA

Because of the subject matter of his discourses, Galambos had to admit that a meeting of the minds between himself and his students regarding any specific commitments to perform any particular task with respect to that subject matter could not be made prior to his disclosures. The proprietary notice was no more than a non-disclosure agreement. Thus, it was simply a covenant acknowledging Galambos’ claim to antecedence at the outset and calling for abstention from disclosure pending further agreement regarding any specific notion or action. No further agreement was specifically forthcoming, and none was anticipated until and unless negotiated after the course when the student would be presumably informed sufficiently to enter into a contract responsibly. Therefore, the proprietary notice was relegated to the status of a ritual. As a result, Galambos never had a bona fide contract with any of his students to behave toward any specific ideas in any particular way. He only had a covenant against certain behavior regarding unspecified ideas, such behavior he classified simply as immoral.

Consequently, abject secrecy was the only way one could be absolutely sure at the outset not to violate the covenant and become stigmatized as an “immoral” actor. This was the result notwithstanding the following language included in the proprietary notice:[10]

“Of course, utilization [of these ideas] is enthusiastically encouraged, subject to mutual contractual recognition of and agreement to such ordinary proprietary considerations as acknowledgement (for primary use) and royalties (for secondary use).”

On the other hand, while subsequent disclosures by Galambos would encourage the student to somehow bring others into the class, he never informed them specifically as to what of the information they received was subject to the covenant against disclosure outside of class. While Galambos may have devised a simple theory in his mind, application of the theory involved a complex and burdensome procedure both for himself and his students to abide. This only goes to show that abstract ideas often lead to complex consequences.

In any case, Galambos’ disclosures were irreversible. The genie could not be put back in the bottle. He inadvertently created a bunch of proxies. All that was left for him to do to try to “protect” himself afterward was to engage in exhortations to “moral” behavior and threats to expulsion from his “moral island.”

Patent attorneys refer to publication by strictly verbal means as “promiscuous disclosure” because they result inadvertently in “dedication to the public.” In this event, the innovator is at the mercy of the “public.” Whether predatory, fair or generous, the “public” is ill equipped to spontaneously recognize abstract conceptions let alone reward the innovator of such. Nature offers no inherent protection from the effects of promiscuity.

It may well be that Galambos did not always behave in harmony with nature. Yet, it is not our place to help nature along one way or the other to punish or reward him. No one appointed us to judge him any more than he us. Our authority, precisely like his was, is limited to allying ourselves harmoniously with nature as best we can. In doing so, we may discover the merit of Galambos’ theory and, if so, find satisfaction in expressing gratitude to Galambos, each in our own way. It would not be appropriate for us to put Galambos in a hero’s crypt. Neither are we contractually bound pay him homage in any particular way. To act as if there were a contract of that sort in effect is highly problematical, to say the least.

CURIOUS SUPPORT FOR GALAMBOS’ THEORY

People are known to not only pay homage but to tithe themselves financially to a church that brings them assorted abstract notions that palatalize their existence. This they do in the name of revered persons of antiquity. However, the innovators of the ideas to whom the church attributes the program it promotes have long since been relegated to a pantheon of heroes. Scholars labor to trace the authorship of the ideas of the current clergy and their theological program. Needless to say, such efforts are not only academic but also controversial.

Notwithstanding the obscurity of the authorship and the questionable authenticity and epistemology of the ideas promoted by the church hierarchy, the existence of the Christian Churches and their considerable annual revenues represents the kind of recognition Galambos envisioned as proper toward the “moral estates” of innovators like himself. While he would have resented any suggestion that his ideas were at all comparable to those embodied in religious institutions, he could not so readily dismiss the likeness of the churches’ and their flocks’ primary property practices to those which he idealized in his theory.

Galambos might well have dismissed the obvious likeness of such religious reverence to his theory of “primary gratitude” by citing one of his favorite Hungarian proverbs:

“When two people do the same thing, it is not the same”.

However, in doing so, he would have encountered an old nemesis, namely, using the ends to justify the means. While it may be easier to admire Galambos’ non-sectarian ends than to embrace the ends of the world’s religious sects, the use of moral intimidation as a means of gaining priority recognition seems a common practice. If moral criteria are brought down from a “higher” authority than is possessed by those affected, it is inevitable that a form of servitude will result, albeit possibly voluntary.

SOME SOCIAL IMPLICATIONS OF PRIMARY PROPERTY

No doubt “intellectual property” (to use the common law term) animates the behavior of an individual and touches all who come into contact with it. How it may be made to behave appropriately in social intercourse is a highly challenging question. Andrew Galambos posed this question in its most general context and claimed to have answered it. Yet, this question remains in the minds of those of us who received Galambos’ instruction. Although he convinced us by his inspired and powerful arguments that such property is the key to the future of the race, perplexities and frustrations persist as to what to do about it. That he left considerable unfinished business in the development of an appropriate theory of social behavior is indicated by the paralysis being endured by his intellectual estate trustees. Clearly, it takes more than a verbal claim or insinuation asserted to sympathetic listeners to create the attributes qualifying ideas to behave as property on a local level. How much more does it take to establish the successful practice of an institution of primary property in society at large in an indifferent world?

Curiously, an innovator can retain exclusive ownership of his “primary” estate with confidence only if he refrains from producing any tangible manifestations of his ideas. He maintains secure control only by keeping his ideas to himself. Any disclosure is likely to result in proxies and imitators who may not be able to trace the origin of the ideas they entertain even if they try. When Galambos applied his definition of “coercion” to primary property, his crisp criterion “intentional interference with property” led to an incoherent, arbitrary and contentious practice. Here is an example of a precise but abstract definition producing a mischievous distraction in application. Evidence of intent is untrustworthy even for a priest in a confessional.

On the other hand, non-disclosure or secrecy prevents ideas from making any social history whatsoever so that the innovator’s satisfaction will be limited to his own mental reveries. In that case, he may become discouraged from a lack of real fulfillment because he will have doomed himself to “contractual oblivion.”

Non-contractual disclosure is the most prevalent behavior of innovators as typified by Galambos. That he established an explicit covenant regarding his intent to maintain proprietorship proves that he was trying to avoid promiscuity. He was simply unable to follow through with the contractual formalities anticipated by his theory. As a result, he took more risk in realizing his aims for recognition and participation than he may have bargained for.

While it is unlikely an innovator would willingly disclose his ideas to a hostile audience, he might willingly forego contractual formalities and dedicate his ideas to the public. This was the posture adopted by Spencer Heath, another practicing patent attorney. Such an act might very well have satisfied his rational self-interest. Having obtained the satisfaction that comes from the conception itself, he might see further profit to himself in terms of the satisfaction that derives from capturing the attention of others and inspiring them in some way. This may in turn create a kind of “resonance” out of which more ideas will be forthcoming. Spencer Heath believed that the more he shared his intangibles with others, the more of them he would have to share. For Heath, disclosure was a means of growing intellectual capital.

On the other hand, the innovator has no duty to disclose anything whatsoever unless he is seeking to control or influence the behavior of others in some manner. In that case, he would seem to be obligated to make a full disclosure of all “pertinent” information to ensure against deception leading to defeat in the long run.

Since there are never enough good ideas to go around, disclosure recipients as potential beneficiaries are likely to be receptive to an innovator’s terms of disclosure, if any. They would be motivated to accommodate him to gain the possible benefits and to encourage the creation of more from where those good ideas came.

In order for an innovator to participate in social benefits, he must risk the potential loss of control of his idea that results from a disclosure in some observable form. Then the question arises as to how he may position himself for receiving such benefits with any confidence. Such know-how is a technology that must be first discovered, then learned, perfected and practiced with diligence. This Galambos was attempting to do with a vengeance.

A promiscuous disclosure is the antithesis of such a posture. So what distinguishes a promiscuous disclosure from non-contractual disclosure? I suggest that the difference is in the attitude of the discloser and the responsibility he willingly assumes for the consequences of his act. When Galambos turned petulant regarding the “quality” of recognition he was receiving from his disclosees, he was flirting with promiscuity since he could not have his cake and eat it, too.

The history of innovation suggests that ideas regularly become the subject matter of contracts whereby innovators successfully participate beneficially in social affairs as their ideas, reduced to practice, benefit all others. This means that ideas do indeed become recognizable to others who accord to innovators some measure of priority or ownership as “creators.” Such “quiet possession,” as it is known in the common law tradition, is based on a rudimentary form of consensus. Such possession is sufficient to eliminate ambiguity to the point where ownership of the idea can be expressed effectively through contract (usually in writing with a modicum of skill) with specific others to act in some kind of concerted effort on behalf of the ideas. (Such contracts are generally known as intellectual property licenses.) This does not happen by accident or by moral persuasion or intimidation. In fact, in history, ambiguity as well as misappropriation is common and contractual incompetence is frequent even when there is no ambiguity regarding ownership or usurpation of such. This is evidence of both the existence of the “primary” form of property as well as the primitive state of its social practice and treatment.

Common law practices regarding “intellectual property” are abundant but they are generally familiar only to patent attorneys who use them in their stock in trade. Such practices are very instructive on how humans have treated property in the past and how they are likely to treat it in the future. I find a striking similarity of treatment in the common law tradition regarding intellectual and real (i.e. land) estates. Indeed, the word “patent” denotes in common language a recognizable title in both fields. It has this value regardless of any standing in court.

A curiosity of common law patents is that they do not compel behavior by physical force. They only signify a claim to property by its owner validated by a process of publication followed by a peaceful defense against all challenges and voluntary compliance with the owners’ claims by others. This is how quiet possession prevails over trespass. A right to sue in court comes not from common law but from statute.

Another peculiarity of common law patents is that a fee-simple sale of an object that embodies an innovation is considered a dedication of the intellectual property to public use. Whereas, no such dedication occurs upon a license to use or a lease of the same object. In any case, the only protection available to the owner regardless of the urgency of his claim is a sanction of quiet possession that is the outcome of a consensus. Yet, no consensus is possible without disclosure and all disclosures, whether by controlled circulation or publication, involve risks to the discloser. This observation seems to sum up the state-of-the-art of intellectual property protection at the present stage of development of civilization.

References and Notes

10 A. J. Galambos, A. Lowi and S. J. Galambos, “Proprietary Notice–Volitional Science (“V”) Courses,” Free Enterprise Institute, Los Angeles, CA, October, 1965.

Section 4

“THE PASSIVE INNOVATOR”: A THEORETICAL OVERSIGHT

Galambos set out to perfect and implement his theory and system for the protection of primary property to make the world safe for innovators as the creators of human progress. His approach to the subject assumed that “innovators are seldom entrepreneurs.”[11] Since such a vision of humanity is defective that may account for many of the problems Galambos encountered in trying to reduce his theory to practice.

A more realistic view of humanity for the purposes of understanding a free society is that all volitional beings comprising it are full-time entrepreneurs whatever else they may be. The alternative is wage slavery or worse. Entrepreneurial activity must include a modicum of innovation in order to succeed in a competitive world without conflict and force. But there is no such thing as a full-time innovator. A man is still a biological organism and he has to eat to remain alive. He cannot eat his ideas no matter how “fertile.” He must “sell” them to others or “sell” others on the merits of engaging in their use for a fee thereby behaving entrepreneurially. The only alternatives he has are mendicancy and predation.

Contracting provides the instrumentation for the exchange anticipated by all this “selling” activity. To be effective, the contractual terms that are to be performed must be practical for and profitable to all parties involved. If they are too stringent or esoteric, they may be useful only to establish injury and fix blame for it in an inevitable default of such a contract.

Concentration on protecting a passive innovator from all possible usurpation regardless of his entrepreneurial competence or prudence leads to a concentration on remedies for injuries that can make no creative social history. Such a theory might not even be able to explain how recourse to restitution of injuries can be effected without invoking further injury or spreading the conflict. What it can do is scandalize plunder as if discouragement of the ugly practice is somehow a remedy, let alone a substitute for know-how in the peaceful and productive administration of property.

SOCIAL EVOLUTION VIS-À-VIS UTOPIA

Society is not some ideal world that exists only in the imagination. It is a real or natural phenomenon that can be experienced and, indeed, is experienced in the preponderance of everyday life. If an ideal world like Galambos’ “Natural Republic” was essential for human society to really function, then most people would have to be existing in a state of suspended animation and remain so until they get a wake-up call from the new regime under construction. Clearly, this is not so. In actuality, society consists of real human beings interacting autonomously in their inimitable manner and such peaceful behavior is very much in evidence at the present time, albeit neither universal nor newsworthy. That people can and will become more competent in expressing their autonomous approaches to life seems to be the natural course of human affairs which is aided and abetted by the science and technology perfected by humankind. If this were not so, civilization would have ended before it started and there would be no clues to the future of the human race as such.

Complete autonomy unabridged by forceful or deceptive intrusions or interventions into the lives of some by others has been idealized as a “free society.” Curiously, such a free society does not offer complete freedom for autonomous individuals. This is because there is no such thing as freedom from the “laws of nature.” Obviously, one can never know enough to always be in harmonious alignment with nature. Conflict with other people is a sure sign of ignorance or worse. Knowing how to recognize the property of others is valuable for avoiding such conflict, and reciprocity is best taught by example. To the extent this is what Galambos had in mind, his work is to be commended and it will be recognized in the future of society.

Galambos’ “Spaceland” concept is actually only a state of mind to be enjoyed by each person who apprehends it. When he associated that idea with what he called “The Natural Republic,” he catered, I believe inadvertently, to false hopes deeply embedded in the human psyche for the construction of an institutional contrivance that would bring real human freedom to the world. In this regard, Galambos was in good company with the likes of John Locke, Benjamin Franklin, Thomas Paine, Thomas Jefferson and James Madison and other less respectable advocates of a Utopia. However, history has been very unkind to such expectations, as Galambos well knew. He developed a somewhat more promising model of progress for human freedom, a vision of society that went well beyond anything imaginable to his liberal ancestors by virtue of his concept of wholly non-political government and his emphasis on entrepreneurship, proprietary administration and innovation. Although he was not entirely comfortable with the implications of his model –specifically that self-government was the only known example that was consistent with it–he could accept the idea of social evolution in terms of the spontaneous order that results from a growing competence among autonomous individuals. This was evidenced by his eloquent treatments of the virtues of honesty and integrity. But he was impatient with the natural processes at work that actually bring about such conditions. I believe his impatience got the better of him when it came to getting across to others the real merit of his vision.

In clinging to visions of engineered social contrivances that are to be “built” to purpose, Galambos indulged in a sort of play-acting among his followers. This approach is reminiscent of earlier social movements calling for the establishment of certain ideal institutions thought to be prerequisite to social life. Sir Thomas More was the first to write such a script.[12] More’s title “Utopia” (meaning “no such place” in Greek) was appropriate to his subject, namely an ideal state of affairs he envisioned in which all is ordered for the “best” of mankind “as a whole” and the “evils” of society–poverty, misery, etc.–have been done away with.[13] Galambos was the first person to enlighten me on this priceless bit of etymology proving he was well aware of the difference between reality and ideality. But obviously, he was not the first person to lose track of that difference in the course of a zealous campaign for setting the world to “right.”

GALAMBOS’ HERITAGE

Galambos was cognizant of the factors that contribute to the accretion and safekeeping of property in society. But he failed to come to grips with them realistically in his own life. To some extent, this was a disciplinary problem with him that every innovator faces. To realize immediate income from a disclosure of heretofore-unimagined notions has to be a great feat of intellect and personality. To have inspired others to accept his ideas and act out his ideological program has to be an even greater one. Galambos took great pride in the fact that he was able to realize immediate income from his lectures, but he was in denial when it came to recognizing that his know-how was inadequate to ensure he would receive the kind of appreciation and recognition he had in mind. This was tantamount to denying that his theory was incomplete or defective as the case may be.

In any event, Galambos compromised his control objectives for financial gain as would most innovators in his circumstances. However, more than would some, he disdained patient investment of his work in a more controllable vehicle such as a controlled-circulation book.[14] One can only speculate as to the reasons for this neglect. Yet, had he not gone ahead with his disclosures without any durable documentation or greater assurances of protection, his ideas may never have seen the light of day, whereupon we would not be here now discussing them and struggling to apply them. He did, after all, have more lucrative business and professional alternatives available to him in his life.[15]

Galambos was famous for the shortness of his patience and the magnificence of his obsession. This combination of “virtues” left him vulnerable to consequences he was not prepared to accept. But he proceeded anyway to give his courses withholding nothing because he felt morally obligated to fully disclose all the information pertinent to the ideological program he was promoting. For some, this was more than they really wanted to know. For others, it was far too little. Afterward, when he saw his ideas being embraced, adapted and implemented by others as he ostensibly wished, he took the last resort of the scoundrel, namely moral intimidation, in an attempt to maintain his exclusivity–as if he could ever have been copied. In this respect, Galambos underrated himself as a person because, if nothing else, his style, passion and insight was inimitable and he obviously enjoyed his work while he was at it. He also realized a great ego profit that comes to very few because few are as well equipped to profit from teaching as he was. Galambos manifested genuine charisma to go with his encyclopedic knowledge.

Galambos achieved a good measure of what he set out to do in terms of developing the traits of honesty, integrity, self-reliance, scholarship and skepticism in his students. To this extent, had aligned himself harmoniously with nature, albeit grudgingly. His extreme idealism seemed to prevent him from taking a full measure of profit from his success. Although he did not acknowledge it, he was also aligned with Thomas Kuhn, Arthur Koestler, F. A. Hayek, Spencer Heath, F. A. Harper and other authors who have pointed out the intimate relationship of intellectual property to technology and thereby to the advancement of civilization. Even without a book to his credit, Galambos probably contributed more to this particular cause than any of them because he so significantly raised the level of consciousness for proprietary administration of intellectual property. Beyond that, Galambos had invented an abstract system of primary property protection, a castle in the sky, so to speak, with which he administered an esthetic experience for most, an intellectual inspiration for some and an emotional ordeal for a few. Because his teachings on the subject lacked immediate practical application, many of his students became frustrated and worried, but hardly more than he was.

As has been suggested previously by at least one of the Free Enterprise Institute’s original faculty members, “common law” experience represents an important source of data in the development of “volitional science.” Little of this perspective seems to have survived in Galambos’ approach. Nevertheless, he definitely established the kind of consensus common law accords owners, albeit not to the extent or level of intensity that he wished. Indeed, he was contemptuous of the merely consensual notion of ownership believing as he did that there was some higher standard of recognition that derived from his theory.

Galambos failed to express his ownership in contractual form. He pronounced moral judgment rhetorically in advance on anyone who would disclose or otherwise make use of his ideas without authorization. He insisted that definite and specific social manifestations of “his ideas” could not be comfortably pursued by specific others volitionally for mutual profit unless explicitly sanctioned by him. So it was more by default than error in theory that he did not live to see more progress with his ideological program. For example, he never exercised an owner’s prerogative by answering the questions of authorization, which a legitimate owner is obliged to do. Thus, his splendid vision of proprietary administration of ideas remains largely untried.

Even now, some of Galambos’ brightest and most enthusiastic students are paralyzed over a moral dilemma regarding their authority to recite let alone research or extrapolate Galambos ideas without specific authorization from Galambos himself or his “moral” trustee. Since such authorization is not now nor ever was forthcoming, those believers so afflicted who persist in their abstinence face intellectual suicide. Once having apprehended Galambos’ grand vision of the future, their thinking about the world can never be the same as before. To think or not to think is a false alternative, which they must set aside in order to become whole persons. That they must act even though they do not understand all they know, or appreciate all the consequences of their actions, is reminiscent of one of Galambos’ favorite quotations. Attributed to the famous electrical engineer and innovator Oliver Heaviside, he said: “Must I refuse to eat because I do not understand the process of digestion.”

Galambos may have made a serious error in connection with his dream of founding of a science of volition. In his expositions of scientific method, he established with great clarity that “validity” and “truth” (which he was inclined to lump together under the term “rationality”) together suffice to prove scientific rectitude. However, he subsequently introduced an “ad hoc” moral criterion that applied only to social phenomena when testing any theories of such.

Originally, Galambos, the scientist and natural philosopher, considered morality to be whatever code of human conduct (ethics) a proper social science would accredit. But he got impatient to implement his ideological program regardless of the maturity of the underlying science. While the specific moral criterion he chose–integrity of property–to be imposed on the usual criteria of scientific rectitude–truth and validity–is a prime candidate for accreditation by science as a “law of nature,” the scientific cycle has yet be completed on the question. Thus, it remains a hypothesis, albeit a highly pregnant one.

Galambos created a serious problem when he took a promising postulate for a science of society and elevated it to the status of parity with the traditional scientific criteria of “rightness.” That decision not only spoiled his epistemological clarity but it also complicated the practice of the scientific method in his chosen domain of phenomena well beyond necessity. It was not like him to dismiss Occham’s advice without a by-your-leave. When he so enshrined his property postulate as a matter of faith, it was never thereafter to be questioned. Then, he came to regard any doubt as to the relevance of his moral criterion of “absolute rightness” to be tantamount to sanctioning immoral behavior. This judgmental posture unnecessarily handicapped him as well as his followers in apprehending, let alone realizing, his grand and esthetic visions of the future of civilization based on scientific method.

One might ask what else could he have done. One thing comes to mind. He could have treated “property” as a property of social phenomena, looking for indications under the rules of scientific method as to the implication for peaceful and creative social behavior, whatever that means.

References and Notes

11 A. J. Galambos, “The Nature and Protection of Primary Property,” Course V-201, Free Enterprise Institute, Los Angeles, CA, October, 1965.

12 Thomas More, “Utopia“, 1516.

13 “The Columbia Encyclopedia in One Volume“, Columbia University Press, New York, 1940.

14 In 1963, a group of enthusiastic patrons of FEI assembled in Galambos’ offices on East Beverly Blvd. to hear a book proposal by this author, then an FEI faculty member. This proposal, complete with an annotated table of contents, was presented to Galambos with his indulgence. A textbook was to be prepared in the manner of Wilson’s treatment of J.W. Gibbs “Vector Analysis, a text-book for the use of students of Mathematics and Physics founded upon the lectures of J. Willard Gibbs“, by E. B. Wilson, Chas. Scribner and Sons, New York 1901.This work had been exemplified by Galambos as a proper one for an author who had more urgent matters to contend with. A limited printing of controlled-circulation, serialized copies was subscribed for in advance at a price of $500 per copy. Only one hundred copies would be printed by FEI and these were already over-subscribed as evidenced by the premiums being offered by the 20 or so existing subscribers for multiple copies with low copy numbers. Galambos was amazed to see this bidding but he avowed that the subscription price was outrageously high and he would not sanction any book of his to be so “overpriced.” At this point in the proceedings, Dr. George N. Haddad, another faculty member and an active bidder for the first ten numbered copies, suggested to Galambos that if he thought the price was too high, he should not buy one. In the end, Galambos shunned this project without further explanation. Needless to say, such behavior had put a damper on the enthusiasm of FEI’s first generation of students.

15 Besides his recognized competence as an astrophysicist and mathematician, Galambos obtained a brokerage license from the National Association of Securities Dealers. During the 1950’s. He built and operated a successful business firm dba Universal Shares, Inc. specializing in the then new field of mutual fund investments using dollar-cost-averaging techniques. He is still remembered more than forty years later by many satisfied clients who got their first real taste of capitalism with his help as he enhanced their personal wealth in the process by acting on his investment advice. After forming the Free Enterprise Institute in 1961, he gradually phased out his investment practice to devote all his energies to his lectures. He eventually became so pessimistic about the health of American capitalism on ideological grounds that he shunned stock market investments altogether. Much to his chagrin, his latter-day disdain for investment in corporate securities through mutual funds proved to be financially disappointing for him and his loyal students.

For Intellectual Property The Property Ideas of Andrew J. Galambos (2015)


 

[First posted June 2015]
by Richard Boren

 

[A note from the webmaster: To preserve the value added by those who discussed (and may continue to discuss) this early version, we will retain this page indefinitely. We’ve released the new Revision as a PDF with a separate public discussion page.]

INTRODUCTION
 

I am in favor of treating ideas as property. The purpose of this paper is to support that position, primarily by using the principles developed by Andrew J. Galambos. In so doing I will address the specific arguments made by N. Stephan Kinsella and others cited by him in his monograph, Against Intellectual Property. I hope to demonstrate that we have no rational choice but to treat ideas as property. It will be seen that doing so is ethical and will not produce negative consequences as Kinsella claims, but instead will be beneficial to both individuals and society. I have tried to represent Kinsella’s views accurately, but for those interested in reading the full text of his paper (and I think you should) it is available at the Mises Institute website and elsewhere.

As noted, my views are primarily informed by the concepts advanced by Andrew J. Galambos, some of which will be disclosed here. I am neither a lawyer, as is Mr. Kinsella, nor a philosopher or other brand of academic, as are most of the people upon whom Kinsella relies. Other than a bachelor’s degree in psychology, I have no generally-recognized academic credentials. However, I did have a multi-year educational interaction with Professor Galambos, and it stuck. It is fair to say that I am a Galambosian, which means that I believe that he was right about how intellectual property should be treated, and much more.

Had it not been for my exposure to Galambos I might well find myself in agreement with Mr. Kinsella on the issue of intellectual property. After all, Kinsella offers the appealing prospect of getting something for nothing, a desire that Galambos identified as basic to human nature, as explained below. In this case the “something” is intellectual property. Unfortunately, as Galambos also pointed out, the laws of physics make it impossible to get something for nothing. As Milton Friedman famously said, “There is no such thing as a free lunch.”

Those readers whose curiosity about Galambos may have been piqued by the references to him in Kinsella’s paper and elsewhere will be presented with facts rather than speculation. It is my experience that the negative comments about Galambos’ ideas always come from people who never took his courses or read his book, relying instead on hearsay and fragmentary information, drawing incorrect conclusions as a result. Mr. Kinsella is in this category. In this work I hope to reveal enough about Galambos’ ideas to convince him and others of their merits.

Galambos was an astrophysicist who observed that the progress that has been made in the physical and biological sciences since what he called the Newtonian Integration has far outstripped that in the social sciences. He believed that the methods of science could be applied to the social domain so as to dramatically increase individual freedom, while dramatically reducing violence and poverty.

Toward that end, Galambos lectured extensively on the scientific method, which I won’t go into. He also taught something else that is fundamental to science, which he labeled “semantic precision,” and discussing it here is essential. The term refers to the use of a vocabulary wherein the words have the same meaning to all participants. Words such as mass, energy, electron, wave, molecule, cell, neuron, and so forth come to mind in the physical and biological sciences. Clearly, progress would be difficult if not impossible without agreement on the meaning of these terms. Galambos noted that one of the major barriers to solving mankind’s greatest social problems was that the relevant terminology was still fuzzy at best. For example, the meaning of words such as “freedom,” “moral,” and “justice” varies from person to person and community to community. One of his tasks was to correct that.

In his courses Galambos provided what are called “stipulated definitions.” Anyone who has ever taken a course in any field will be familiar with having the instructor introduce various terms as the course goes on. Students are expected to learn them and to communicate using them. That was the way Galambos taught his courses, defining terms as he went along and never deviating from using them in the same way every time. All in all, the Galambos glossary contains about 100 words and phrases, the majority of them introduced in his basic course, V-50. This is the language that I think in today, and the concepts form my world view. I’ll use some of the words and phrases in the rest of this document, doing my best to use them as Galambos intended.

Galambos founded the for-profit Free Enterprise Institute (FEI) in the early 1960’s and operated it successfully until the mid-1980’s when he was struck by Alzheimer’s disease, eventually passing away in 1997. He made good money teaching his ideas to willing students in a university-type lecture setting, but at a lower price than college courses of comparable length, and with a money-back guarantee to boot. Most of what he taught wasn’t available anywhere else, either at that time or since. I attended FEI classes from 1975 to 1979, and accumulated about 1,000 hours of lecture time. It was far and away the most exciting and valuable educational experience of my life.

Galambos planned to write a book and even pre-sold it to his students, who paid for it in advance. I am one of those students. Publication was targeted for 1987 (not coincidentally the 300th anniversary of the publishing of Newton’s Principia Mathematica), but he never wrote it. Instead, in accordance with the book purchase contract, a lightly-edited transcript of his 1968 delivery of Course V-50, together with an extension called V-50X, given in 1976, was published by his trustees in 1999 as Sic Itur Ad Astra, Volume One (SIAA). The Latin title means, This Is the Way to the Stars. I own a copy and will be quoting from it. I also own a recording of Senior Lecturer Jay Stuart Snelson’s 1978 delivery of the course, to which I have listened numerous times.

The trustees have a contractual requirement to publish the remaining volumes, which were to have included the contents of Course V-201, the course Galambos called his most important. However they have refused to do so, saying that it was a mistake to have published anything. In line with that position, they have withdrawn Volume One from sale. I strongly disagree with these actions. In my opinion, by Galambos’ standards what his trustees have done is criminal.

One of the results of their actions is that Galambos remains an obscure figure, and I find myself having to write this. Fortunately, in lieu of the unpublished remaining volumes I have access to the notes that Jay Snelson used when he taught Course V-201. These notes are reportedly a virtual transcription of the lectures Galambos delivered. Finally, I have my own student notes.

Galambos worried that some students might misconstrue, misapply, or incompetently apply his ideas and bring unfair criticism on them. In an effort to control those things as much as possible, he required students to sign a non-disclosure agreement. This has been misunderstood and even ridiculed by some, as when Kinsella says, “…his own theories bizarrely restrict the ability of his supporters to disseminate them.” For the record, the agreement did not say that students could never discuss or use the ideas, only that doing so would require Galambos’ permission. Such agreements are common when intellectual property must be exchanged in confidence. For example, this may be done to protect trade secrets, or to withhold the existence of a scientific discovery until it is confirmed or can be turned into a product. Given that Galambos’ stated purpose was to bring about positive social change based on his ideas, it was clear that at some point they would be disseminated and used. However, in the interim, the lack of publication, coupled with piecemeal, out-of-context disclosures by some students, has led some people to gross misunderstandings of what Galambos taught, said, and did.

Importantly, Galambos did not require book purchasers to sign a non-disclosure agreement. With that book he intended to put his ideas into the marketplace. Therefore, in my opinion I am free to discuss the content of both V-50 and V-201, keeping in mind that the pitfalls of out-of-context disclosures still exist. Therefore, such disclosures as I make herein will represent my best effort to do no harm. That said, by definition the disclosures are out of the context of Galambos’ entire bundle of ideas. There is no substitute for hearing all of them, which combine to constitute a complete system that is both internally consistent and consistent with the laws of nature, including human nature. However, I have presented only those concepts that are both relevant to intellectual property and which can be understood on their own. I hope that I have done this well.

Galambos saw the American Revolution as a major turning point in the history of man—the end of the idea that we need a ruler, as expressed in the Declaration of Independence. In 1776, “ruler” meant “king,” but the broader meaning was any ruler at all. He recognized that the Constitution instituted a new kind of rulership, and set about trying to find ways to “fix” it. (He also noted that the Constitution lacked a glossary, with the resulting lack of semantic precision leading to centuries of squabbles over the meaning of words and phrases.) However, within a few years he concluded that all political systems—even democracy—relying as they do on coercion, are not only morally wrong but are functionally unable to achieve their noble goals. He abandoned political government and came up with a non-political, non-utopian, total system for achieving peace, prosperity, and freedom.

Much of his system was revealed in Course V-50 (a catalog number, with “V” standing for “volition”) which consisted of 16 sessions, each of approximately three hours, plus three question-and-answer sessions of similar length, called “workshops.” His teachings came to be known as “Volitional Science,” a term coined by Jay Snelson and put into use to distinguish the concepts from what most of the world calls “social science.”

KEY CONCEPTS DEFINED

In the first session, students were told that the course was about freedom, and how to build it (not fight for it, march for it, vote for it, or pray for it). The first step was to define “freedom.”

Freedom: The societal condition wherein every individual has full (100%) control of his property.

At this point you might say, “That’s impossible,” and stop reading. Perhaps another of Galambos’ stipulated definitions will keep you engaged.

Impossible: That which would violate a law of nature.

By definition, laws of nature cannot be violated. However, there is no known law of nature that will prevent the attainment of freedom. As a way of illustrating this, Galambos pointed out that manned, heavier-than-air flight was never impossible; we just didn’t know how to do it until the various problems were solved, principally by the Wright brothers. The fact that something is difficult does not mean that it is impossible. Galambos acknowledged that it will be difficult to build freedom, at least initially, but it is not impossible. Your reading of this paper is a step in the right direction.

As an aside, I consider the definition of impossible to be one of the most valuable things I learned from Galambos. I learned that if a violation of a law of nature is observed, it simply tells us that the law wasn’t a law in the first place. Since learning this there have been countless times when I’ve heard someone say, “That’s impossible,” and known it not to be true. I’ve also heard the statement, “Anything’s possible,” and known it to be false.

You should also know that freedom as Galambos defined it is a goal, to be approached asymptotically. We can get close, but because of the nature of humans we’ll never quite reach perfection. Of course there is always a statistical possibility of that happening, meaning that at one particular instant every human will behave himself, but in general there will always be at least a few miscreants interfering with someone else’s property. The society that Galambos conceived of is based on principles that will tend to minimize such property interferences in the first place, and to quickly rectify them when they occur. His courses revealed those principles and showed how to create a society where, for all practical purposes, freedom is a fact. (I don’t know what kind of social features Mr. Kinsella wants, but I’ll speculate that he would like what Galambos had in mind.)

This discussion of freedom, taken out of the context of his full course, is an example of the out-of-context problem that worried Galambos. So here’s some needed context: To complete the definition of freedom, Galambos had to define property. He said that he would define it “differently from the way it has been defined before” and that “the entire theory of Volitional Science depends on it. ‘Property’ in Volitional Science is just as fundamental as ‘mass’ is in physics.” [SIAA p. 21]

Property: A man’s life and all non-procreative derivatives thereof.

It can be seen that this excludes children as property. Galambos later changed “man” to “volitional being” so that it would apply to other volitional (choice-making) beings in the universe.

Property is of three types:
Primordial Property: Life
Primary Property: Thoughts, ideas, and actions
Secondary Property: Tangibles

Galambos’ view of property conforms to the principle of Occam’s razor. His definition (a person’s life and its non-procreative derivatives) is simple, and all types of property receive the same treatment. Kinsella, on the other hand, wants us to treat life and tangibles in one way, and intellectual property in the opposite way, all the while saying that intellectual property isn’t property in the first place. To be sure, Occam’s razor is only a guide, but it is one that has proven quite reliable.

In a state-free society there would be no “lawmakers” and no legislated law. Instead, there would be what is known as “common law,” a set of principles by which behavior would be measured and disputes resolved. If common law was based on Galambos’ principles and definitions, it would acknowledge that you own your life, your thoughts, your ideas, your actions, and the tangible things that people usually mean when they talk about “property” today. In that society you would have a right to full (100%) control over all three types of your property. When it came to choices regarding the disposition of your property, the decision would always be yours and no one else’s. You might give some or all of it away, but that decision would be yours.

The ownership of primary property was, in Galambos’ view, essential to achieving freedom, from which lasting peace and prosperity would spring. Galambos held that freedom, once attained, would be indestructible. A similar belief was later voiced by Murray Rothbard in For a New Liberty, where he points out (I’m paraphrasing here) that if a group of people was dropped into a state-free place they would not turn around and appoint a subgroup to rule them, and would consider such a proposal ridiculous. Other modern authors such as Michael Huemer, Carl Watner, David Friedman, Hans-Hermann Hoppe, Morris and Linda Tannehill, and Stefan Molyneux have made much the same observations in describing how the institutions of a totally voluntary society would function without devolving into a new state. To anyone who is as yet uncertain as to how such a society would function, you will find the answers in the works that I have listed below.

WOULD PATENTS AND COPYRIGHTS EXIST IN A STATE-FREE SOCIETY?

At first glance, the spirit of U.S. patent and copyright law might seem to be generally consistent with Galambos’ views on primary property, meaning that it should be protected. I have been fortunate to live my life in the USA, where people who create primary property can, and frequently do, achieve fame and/or fortune from it. Although our system of patent and copyright laws are provided and coercively enforced by the state, they at least have the nominal goal of protecting primary property. The ordinary citizen knows that if he has primary property that he thinks is valuable there are steps he can take to protect his interest in it.

Although Galambos sought to protect primary property, he rejected the methods in use today. In SIAA he said:

The patent is a coercive monopoly, with the state on the side of the one who has the patent and to hell with everybody else! And how about the copyright? That’s nothing. The copyright doesn’t have any function whatsoever. Do you know what the copyright protects? How many of you know what the copyright protects? Phraseology. You can take a book and rewrite it in different words; steal the idea and there’s nothing that the copyright does to protect you against that. You can reword an essay, a poem, a story; the copyright protects nothing except the phraseology. It’s a farce. [SIAA p. 632]

I suspect that Mr. Kinsella would agree with this. However, when people in his camp criticize innovators such as the Wright brothers for using the power of the state to protect their ideas, I must remind them that they were using the only tools and knowledge that were available at the time. They did not have the advantage of living in a state-free society operating under common law based on the rational principles advanced by Galambos.

As noted, Galambos rejected all attempts to solve problems by political action. None of his insights, discoveries, hypotheses, or proposals requires political action of any sort. He believed that all political entities inevitably collapse and that all such current entities, including the United States, are collapsing now. His prescription was to ignore them as much as possible without incurring their wrath and going to jail or worse, and to set about building a free society in parallel, one that would survive the collapse. With the advent of the Internet, which allows communities to exist in cyberspace, this is much easier to achieve, and on a larger scale, than it was in Galambos’ day.

Although we don’t yet have a state-free society, that was Galambos’ goal and his frame of reference. Therefore, I will not address any of Kinsella’s complaints that have anything to do with state-created patent and copyright laws, their imperfections, their cost to administer, or their negative consequences, and will focus only on activity in a state-free world.

I will also not address anything having to do with “natural” rights, “inalienable” rights, or rights “endowed by a creator.” To Galambos, the only rights are contractual. He said:

I don’t agree that we are endowed with any rights at all. We are endowed with our lives and our brains and the natural resources to which we have access. We are endowed with no rights whatsoever. That’s an error right there. We have to earn rights. Rights are man-made…. [SIAA p. 97]

My first encounter with Against Intellectual Property was in 2009, when a Google search for “Galambos” led me to a 2006 blog post by Mr. Kinsella on the Mises Institute website under the headline, “Galambos and Other Nuts.” Since I was certain that Galambos wasn’t a “nut,” I was disturbed to see that Kinsella had applied that label while admitting that he was almost totally ignorant of what Galambos had said. I added a comment, comparing Kinsella’s remarks to those of a critic who attacks a movie without having seen it.

I was surprised to learn that Kinsella—or anyone—had written a paper attacking intellectual property. I had no idea that anyone in a non-communist country could possibly be against owning it like any other property. I began to read Kinsella’s paper, but soon found what I thought were fatal errors and didn’t finish it. I also came across something written by Jeffrey Tucker. He said that after six years of thinking about Kinsella’s paper, he finally came to embrace Kinsella’s view and had concluded that “intellectual property is a form of exploitation and expropriation that is gravely dangerous for civilization itself.” To me, it is that belief that is gravely dangerous. Kinsella and Tucker have some influence in the libertarian community but, in my view, the influence is in the wrong direction on this matter. As a result I felt compelled to write this paper.

Recently, on the Liberty.me website, Tucker answered a subscriber’s question with the following:

It’s hard to square IP [intellectual property] with private ownership. We might be talking about different things. If you have an idea and write software, record a song, or whatever, there is nothing wrong at all with taking steps to retain your market monopoly on that product. People do this every day. The one and only problem is state grants of monopoly. I guess I’m doomed to be frustrated that the ultimate article/treatise on this subject is not written.

I have good news for Mr. Tucker. Although Galambos’ teachings may not be the “ultimate” article/treatise, it gets us over the hump. It shows how to protect intellectual property without any state intervention, indeed, without any state. If “the one and only problem is state grants of monopoly” then Mr. Tucker’s problem is solved. Unfortunately, that still leaves Mr. Kinsella, who claims that ideas aren’t property, and that attempts to treat them as such would require unethical control of other people’s property. This is his view even in the absence of a state. Since Mr. Tucker has embraced Kinsella’s paper wholeheartedly, it would seem that he agrees with these positions.

This leads me to mention an observation. It seems that the leading libertarian writers, while offering powerful defenses of life and of physical property, are usually silent when it comes to intellectual property as can be seen by looking at the indices of their books under “property” and “intellectual property.” (The opposite is true for Lysander Spooner’s The Law of Intellectual Property, which argues magnificently for intellectual property and the perpetual ownership thereof.) For most authors, it’s as though such property doesn’t exist, a surprising thing in view of the fact that their work product is ideas. Several of them paint an elaborate picture of how a libertarian society would function, with everything provided by private means, but never mention how intellectual property would be treated. Perhaps they don’t know how to handle it and simply ignore it. When I encounter these works I say to myself, “If only you knew what Galambos had to say.” With this paper I hope to effectively convey that information.

When I began to read Kinsella’s paper, I was struck by his statements that only scarce things can be property, and that ideas are not naturally scarce. Therefore, he said, ideas cannot be property and cannot be owned. I find problems with both of his premises and with his conclusion.

DOES SOMETHING HAVE TO BE SCARCE TO BE PROPERTY?

Kinsella begins the section of his paper called “Property and Scarcity” by saying, “Let us take a step back and look afresh at property rights.” He then goes on to claim (aided by a number of quoted sources) that it is scarcity, and the possibility of conflict over the use of scarce things, that gives rise to property rights as a means of avoiding that conflict. To this he adds that such rights must be visible. They must also be just, with the first-occupier homesteading rule providing the standard of justice.

Galambos also “stepped back and looked afresh at property rights.” The result was his afore-mentioned definition of property, first published in 1963: Property is a man’s life and all non-procreative derivatives thereof.

There is no mention of scarcity in Galambos’ definition. Rather, a person’s life and everything that person generates, tangible or intangible, scarce or not, is his property, and he owns it by default. Galambos’ goal was to show us how to create a society in which every individual has full control of that property. He then defined the societal condition in which such control existed as “freedom.” We can create that society without ever pondering the concept of scarcity.

Would this be a just way of doing things? Yes, because the first-occupier homesteading rule would apply. Galambos recognized that multiple people could independently have the same idea. His definition of property includes that possibility. Your ideas are your property. It doesn’t matter how many other people have the same idea, or when—it belongs to each of you. Although Galambos did not cite the homesteading rule as the means of establishing ownership, in effect he was saying that just as an idea can be used by more than one person it can be homesteaded by more than one person. By thinking it, you have homesteaded it. Then, by registering it, you have documented your homesteading claim, thus creating the needed visible borders and establishing your ownership versus the non-ownership of those who haven’t independently had the idea. With this system in place, conflicts could arise but they would only be about determining independency.

But let’s not forget about scarcity entirely. Kinsella says that ideas are not scarce, but are superabundant. There’s much more on this in the next section, but for the sake of argument, let’s agree with him for a moment. Suppose that—horror of horrors–some non-scarce thing was included in the definition of property. In my view it wouldn’t matter. If someone calls a non-scarce thing their property, they will simply be ignored by the rest of society. Because the thing is abundant there will be no reason for conflict.

To Mr. Kinsella’s credit, he at least acknowledges (I would say grudgingly, in Footnote 89) that there could be alternative systems to his:

Of course, in anarcho-capitalism, it is difficult to predict what extensive contractual regimes, networks, and institutions will arise. Various enclaves or communities may well require their customers, patrons, or “citizens” to abide by certain IP-like rules.

I wonder whether Mr. Kinsella ever thought about what those “IP-like” rules might be. I don’t know what he means, and I wish he had given us an example. In my view, something is either intellectual property or it is not, and the distinction has been made clear by Galambos, seemingly eliminating the possibility of anything being IP “like.” Galambos, for his part, did in fact create a set of basic rules for IP, and you are reading them here.

Mr. Kinsella is free to advocate for a society in which ideas aren’t recognized as property. As suggested by his footnote, he might do just that and start an anarcho-capitalist enclave or community where the rules explicitly deny that intellectual “property” is property at all. Indeed, that’s what he seems to want, and he could move there. However, his pronouncements could not keep the community next door from using Galambos’ definition and giving ideas the same property status as human life and tangibles, with specific rules and protections fitting the unique requirements of each. If the concept failed in practice, then that would be that.

I believe that not only is it possible for a community to successfully treat ideas as property, but that it will work for society in general, not just enclaves. I encourage creative readers to begin thinking about the advantages of living in a world where common law would treat your ideas as your property, to do with as you please. Then think about living in Kinsella’s world.

SOME IDEAS ARE NATURALLY SCARCE

There is a problem with Kinsella’s premise that ideas aren’t naturally scarce. In fact, he says that ideas are so plentiful that they should be free, as air is free. As a quantitative matter he is correct because every human constantly generates ideas. And, as Galambos pointed out, ideas cannot be consumed. They cannot be used up. As a result, ideas exist in numbers beyond counting. In the quantitative sense ideas are not scarce. But it is not the quantitative sense that matters when it comes to deciding whether to treat them as property.

The problem with Kinsella’s argument is that he speaks of ideas as though they were a homogenous group, which they are not. Specifically, he does not distinguish between useful ideas that work to achieve their purpose, and ideas that fail to do so; in other words, good ideas and bad ideas. He also does not distinguish between important ideas and unimportant ideas.

Importance: The measure of the total amount of property affected.

Ideas that are both good and important are scarce. This is what I call qualitative scarcity, and it is what matters. The qualitative scarcity of ideas refers to a scale that begins with an enormous number existing ideas, varying widely in utility and importance. Of these, a small number are both important and good. For example, the formula, E = mc2, first disclosed in 1905, is an important, good idea, at the top of the scale. Ideas like this are incredibly scarce. There may be only a few outstanding ideas per generation, and we have only reached even that small production since Newton.

Interestingly, the economic value of the discovery that mass and energy are equivalent was not quickly or generally recognized. Even Einstein himself saw little practical application. How would you turn it into money? Galambos observed that this failure to recognize the importance of a discovery is the typical case. We just cannot see all of the implications and possibilities. Even as late as 1932 Einstein said, “There is not the slightest indication that nuclear energy will ever be obtainable. That would mean that the atom would have to be shattered at will.” Therefore it is likely that in 1905, and for decades thereafter, he would have licensed the idea at a very low price in comparison to its ultimate economic value. This is just one of several natural conditions that will work to restrain the price set by the innovator for the use of his primary property. More of those constraints will be discussed below.

The greatest scarcity possible is something that doesn’t exist, in other words, something that is infinitely scarce. An idea that has not yet been thought of is infinitely scarce. We are today surrounded by the bounty stemming from ideas that were once infinitely scarce.

An idea that has been thought of, but has not been disclosed by the innovator, exists in a quantity of one. An idea that has been disclosed to one other person who has agreed not to disclose it exists in a quantity of two, and is scarce. According to Kinsella, it is scarcity that qualifies something as property. Scarcity is necessary, he says, because it is only scarcity that makes conflict possible. Since it is clear that ideas can be scarce, by Kinsella’s standard it follows that they are property after all.

At the other end of the scale from the few ideas that are both extremely good and extremely important, there are unimportant ideas, both good and bad. These comprise the vast majority of ideas. However, nothing about them disqualifies them from being property. It only makes them property of little value, no value, or even negative value. Therefore they have little or no market demand and there is no incentive to have conflict over them. But things change. An idea that is both good and important today may be neither tomorrow, and vice versa. The surest way to avoid a future problem is to treat all ideas as property from the start.

Galambos proposed a system whereby all ideas, even the best and most important ones, would ultimately be available on the most reasonable terms imaginable, effectively removing any rational reason for conflict. I will describe this in detail later, but mention it now so as to begin to put to rest the idea that treating ideas as property will result in the owners of those ideas (and perhaps their heirs) having a stranglehold on civilization’s progress. Such a conclusion could only be reached by someone who doesn’t know what Galambos proposed, has let his imagination run wild, and has jumped to a pessimistic conclusion. Perhaps it’s the result of seeing too many movies where a villain seeks world domination by controlling something crucial to human survival.

In addition to erroneously denying that there is any natural scarcity of ideas (which there is when it comes to quality and importance) Kinsella says that if you decide to treat the supposedly non-scarce ideas as property anyway, you will have created artificial scarcity. By this he means scarcity created by statute law in the form of patent and copyright.

Kinsella and Galambos agree that the state should end, thus putting an end to legislated laws such as patent and copyright. However, Kinsella also wants to end any effort to protect primary property in any way other than by contract. He believes that unless you are bound by such a contract you have no obligation to the innovator, and you cannot legitimately be prevented from using his primary property. Galambos, on the other hand, would protect that property just as much as tangible property is protected. A car thief can legitimately be prevented from using the car, and an idea thief can be barred from using the idea.

Why would anyone object to letting a person who comes up with an idea protect that idea? One possibility is that Mr. Kinsella doesn’t seem to place much value on the achievement we call innovation. His use of the phrases “merely innovating… merely authoring an original expression of ideas… merely thinking of and recording some original pattern of information” [the emphasis on merely is mine] suggests that he puts innovation pretty low in the hierarchy of human achievement.

Galambos had the opposite view. In Session One of V-50 he defined innovation.

Innovation: Learning how nature operates is called discovery, harnessing it is called invention; and the two together are called innovation.

All told, the word “innovation” appears about 100 times in SIAA, always in a positive context. To Galambos, all progress begins with innovation, and innovators occupy the figurative top slot. Protecting the work of innovators (their primary property), as well as their physical well-being, is the starting point for achieving freedom.

CONTROL OF OTHERS’ PROPERTY IN DEFENSE OF YOUR OWN IS ETHICAL

Now let’s look at what Kinsella asserts would be the negative effect of innovators having total control of their primary property and allowing them and no one else the ability to set the terms and conditions of use. He would approve of Innovator Brown making a contract with User Green wherein Green agrees to Brown’s terms and conditions. However, if Green then gives the idea to Black, Black is not bound by that contract and is free to do as he pleases with the idea. Any attempt by Brown to stop Black would be, in the view of Mr. Kinsella, exercising unethical control over Black’s own property.

He goes further and equates control with ownership. I think that’s simply not true, and wouldn’t respond to it here except for the possibility that it bears on Kinsella’s argument in a way that I do not see. Therefore, I’ll mention that Galambos made a clear distinction between the two words. It also gives me a good place to introduce two fundamental concepts.

Control: The ability to make volitional decisions concerning the disposition of property.

Ownership: The total, permanent, and moral control of property until voluntarily transferred by the owner, where possible.

Moral action: Any action that does not involve coercion.

Coercion: The attempted, intentional, interference with property. Coercion can be by force or by fraud.

The phrase, “where possible,” refers to the fact that it is not possible to sell the ownership of an idea, only its use, in the same way that it is not possible for an author to sell his authorship, only the right to read or reprint his work. This is because innovation and authorship are historical facts, which cannot be changed. The result is that the ownership of primary property is in perpetuity—automatically.

Permanent moral control is ownership. Temporary control is of two kinds—rental, which is moral, and theft, which is immoral. My control of your property, whether moral or immoral, does not confer ownership.

Mr. Kinsella says that “all libertarians” favor property rights in tangible things and rights in one’s own body. These things can be owned. However, in his view intellectual property cannot be owned. (I find it curious that he hasn’t found a better word than intellectual property to describe something that he says isn’t, and cannot be, property.) This seems to expose a logical inconsistency. If I understand Mr. Kinsella correctly, these would be his positions on property protection in the state-free, anarcho-capitalist world that he appears to want:

  • I can protect my primordial property (life) by putting people on notice that I do not want them to physically harm me. Then, if they try, in self-defense I can block their blows or even, as a last resort, use deadly force. Such actions would control other people’s property–their arms, their fists, their clubs, their guns, and would be permissible. I could seek restitution from the attackers for any harm I suffered.
  • I can protect my secondary property (tangibles) by putting people on notice that I do not want them to take it without my permission. If someone tries, in defense I can block their entry with a lock on my door. If they defeat that lock, I can continue to defend my secondary property by physical means, controlling their arms and legs and such other property as they had brought with them. This control of someone else’s property would be permissible. If despite my efforts they were successful and took my property, and then sold or gave it to others, it would still be my property and I could reclaim it by using force if necessary, and I could seek restitution from them for any loss.
  • I can protect my primary property (ideas) by putting people on notice that they cannot be used without my permission. In defense I can take data security and contractual steps. If someone defeats those measures and steals my ideas I can seek restitution from him of such damages as I might be awarded. However, if that person sells or gives my ideas to other persons, any defensive actions against them, such as preventing them from using the ideas or attempting to obtain restitution, would unethically control their property, and would not be permitted.

How can it be ethical to control the property of others in defense of primordial and secondary property, but unethical to do the same thing in defense of primary property? In a civilized society, I don’t have to ask you not to hit me or not to steal my money. I can walk down the street and not worry that a random pedestrian will punch me in the nose. I can set my wallet down on the table and not worry that a fellow restaurant patron will snatch it the minute I glance away. Why should I accept a society where I do have to ask others not to steal my ideas, and where I would have no protection if they do? Mr. Kinsella is certainly free to set up a community where those are the rules, but I wouldn’t want to live there.

STEALING IDEAS IS IMMORAL AND HARMFUL

As previously stated, communities can be formed with members creating and agreeing to follow whatever common laws they desire. Although Galambos did not use the term “common law” to describe the societal rules that would be derived from the principles he taught, that seems to be his meaning. I, for one, want to live where common law recognizes ideas as property and protects them just as it protects life and tangibles, with this definition in effect.

Stealing: Taking property without the consent of the owner.

Stealing is a form of coercion and is immoral. However, all of us want to get things with as little effort as possible and stealing is one way to do it. But there are powerful social taboos against stealing. We accept that it is wrong to control someone else’s primordial property without permission or payment (a form of theft called slavery) or to control someone else’s secondary property without permission or payment (property theft). But when it comes to taking someone’s primary property without permission or payment (also property theft), Kinsella and others think that’s just fine. Their first justification is that ideas are not property in the first place, so they can’t be stolen. But we’ve seen that ideas are property after all, and therefore can be stolen.

Their second justification for using ideas without permission is that restricting the use of an idea is creating “artificial scarcity,” which is supposedly bad for society. According to Mr. Kinsella, it is ethical to counter this by simply using ideas without permission. He claims that there is no harm to the innovator because, unlike a theft of tangible property, the owner still has his idea. If you steal a chair the owner can no longer use it, and that’s bad. But if you steal someone’s idea, everyone, including the owner, can use it, so Kinsella says there can be no conflict. Apparently it is supposed to be obvious that there is no victim. It’s a win-win proposition, Kinsella seems to say. That is a very appealing scenario, so people may not examine the reasoning too closely—if they examine it at all.

But, as an example, let’s look at the act of downloading music without permission and without paying for it. Defenders of the practice say, “The musicians are still rich, aren’t they? Sure, they can’t make money by selling albums anymore, but they just have to adapt to the new business model, which is to make their money by touring. They haven’t been harmed and the rest of us have the music.” The reality is that the “new business model” is a rationalization for the change musicians have had to make to try to compensate for the activities of thieves from which they have little protection. You might as well say that a neighborhood full of burglars and petty thieves would be a “new residential model” for homeowners, and that they should adapt by buying guns.

Generally speaking, it is easy to take ideas without permission, and this is perceived as a negative. There is even an attempt to rationalize the practice by saying, “In the digital age it is so easy to copy things like music, books, movies, data, and other forms of primary property that we should stop trying to prevent it. That sort of defense is obsolete, and is a lost cause.” However, being able to easily steal something doesn’t make the theft moral, any more than the ease of capturing African natives made slavery moral.

I’m struck by the fact that the defenders of primary property theft do not make the slightest suggestion that the thieves should make at least some payment to the person whose primary property has been expropriated. No, it’s just straight-out theft. Why is that? Why doesn’t the downloader of “free” music, music from which a number of people are trying to earn a living, music that none of them want downloaded without payment, and music that gives the downloader pleasure, say, “I love this song! I’m going to pay a royalty. I’d feel bad about myself if I didn’t.” Why doesn’t the seller of counterfeit merchandise or the invention thief do the same? Of course the reason for some of them is that they are simply criminals and know that they are criminals. But others, those who we otherwise think of as “decent people,” have been given superficial, pseudo-intellectual rationalizations for their behavior, and have bought into them because it’s what they wanted to hear.

It’s the second group that bothers me most. That’s because I fear that many good people, having not given the matter much thought, and being driven in part by the desire to get something for nothing, are easy prey for the fallacy that not only is there is no harm in primary property theft, but that protecting it (creating artificial scarcity) is a social evil, and blocks the progress of civilization.

The society that many libertarians claim to want—one without a state—is one in which the activities of the individual are restricted only by what is known as the non-aggression principle. I assume that Mr. Kinsella subscribes to this view. And yet he and some of the other supposed champions of liberty believe it is perfectly acceptable for someone to take primary property from its owner and use it any way they wish, even when the owner explicitly asks them not to do so, and without any financial payment or credit for the idea. These same staunch libertarian, anarcho-capitalist folks say they are all for private property rights, but when it comes to ideas—primary property—they have no problem turning them over to the collective without the owner’s permission. With that mindset, the obvious next step is the taking of tangible property. The phrases, “He’ll never miss it” or “He can afford it” are the functional equivalent of saying, “Using an idea without permission does no harm.” After all, if we can redistribute (steal) ideas, the source of all tangible property, then why not redistribute (steal) that property too?

In Frederic Bastiat’s landmark essay, What Is Seen and What Is Not Seen, we learn about the broken window fallacy. We learn to reject the claim that an obviously bad thing, a broken window, is a good thing because of what is seen: the work it provides to the glazier who replaces it. We learn that what is not seen is that if the window had not been broken, its owner could have used his money to buy a new pair of shoes, giving work to the shoemaker, and leaving him with both his original window and a new pair of shoes.

A similar fallacy involves another obviously bad thing, the theft of primary property. Kinsella seems to call it a good thing because of what is seen: ideas that are made available free to everyone, hypothetically leading to a cascade of even more innovation for the benefit of “society.” What is not seen are the potential negative effects on the innovator of taking his property without permission, without payment, and quite likely without credit or gratitude. It would defy reason to claim that those effects are zero, but that’s what “no harm” means. And yet that is what the opponents of intellectual property seem to claim.

Only the owner of property can evaluate the harm done by its theft. The value of property of every kind is subjective to its owner and the owner is the only one who can assess the harm, which may be tangible, intangible, or both. The opinion of a third party, and especially that of the thief, is irrelevant. The person who, rather than pay what the seller of property asks, simply takes the property, should not gain from that acquisition. He’s a thief. Once this is part of common law, others, knowing of his behavior, will be reluctant to accept him into their community or engage in economic transactions with him. His life will become very unpleasant.

It is beyond puzzling to see how those who, calling themselves libertarians, and advocating the sanctity of private property, can at the same time callously sacrifice the individual to the collective without so much as a “Please,” let alone a “Thank you,” and then call the results a good thing, saying no harm was done. Isn’t that what the worst political states do? And think about that action on a more personal level. When a person says, “Please don’t kill me” and you do anyway, what are you? When a person says, “Please don’t steal my car,” and you do anyway, what are you? When an inventor says, “Please don’t copy my invention without a license,” or a singer says, “Please don’t download my song without paying for it,” and you do anyway, what are you?

FINALLY, JUSTICE FOR ALL

Here I’ll introduce some Galambos definitions which, along with those of “property” and other concepts, would be part of what I’ll call Galambosian Common Law.

Crime: Any successful act of coercion.

All attempted, intentional interferences with property (coercion) are crimes. Galambos proposed a justice system that would be privately administered (by definition, this is the only possibility in a state-free society) and restitution-based.

Injustice: A crime to which there is no recourse to the victim.

Justice: The elimination of injustice.

One of Galambos’ goals was to reduce injustice to near zero via a proprietary justice system. Its major, profit-seeking participants would be arbitrators, detectives, forensic analysts, security forces, and insurance companies. Various authors have written brilliantly on how a state-free voluntary society would provide every needed product and service, including a justice system. Reading their analyses should firmly establish that a totally private, voluntary society would be hugely successful. However, that is not a claim of perfection, but of relative success.

As Michael Huemer said, in discussing a review of his book by Kevin Vallier at BleedingHeartLibertarians.com, “The question is not whether anarchy is perfect, but whether it is better than government.” I believe that Galambos would agree, although he would use his own definitions. What Huemer calls “government,” Galambos calls the “state.”

State: Any organized coercion which has general accreditation and respectability by the people; a monopoly of crime.

Government: Any person or organization which offers services or products for sale for the purpose of protecting property, to which the owners of property can voluntarily subscribe.

Huemer defines “anarchy” by contrasting it to a government that is coercive rather than voluntary, and which has a monopoly in the services rendered. I believe that he and Galambos are in complete accord here. However, Galambos pointed out that the Greek root of “anarchy” means “without leadership.” In that sense, Galambos said, he was not an anarchist. Instead, Galambos proposed that leadership be ideological, not political.

In thinking about a state-free society, and what should or shouldn’t be protected by common law, we must take into account the things we call incentives and disincentives. Any attempt to make ideas “free” by allowing them to be used without permission or payment will be perceived as a disincentive by innovators, entrepreneurs, and investors. In a society that accepts this practice, there will indeed be “free” ideas. As we know from Bastiat, this is what will be seen. But what will not be seen are the ideas that will never be innovated or, if innovated, will not be introduced into that society’s marketplace. Innovators, entrepreneurs and investors will have an incentive to move to a community where ideas are protected.

But, asks Kinsella, what is the net effect on society of protecting ideas? Is it good or bad? He says it’s “not clear” and “debatable.” In other words, he doesn’t know. But just look at the immense cost of doing so, he says. Shouldn’t the proponents of intellectual property have to justify this cost? However, he’s referring to the legislatively-created, coercively-enforced monopoly system under the state, with taxpayers coercively forced to foot the bill. When did the state ever do anything efficiently and at low cost? Galambos visualized a state-free world, where private, profit-seeking companies would compete to provide the protection their customers wanted at the lowest possible cost. This is how all forms of property would be protected, and there is no reason why the cost of protecting intellectual property would be anything other than reasonable.

Kinsella says that “it has not been shown that IP leads to net gains in wealth [of society].” But he’s ignoring his own premise: “Wealth maximization is not the goal of law; rather the goal is justice—giving each man his due.” Galambos would agree, and so would I, adding that protecting an individual’s property in all its forms satisfies that requirement. It follows that protecting individuals would have a positive net effect on society.

Kinsella also says that if you are going to “advocate the use of force against others’ property you should satisfy a burden of proof.” He’s referring to what he calls the “unethical violation of some individuals’ rights to use their own property as they see fit.” This is what political operatives call “spin.” What he’s describing are various acts taken in defense of property. He wants us to “prove” that defending our property is ethical. As discussed above, if I block your fist as it races toward my nose, if I put a deadbolt on my door, and if I make my ideas available only with my permission, these are entirely ethical actions. My actions to seek restitution if any of my defensive measures fail and I am harmed are also ethical. To call any of them unethical because they “control” your property would void the concept of self-defense. To say that “advocating use of force against other people’s property” in these circumstances somehow turns the aggressor into the victim is ludicrous. But Kinsella applies this reasoning to the defense of primary property, calling the use of force to defend it unethical. He does this based on the false premise that it’s not really property, and that bad things will happen if you treat it so.

To achieve justice, all forms of property must be defended. Justice is not about society, but about the individual. Societal wealth will follow. As I heard John Stossel say, “Free people, left alone, will make themselves prosperous.”

THE FOUNDATION OF THE SCIENCE OF VOLITION

Now I’ll introduce to you what I believe was Galambos’ most important idea. He called it the First Postulate of Volition. (There is a Second Postulate, but a discussion of it would go beyond the scope of this paper.) All sciences have postulates. They are sometimes called axioms, or first principles. Galambos preferred “postulate” so I’ll continue his usage. A postulate is an original premise of a science. It’s where you start and what you build upon.

The First Postulate of Volition: All volitional beings live to pursue happiness.

Despite my claim that this was Galambos’ most important idea, it’s a safe bet that you didn’t feel the earth move under your feet as you read it. It is likely that because the phrase “pursuit of happiness” appears in the Declaration of Independence your brain took a shortcut and assumed that the postulate said the same thing. But that’s not the case. Rather, it is a profound insight into human nature. (Some might see a relationship between this and Ludwig von Mises’ action axiom as stated in Human Action. Galambos read that book, sold it in the FEI bookstore, and had Mises as a guest lecturer. Although Galambos was possibly influenced by Mises on this point, I believe that his formulation is clearer, and is by far the stronger statement about how things are, i.e., this is a law of nature.)

For the postulate to make complete sense, it is necessary to define “happiness,” and doing that requires definitions of “good” and “bad.”

Good: The subjective valuation of a preference.

Bad: The subjective valuation of a dispreference.

Happiness: The totality of all the ‘goods’ that a person has subjectively experienced throughout his lifetime up to the point he’s making the evaluation, less all the ‘bads’ that he has experienced.

On first hearing, some people will dispute the claim that everyone is seeking happiness. For example, what about the person who is intent on committing suicide? With a little thought it can be seen that for that person, death is a way of ending his continuing and possibly increasing state of unhappiness. To him, death would be subjectively preferable, a “good” thing.

Galambos was a great admirer of the Declaration of Independence and its significance in the march toward freedom, and he lectured on it at length. His insight was that although life and liberty are rights that can be secured contractually, the pursuit of happiness is not a right, but human nature. It is observable that all people pursue happiness during every waking moment. We can’t help it, and no one can stop us from doing it. I’m doing it now, and so are you. It’s what we do. This, said Galambos, was a law of nature.

To repeat and reinforce the concept, it is a law of nature, specifically human nature, that every person is pursuing happiness all the time. Therefore, any proposed social organization or common law has to take that into account. Since it is impossible to violate a law of nature, attempts to do so will always fail, and there will be a net loss from the effort. It follows that if we expect to have a society of freedom the rules must not ignore or attempt to directly violate this law. It is a requirement that we acknowledge this law and work with it.

I know that some people, and perhaps most people, would say, “Freedom as Galambos defined it is unrealistic. Giving people 100% control of their property would mean that we couldn’t require them to pay for things that are good for them, as we can now by means of taxes. For example, who will build the roads?” Larken Rose, who is perpetually engaged in discussions of this sort, says that he often responds with another question: “How would you do it?” Quite often the skeptic will respond with a free market solution. They seem to know what to do, but “it has just never occurred to them that they are already in charge of themselves, their futures, and the future of the world.” [The Most Dangerous Superstition, p. 171]

Many readers of this document will already be well-versed in how a market economy can deliver all of the property protection products and services now supposedly supplied by the state, so I won’t deal with that here. But what about property in ideas? As I understand Mr. Kinsella’s position, no matter how society is organized, whether under a state or without one, ideas should not be protected like other forms of property because doing so is harmful to civilization. Not only would Galambos dispute that, he would claim that the protection of primary property is necessary. That’s because of the First Corollary to the First Postulate.

A corollary is a restatement of a postulate. Galambos restated the First Postulate, which is, once again, all volitional beings live to pursue happiness. By restatement, we have this corollary:

The First Corollary to the First Postulate: All volitional beings live to acquire property.

We are all seeking to acquire property all of the time, and as a law of nature this is true without exception. There is no way around it. Therefore, we have to find ways to deal with this fact.

To be successful, the rules of society must resolve conflicts regarding all forms of property. When it is human nature to acquire property, attempts to take it from us without our permission are going to be resisted, and there will be a cost. Property can never be acquired “free.” It is impossible for it to be otherwise. (Even when you receive a gift, you pay for it with expressed gratitude; if you don’t do that, you pay for it with a loss of self-esteem and quite likely a loss of reputation in the eyes of the gift-giver.)

It is observable that people resist having their ideas taken from them. Why? Because it is human nature to treat ideas as property, in the same way that we put “my” life and “my” automobile in the category of “my” property. I claim that this view is held by humans everywhere. Its universality explains the very existence of the term, “intellectual property.”

Every reader of this essay will have had many ideas in his lifetime. Who hasn’t said, “That was my idea?” We have all encountered the expression, “I gave him that idea.” We’ve also heard, “He stole that idea from me.” We know what these expressions mean: property was transferred as a gift, or property was stolen.

Even a person who attacks the concept of ideas as property, such as Mr. Kinsella, must think of the arguments he puts forth as his arguments. Further, in citing the ideas of others, he attributes specific ideas to specific people in the same way that one refers to an owner of tangible property, e.g., “Adam Smith’s flawed labor theory of value.” In the face of such empirical evidence, how can ideas be anything but property?

At this juncture someone might say, “Wait a minute, even if ideas are property I disagree that everyone is always trying to acquire them. Personally, I don’t care anything about acquisition. I create ideas for the good of mankind, and I give them to anyone who wants them, free of charge. I spend countless hours writing articles and blogging, all for the good of my fellow man. And what about all the scientists who are working on curing cancer and the like, and who gladly share their research, and what about the billionaire philanthropists who donate huge sums to worthy causes? Aren’t such personal sacrifices the opposite of acquiring property? We’re all giving our property away in selfless acts of altruism. Doesn’t that prove that your corollary is false?” Not surprisingly, the answer is “No.”

This is where I will introduce you to Galambos’ concept of primary profit. Perhaps you already see where I’m going just by reading that term. If not, you soon will, and you will find it useful in understanding human behavior, beginning with your own. (Those readers who are familiar with Human Action may be reminded of what Mises called psychic profit, which is a very similar concept—perhaps the same—but neither man is here to tell us.)

We begin with Galambos’ definitions of profit and of plunder.

Profit: An increase in happiness acquired by moral means.

Plunder: An increase in happiness by immoral means; property is converted to plunder when coercively transferred.

We live in a world where profit and plunder are almost always thought of in terms of money or other tangible things. As we’ve seen, these are secondary property. Profits that come in the form of secondary property are called secondary profits. Those who say they oppose profit are thinking of secondary profit.

Galambos saw that with primary property, which is intangible, we can have primary profit, which is also intangible. This, in my view, is a brilliant insight. Primary profit consists of things like the satisfaction one feels when reaching a goal, the increase in self-esteem from having done something moral in the face of temptation to do otherwise, the receipt of gratitude from someone you have helped, or the improvement of your professional or personal reputation. Practicing the Golden Rule, a feature of every major religion, produces primary profit. Some people are motivated almost entirely by primary profit. It’s a beautiful and very useful concept.

Framing these human emotions as a form of profit to correspond with monetary profit makes it possible to compare the two and to consider the fact that we make exchanges between them. When I pay to download a movie even though a pirated version is available “free,” I feel good about myself—a primary profit. I could watch the movie without paying and preserve my secondary property (money) but I choose to exchange that money for a primary profit measured in self-esteem. I also know that the “free” movie is not really free; the price I would pay to accept stolen property would be a reduction in my self-esteem—a primary loss. What’s more, the stolen property in my possession would not be my property, because theft transfers control but not ownership. I would be holding plunder.

The concept of primary profit fully explains what we call “altruism.” Galambos pointed out that there are no “selfless” acts, and no such thing as altruism. He said that Ayn Rand had made this point so well in her book, The Fountainhead, that “it would be a waste of time to put that into this Course other than to refer to it.” [SIAA p.276] All “altruistic” acts represent an attempt to earn a primary profit and increase one’s primary property. Seen in this way, a donation of money is an exchange of secondary property for primary property in expectation of receiving a primary profit. All of us are all pursuing happiness, and seeking to acquire property, all of the time. Both happiness and property come in different forms, and individuals ultimately pursue the kinds of property and profit they prefer.

Galambos had an interesting opinion about this that was shared by Ludwig von Mises. He said that scientists and other producers of primary property are drawn to socialism out of the feeling that it is unfair that they, the ones with all the brains, and the ones doing really important things, make little money, while entrepreneurs engaged in mundane pursuits make millions. To Galambos this was envy, and he referred his students to Mises’ book, The Anticapitalistic Mentality, for more on the subject.

The point is that the low-paid intellectual and the high-paid executive are pursuing the same thing: profit. The difference is in the form of profit they’ve chosen to pursue, and how wealth is measured. When wealth is measured in terms of secondary property, the businessman seems rich and the philosopher poor. But when the measurement is made in primary property we may find the reverse.

In a society that recognizes the existence of primary profit and primary wealth, (concepts taught in childhood) the effect will be, at a minimum, to reduce the envy. Rather than denigrating or despising the very idea of profit, the producers of primary property will embrace profit in its primary form. Having pursued happiness in their own way, they will see that they have accumulated primary wealth. For many of them, perhaps most, this will be enough. Others will explore ways to use their primary wealth to earn secondary profits.

Because of Galambos we now know that every human action is an action in the pursuit of happiness. We are all doing it, all the time. We are all seeking to acquire property in its various forms all the time. We are all trying to increase our happiness by coming out ahead on everything we do, whether it is a primary gain or a secondary one. This can now be considered a fact.

What has long been understood (as the concept of diminishing marginal utility) is that as our secondary property needs are met and our secondary wealth increases, further increases tend to motivate us less. When this happens, the appeal of primary property and primary profit becomes relatively greater. A person may begin to seek primary profit by engaging in activities that increase self-esteem and other forms of primary profit. This explains the philanthropic activities of not just billionaires, but of everyone.

THE PROBLEMS OF PROPERTY OWNERSHIP

Although there are certain specific difficulties with the ownership of ideas, all property has problems associated with its ownership. It is impossible to have property without risk or without problems. Let’s look at those property ownership problems, category by category.

Primordial Property. Life has the problem that it must be kept alive. It’s quite an effort to keep a human alive. We perish rather easily in temperatures that are not much different than optimum, and we have to be sheltered and clothed in some conditions. There are also the problems of ensuring a supply of potable water, enough calories to avoid starvation, and the correct array of nutrients required for health. There are illnesses and the potential for fatal injury, and there are animals and other humans who might attack us. It’s a big chore to maintain the property we have in our lives. Finally, despite our best efforts, we inevitably die and our primordial property falls to zero.

Secondary Property. Our tangible possessions present us with innumerable challenges. Every possession is subject to the possibility of theft or of destruction by accident or natural disaster. Most things can be damaged in normal use, and eventually everything wears out or becomes useless through obsolescence. The more secondary property one has, the more effort must be put into taking care of it. It can be quite a headache. And if you have a lot of material things there are those who would criticize you just for your success, and attack you for having “too much,” even though you acquired it through moral means.

Despite these problems and more, we are still eager to claim our lives and our tangible possessions as our private property. Occasionally some societies have experimented with not treating them so. Those societies failed, some spectacularly, and with great loss of life and much suffering. Nevertheless, there remains a contingent that hasn’t learned this lesson and still argues, if not for the outright abolition of private secondary property, then at least for its substantial redistribution. Every effort in this direction is an attempt to violate a law of nature and will fail.

Primary Property. In principle, this is the easiest property to care for. There is no required maintenance, and there are no physical problems. Ideas may lose utility over time, but they don’t wear out in the conventional sense, and they can’t be consumed. Ideas can be lost, but not destroyed. If lost, someone will inevitably discover them again, so the loss can be seen as a temporary setback at most. This is especially true in what we call modern civilization where the search for useful ideas is relentless.

The ownership of primary property seems to have few problems. However, there are three potentially significant ones, but they can be dealt with easily.

The first potential problem of primary property is what Galambos called “promiscuous disclosure.” This means non-contractual disclosure. Promiscuous disclosure is analogous to giving control of one of your tangible possessions to someone without an explicit agreement as to its allowed use, their responsibility for taking care of it, and so forth. Galambos cautioned students against making promiscuous disclosures of ideas from the course. Sometimes, spurred by their excitement and their desire to get a friend or relative or business associate to attend, they disclosed some of the course’s conclusions out of context, where they could indeed sound bizarre. Predictably, this made it harder to get the person to attend. It is important to note that despite the fact that Galambos had his students’ written agreement not to disclose, he didn’t use that as a legal club. He only mentioned the practical aspect of disclosure being counterproductive.

Innovators themselves are capable of making the blunder of promiscuous disclosures. One can envision a drunken inventor blabbing his secrets in a bar, with a sober competitor listening intently. Although most promiscuous disclosures happen less colorfully than that, in all cases the innovator has begun to lose control of his primary property when he makes a non-contractual disclosure. In the worst case, he totally loses control and the idea becomes generally known and without an apparent owner. From a moral perspective, unless coercion was used, anyone receiving an idea through promiscuous disclosure is free to use it (though he might see it as taking advantage of another person’s error and not use it, following the Golden Rule out of consideration for his own self-esteem). Realistically, almost all ideas are of such little importance and value that they can be disclosed without any precautions whatsoever. But for those ideas believed by their innovator to have present or future value, care should be taken to register them in a way that establishes borders and independency.

The second potential problem has to do with property borders which, as Mr. Kinsella correctly observes, must be visible. As a patent attorney, Mr. Kinsella has experience in the creation of the very documentation that makes them so. The patent process, flawed though it is, at least attempts to make the borders visible by articulating the details of the invention and identifying the person who claims ownership. The same thing will be done in the world envisioned by Galambos, where Mr. Kinsella would find plenty of opportunities to profit from his skill. In Course V-201, Galambos went into substantial detail about how innovators would register their ideas with companies that provided registration services on a proprietary basis. In addition, printed notices or markings could make it clear that someone has claimed ownership. Ideas that are well-documented have good borders. This is a market solution to the border problem, and is illustrated later in this paper.

RESOLVING CONFLICTS OVER PRIMARY PROPERTY

The resolution of all disputes involving all forms of property begins with answering the question, “Whose property is it?” In general, we will know via various items of evidence. But property borders for ideas may not always be clear, especially for less important, poorly documented ideas. If the question of ownership is unanswered, or perhaps unanswerable, and the idea is minor, there is unlikely to be any conflict over it.

However, when the idea is a significant one, the border is likely to be very clear. That is because the innovator himself will know that it is his idea. If an idea is a “big” one, we are unlikely to forget that we thought of it. We will also have documented it. If it is not our idea, then by default it is someone else’s, and to claim otherwise or to use it without permission would make us a criminal. Moral behavior requires that we find out whose property it is and the terms of use. This will not be hard. Computerized databases will contain this information. (Just think of iTunes for everything.) Nor will it be a frequent task. The duty of establishing ownership and securing use of ideas will be that of product manufacturers, not consumers.

When there are competing claims about the ownership of an idea and the conflict cannot be resolved by the parties, if the idea is important enough to pursue such a resolution then the insurance and arbitration mechanisms can be brought to bear. Insurers and arbitrators and their agents will do detective work and employ various tests for independency of discovery or creation. In Course V-201 Galambos suggested nine tests for independency as a way of weeding out false claims. So-called “reverse engineering” would not be an independent creation, but theft.

In Galambos’ view, each bona fide independent innovator has the same ownership rights to the innovation as the first innovator. There is no special status accorded to the person who first had the idea other than what we might call “bragging” rights. No monopoly rights would be awarded as they are with patents. Although a competitive advantage would quite likely accrue to whoever was first with a marketable innovation, that advantage would not be protected against competition from a later independent innovator. (Galambos remarked lightheartedly that as a high school student he was quite excited to have discovered a mathematical principle, only to learn that it already had a name–the binomial theorem–and had been discovered by Isaac Newton more than 250 years earlier.)

The fact that all independent innovators have equal standing totally eliminates one of Kinsella’s biggest concerns. He fears the possibility of a greedy innovator, owning an idea in perpetuity, and controlling the use and further development of that idea, to be succeeded by generations of heirs who had nothing to do with the innovation. Quoting Kinsella, “No one would be able to manufacture—or even use—a light bulb without getting permission from Edison’s heirs.” Galambos’ brilliant idea to give equal status to independent innovation makes this a non-problem. In the worst possible case, society simply has to wait for the independent innovation of the same thing or something better. No one in society has a right to “have it now,” or a right to steal it for any reason.

Ideas are only valuable because they fill some perceived need. The greater the need the more people will be trying to fill it, and the sooner the solution will occur to one of them. Perhaps they will have an even better idea. (As it happened, Tesla was right there with the fluorescent light.) The feared monopolies charging “outrageous” prices would, in the overall scheme of things, be short-lived. They would also be rare, because they would tend to be less profitable than if they charged lower prices and had higher volume. I’ll address this again below, to further reduce the concern.

The third potential problem with primary property affects secondary property as well. It stems from what Galambos called the Principle of Least Action, suggested by a principle of the same name in physics. This was alluded to above as the desire to pursue happiness with the least effort possible, and in the ideal (but impossible) case getting something for nothing. With humans, the least action may be to use coercion, by either force or fraud, to obtain control of tangible property, or the use of an idea, without the owner’s permission. Knowing that humans have this underlying motivation, the solution is to make it unprofitable to act on it. The justice mechanism envisioned by Galambos would make immoral behavior such as stealing far less profitable than moral behavior. He posited that crime of all kinds would be so unprofitable that the number of incidences would approach zero.

AN UNAPPRECIATED VIRTUE OF PRIMARY PROPERTY

Unlike a car, or a chair, or a piece of pie, use of the same primary property can be sold again and again. This is a benefit to both innovators and users. The innovator can spread his development costs over many sales, thereby lowering his cost per unit and allowing him to make use of the idea available at an affordable but still profitable market price. His rational goal is to maximize his profit, and that is usually accomplished by selling things in large numbers. It is seldom, if ever, accomplished by selling just a few things at a high price. (Remember the hardwired “car phones” that only the wealthy could afford? Now there are literally billions of handheld and vastly more capable devices that are affordable enough for almost everyone.)

It is a fallacy that protecting the ownership of primary property will choke off production of useful things. Rather, it will lead to increased production, because the innovators, entrepreneurs, and investors will know that the market value of their property will not be destroyed by theft. In addition, they will not have to build that risk into the price of their innovation, thereby enabling a lower price. Finally, the innovator’s knowledge that an independent innovation of his idea, or a competing idea, might come into the market tomorrow, will give him an incentive to keep the price low. In any event, unless we want a society where stealing is approved as a way of acquiring property, we have to live with the outcome of accepting the ownership of ideas.

In the industrialized world, the price of tangible goods, all of which are the fruit of ideas, has come down steadily. Is this because ideas have been stolen, or because they have been given at least some protection by both our laws and our sense of morality? I believe that it is the latter, and that both common law and the moral standards of individuals will be improved as Galambos’ ideas move into the mainstream.

CONCLUSION

I believe that I have argued successfully in favor of intellectual property by showing that

  • Something need not be scarce to be property.
  • Ideas in general are plentiful, but the ideas that matter are scarce.
  • Intellectual property can be homesteaded by more than one person.
  • Intellectual property can have visible borders.
  • Protecting one’s ideas does not unethically control the property of others.
  • Using intellectual property without permission is not harmless.
  • It is human nature to treat ideas as property.
  • Protecting ideas is beneficial to both the individual and society.
  • Not protecting ideas harms both the individual and society.
  • The ownership of ideas by innovators and heirs will not choke off civilization’s growth.
  • Treating ideas as property conforms to Occam’s razor.
  • Ideas are automatically owned in perpetuity.
  • Keeping track of intellectual property will not be costly.

As I review the above I cannot know whether I have said too much or too little. I cannot know whether my explanations are clear and satisfactory, or have further clouded the issues. I could make this much longer, but then I would be teaching the course, and my only goal here is to counter the arguments of those who are against intellectual property. I cannot know whether you found value here, but I hope you have. And, as I mentioned earlier, I hope you begin to contemplate a society structured using the principles innovated by Galambos. I think you will conclude that it would be just, peaceful, prosperous, and worth building.

A new scientific truth does not triumph by convincing its opponents and making them see the light, but rather because its opponents eventually die, and a new generation grows up that is familiar with it.” Max Planck

APPENDIX: INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY IN A FREE SOCIETY

I’d like to take you through some steps to bring into focus the practicality and feasibility of using the abstract principles and definitions you’ve just read. I’ll begin by introducing another Galambos concept, a convenient system of notation to be used in discussing property. Influenced by his background in mathematics and the physical sciences, Galambos used the written notation, P0, P1, and P2 to identify the three types of property. In lectures, he would verbalize primary property as “P one,” and secondary property as “P two.” Thus in general conversation one might say, “In this business I expect to use this P one to generate a P two profit.”

In recent correspondence with other former Galambos students I’ve noticed some of them typing P1 rather than P one and P2 rather than P two. What a relief, at least for me, who struggles at the keyboard. I have adopted this new convention. From here on, Primary property is P1, secondary property is P2.

Let’s envision a voluntary society where the principles identified by Galambos are the basis of common law. There being no state, all property protection products and services are provided by private entities, known collectively as government per Galambos’ definition. (And it’s not “the” government, because competition prevails. Numerous companies would offer government services).

As part of the basic instruction given to children by parents and teachers, P1 will be considered to be property just as P2 is today. Children will learn that it is wrong to steal, and that stealing includes P1 as well as P2. Children will learn to respect other people’s property rights, and those include P1 as well as P2.

Children trained in this way will have the world view that ideas are property. Similarly, children will be taught that everyone is seeking happiness, and that it is a perfectly normal pursuit which they can’t help doing, so their own pursuit of happiness is nothing to be ashamed of. They will be taught that morality consists of not interfering with anyone else’s property, whether it is P0, P1, or P2. (Reading this paper means that you don’t have to wait; you can teach these principles to your child today.)

To continue with how P1 will be treated, I’ll again mention that it is the nature of things that the total number of items that are in the category of P1 is beyond counting. My decision regarding the placement of a lamp on my desk, or which drawer is best for my toothpaste, is P1. The design of a restaurant menu is someone’s P1. The ingredients and manufacturing process of a given kind of plastic is someone’s P1. A Facebook post is someone’s P1. We live in a sea of P1. The vast majority is of no use to anyone other than its owner, is not necessarily of very high quality, and is not very important, even to its owner.

Out of this enormous mass of P1, some of it may have a little utility and a little importance to someone other than its owner, but not enough to have what we call “commercial potential,” which is to say the possibility of P2 profit. Such P1 is generally given away at no charge when the occasion arises. Maybe I found a really great restaurant. This knowledge is my P1, but I’ll give it away to my friends without charge in exchange for the P1 profit that consists of the good feeling I get when they say, “Thanks for telling me.” Perhaps some of my P1 pertains to my job, where creating and using P1 is part of it, and I receive both a P1 profit in the form of satisfaction for a job well done, and a P2 profit as my effort is rewarded financially. Perhaps I’m part of a collaborative effort, where ideas flow back and forth and no one keeps track, but all enjoy the P1 excitement of achieving something that couldn’t be done on one’s own. The result of all this is that the vast majority of P1 is given away via non-contractual disclosure, and is available to everyone.

We have no reason to be concerned about the fate of low level P1, or P1 that was designed to be given away, as long as it is not interfered with. A major Galambos tenet is, “There is no such thing as a small interference with property.” Although I think there are better ways to word it, I hope the meaning is clear: interference with property is always wrong, and if you accept a small interference, you open the door for larger interferences and, ultimately, tyranny.

Now let’s talk about P1 that is good enough and important enough to have evoked Mr. Kinsella’s fear that keeping it in private hands will be a disaster to society. I’ve tried to make it clear that it is the protection of the individual and his property, and not of society, that should motivate us. That’s because if the individual is protected, society is protected. You’re about to see that Galambos’ ideas serve both interests. What follows is my interpretation of his model, although such was his confidence that I’m sure that he saw it not as a model, but as the way things will be. It was disclosed in great detail in V-201, but is presented here, and only in part, as just a conceptual framework. I believe that market forces will no doubt cause deviations from the Galambos model when it meets the real world, so leaving the details out at this point should not matter to your comprehension.

In the Galambosian model, owners of P1 will be able to register their P1 with one of presumably many companies in the P1 registration business. These and other companies will compete for P1 as “inventory,” and seek P2 profits from representing the innovator in the market. Such companies will identify potential customers for the P1, acting as the innovator’s agent, and isolating him from the fray. It’s the principle of the division of labor at work, with each participant free to do what he does best. Innovators can specialize in innovating, and the P1 matchmakers can do what they are in business to do: earn a P2 profit for themselves and their innovator customers.

Remember that P1 itself cannot be sold, only its use. There are an infinite number of contractual terms that can be arranged between the P1 owner and the prospective P1 user. One arrangement might be a payment for permanent exclusive use of the idea; another might be payment based on the gross sales of the innovation; another might be on the net profits; still another might be a royalty, perhaps based on each item sold.

Galambos chose the royalty system for his model. Although I don’t recall him mentioning it, that compensation method fits the fact that, as mentioned above, P1 ownership is perpetual. Therefore, as long as the innovation is in use, who but the owner should receive the P2 revenue and the P1 credit? Royalties are the traditional way to achieve this. And, since it would be immoral to use an innovation without paying for it, the innovator, and then his heirs, must be paid for as long as the innovation is used. In principle, this means for the duration of the Universe. It is this prospect that concerns Mr. Kinsella. However, the possibility of a negative outcome is so unlikely as to be safely ignored, as will be seen.

Galambos proposed that the initial P1 contract, whether with one user or many, would be based on negotiated price and terms, just as things are sold and licensed now. In the Galambosian model, two standard terms would always be included, in the way that certain standard clauses are used in contracts today. First, the use of the P1 must be non-coercive. Second, P1 credit must be given to the innovator. Failure to honor any of the terms would carry penalties, up to and including terminating the contract and receiving restitution for damages.

Following the initial P1 contract, after a period of time as determined by the P1 owner (presumably in cooperation with his P1 agent) the P1 would be made available to anyone who wanted to use it. The user would be allowed to pay whatever he thought it was worth, as long as the payment was greater than zero, and the standard terms of non-coercive use and P1 credit to the innovator were accepted.

In Galambos’ view, this way of handling P1 would become the standard way of doing business. The “pay what you want” feature would eliminate the possibility of bringing civilization’s progress to a halt due to unaffordable royalties. We might pay Edison’s heirs, but not much, as will be seen. However, an obvious question is why would an innovator, other than a naïve idealist, agree to the “pay what you want” plan? Wouldn’t he be leaving P2 profits on the table? Those questions are answered by the laws of economics.

We must remember that although an innovator owns the P1 forever, unlike the present patent system there is no time when he can prevent others from offering the same thing, if independently innovated. Innovators who come later have the same rights, and are free to contract with interested parties. Therefore, the clock is always running. Someone else may soon create the same P1, or perhaps a comparable or even better alternative. Other things being equal, the market value of the original P1 will shrink once a competitor comes onto the scene. Both licensors and licensees will have this in mind when agreeing to the original price and terms of the license, helping to keep the price down from the beginning.

In a market economy, the price and terms of the license will be the market price, agreed to voluntarily. Since innovators cannot force us to buy their P1, those who demand more than the highest bid will have no sales. The world will move on without them, and eventually the P1 in question will be made available from an independent source, or there will be a substitute for it, at a price the P1 users are willing to pay. How long will “eventually” be? Not long, if the demand for the P1 is high. In fact, it might happen very quickly. The original innovator may respond by lowering his price rather than “sitting tight” with no sales and taking the risk that the market value of his innovation might go to zero if a competitor appears. Alternatively, the prospective licensee may reevaluate his position and decide to pay the higher price.

Better innovations will be surely developed, making their predecessors obsolete. We know this from observing our world, where obsolescence is expected. I imagine that the patent for the rotary phone dial (“What’s a ‘rotary phone,’ Grandpa?”) does not have much value today. An innovator, realizing this (and once again with the advice of his agent, who does this for a living) will reach a point where it makes economic sense to release the P1 to everyone, essentially adopting a mass marketing approach, hoping that increased sales volume will work to offset his lower P2 profit per unit. (It is certainly possible that this strategy could be adopted early on, or even from the beginning. That would be up to the P1 owner and his advisor.)

One possible problem with the “pay what you want as long as it’s more than zero” format is that a user of the P1 might pay virtually nothing, thus technically satisfying the “more than zero” requirement while providing no significant P2 benefit to the owner. Galambos acknowledged that this (known in economics as “freeriding”) could happen. However, he believed that anyone who did this would find it difficult to bargain for other P1 in the future. (“Aren’t you the guy who only paid a tenth of a cent for the right to manufacture that widget?”) Just as a “big tipper” might get special service at a restaurant the next time he comes in, a person that pays generous voluntary royalties will be remembered, perhaps by being given the “first look” at new P1, while the cheapskate might not be given access to it at all. It remains to be seen whether this system will work in the real world exactly as Galambos described it. Remember, it’s a model. That said, I have confidence that its fundamental premises are sound.

The ultimate fact of economics that will keep innovators from holding the world hostage is that users of P1 cannot pay more in total royalties to all providers of P1 than the profitability of the enterprise will support. Left alone, people will only do things that they believe will be profitable. Let us say that a business can afford to pay royalties equal to 10% of its gross revenue. Suppose that it needs to use three different items of P1, and each owner asks for a royalty of 10%. Clearly the business cannot pay 30% of its gross revenue. The new business might not move forward at all but, more likely, a compromise will be reached at the negotiating table. I think the reader can see many ways in which this could be resolved.

In worrying, as some do, about all the possible ways in which an innovator might impede the progress of civilization by restricting access to his innovation and/or pricing it so high as to be unaffordable, it is easy to overlook the most likely case. Innovators, like all humans, are engaged in the pursuit of happiness all the time. The most likely case is for them to make their innovations available at a price that will bring them not only a monetary profit, but the satisfaction of having produced something that others want, and receiving acknowledgment and praise for providing it. This is clearly the usual behavior of innovators. I believe that we would be hard-pressed to find many exceptions, and shouldn’t worry about them.

Let’s use the supposed problem of “Edison’s heirs” as an example of why we have nothing to fear from heirs in general. Suppose that today a company gets a license to use the P1 for a light that uses almost no energy, is cool to the touch, and will last 100 years. In the license they have agreed to pay a 9% royalty on gross sales for the exclusive right to use this new P1. Let’s say that this company can afford to pay 12% in total royalties to all P1 licensors combined, so that leaves them with just 3% available to pay all other royalties. They look into it and realize that after Edison several more innovators contributed P1 to the light bulb. However, a couple of the innovations are no longer used, and there is no reason to pay a royalty. They find that there are three companies whose P1 is essential, and is available on a “pay what you want” basis.

Finally, they discover that the only one of Edison’s innovations still in use by anyone is the discovery that the air had to be evacuated from the bulb so that the filament won’t instantly burn. However, their new P1 operates in air and with no filament, so there is no need to evacuate the bulb. In fact, there is no longer a part called “bulb.” Therefore there is no reason to pay Edison’s heirs. His innovation had a good run, but now it looks like it’s over.

This outcome will be typical, with only a few innovations having perpetual utility. In those cases, royalties will be ongoing, but so many innovations will have been added on top of them that the heirs will collect extremely small amounts, albeit on potentially enormous volume.

The lesson here is that no matter what the owners of P1 may ask to be paid, no business can pay more in total royalties than its profit margin will support, and it will only pay for things it uses. Innovations that come later and that must be implemented in order for the product to remain competitive will have to be paid out of the same total percentage that the business can afford. Therefore, royalty recipients will be under pressure to adjust their royalty fee downward if they want their innovations to be used at all. With luck, total revenues will grow, and 1% of a new larger pie will be worth more than 3% of the old pie. Galambos suggested a formula for how royalties would be adjusted downward as you worked backward through the chain of innovations that led to the present state of the art. Royalty calculations would be performed, tracked, and paid by computer at low cost.

Now let’s consider a case where the P1 is so fundamental that it will always be used. Einstein’s equation, E = mc2, is a law of nature. Einstein does not own nature itself, but he does own his discovery of it and the law described by that equation. Had Galambos’ system been in effect, we would still be paying Einstein’s heirs.

Somehow the idea of paying heirs seems to provoke a sort of indignation in some people. Let’s look at that more closely. Paying anything to the heirs means that the owner of the P1 has died. Galambos believed, without elaborating, that physical death is not necessarily inevitable. Other scientists say the same thing, and the prospect of perhaps digitizing our “selves” may provide another way to be immortal. But let’s say life was extended to 1,000 years. Would anyone object to paying a 1,000 year old Einstein? I don’t think so. Even modest improvements in life expectancy will bring this into focus. After all, Einstein would only be 136 years old today. Would it bother you to know that nuclear power plants were paying him a royalty? If we begin to act in accord with the laws of nature and make the protection of primary property part of common law and of everyone’s world view, we will set the stage for this eventuality.

But we still haven’t addressed the “problem” of heirs that troubles some people. They believe that the heirs of a deceased innovator don’t deserve to be paid. They don’t seem to have the same negative feeling when the heirs inherit a large amount of P2, such as money or a house, but no stake in royalties. For some reason it bothers them to think that in purchasing a product they are paying people who had nothing to do with its innovation. Perhaps this is envy, which is among the least appealing traits in humans. Whatever the reason, I offer the following.

We are talking about a society in which the P1’s owner faces the prospect of competition from the very start. The better and more important the P1 is, the more competition there will be. As a result, the P2 royalty stream may be sharply reduced or even ended before the P1 owner’s death, thus eliminating the “problem” of paying the heirs. Further, each subsequent innovation that builds on the original P1 dilutes the share of P2 that can flow to the owner of any specific item of P1 in that chain. The heirs might get very little, and perhaps nothing, as we saw in the Edison illustration.

Einstein’s heirs would clearly get something, but it would be diluted by the many subsequent P1 developments that were necessary to turn E = mc2 into something, such as nuclear power plants, that can generate a large amount of P2. Because of this economic reality it would be extremely rare for an innovator’s heirs to be collecting a large amount of P2, and virtually impossible to do so for generations. Although they will control the use of the P1 in perpetuity, it is quite another thing for an innovation to have perpetual market value. The more likely case will be for the heirs to be struggling to get any revenue at all.

Because of all of the above, the concern that civilization will routinely be held hostage by a greedy, unreasonable, or even insane innovator or his heirs is totally unfounded

Galambos didn’t focus on heirs in the sense of children and other family members who traditionally receive some or all of a person’s P2. This will likely occur as long as humans exist, but Galambos’ interest was in the major P1 innovators. He advocated that those whose P1 could produce a long term stream of P2 should create something like what we now call “foundations” that would collect revenue and invest the accumulated wealth in areas designated by its owner. With the protection of primary property, things like the Rockefeller and Ford foundations would be joined by entities bearing the names of Einstein, Planck, and Tesla. But, despite focusing on the major innovators, Galambos observed that every human accumulates P1 and P2, and has the ability to make similar plans for it upon his death. Rather than worrying about someone else’s heirs, and what they might be paid, it might be more profitable to plan for the disposition of one’s own P1 and P2.

ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS

I would like to thank Carl Watner, Alvin Lowi, Jr., Frederic G. Marks, Brian Gladish, Greg Boren, and my wife Pauline Boren. Their encouragement and their many suggestions, most of which were adopted, made this a much better paper than if I had done it all on my own.

Thank you for taking the time to read this. Please address comments and questions to me at richardborenP1@gmail.com

SUGGESTED READING/LISTENING

Sources regarding intellectual property.

Sic Itur Ad Astra, Volume One, by Andrew J. Galambos. This is the transcript of his 1968 delivery of Course V-50. Discloses the basics of the Science of Volition. Used copies sometimes available. Course can be taken online at www.fei-ajg.com, subject to significant restrictions. Site is operated by the same people who refuse to publish.

The V-50 Lectures by Jay Stuart Snelson (1978 audio recording). Snelson put Galambos’ ideas into a beautifully crafted and delivered lecture series, attended by many thousands of people over his 14 year career at FEI. Published by Charles Holloway in 2008.

Thrust for Freedom by Andrew J. Galambos. A collection of short essays originally published under that name in 1963. Among them is Galambos’ definition of property, with an explanatory narrative, and a number of lengthy passages from Sic Itur Ad Astra.

Capitalism, the Liberal Revolution. A website devoted to the work of Galambos and Snelson. Created by Frederic G. Marks, first a Galambos student, and then his attorney for many years. www.capitalismtheliberalrevolution.com. (“Liberal” means “pertaining to freedom” here.)

The Law of Intellectual Property by Lysander Spooner. Argues persuasively for the ownership of ideas in perpetuity. Galambos arrived at the same conclusion independently, and via different reasoning. Available at www.lysanderspooner.org

Sources arguing for a state-free society and describing how, in that society, the functions traditionally assigned to the state will be successfully provided on a proprietary basis.

The Voluntaryist. A newsletter published by Carl Watner. Also offers a website filled with many essays. A treasure trove of thought on these matters. www.voluntaryist.com

No Treason No. VI, the Constitution of No Authority by Lysander Spooner. Are you bound to obey political laws that you did not agree to? Well, no. See www.lysanderspooner.org.

Everyday Anarchy and Practical Anarchy by Stefan Molyneux, best read in that order.

The Problem of Political Authority by Michael Huemer. I put more Post-it notes in this book than any other in my library.

Democracy, The God That Failed, by Hans-Hermann Hoppe. No one could read this and Huemer’s book and still believe in the state, or that private enterprise couldn’t successfully take its place.

The Most Dangerous Superstition by Larken Rose. Beautifully written in an in-your-face style. Easy to read but will upset a statist’s stomach.

The Machinery of Freedom by David Friedman. Excellent analysis of the private production of government services.

For a New Liberty by Murray N. Rothbard. Excellent on everything, but like most leaves out intellectual property.

The Market for Liberty by Morris and Linda Tannehill. An excellent book, quite possibly containing some of Galambos’ ideas supplied by a former student without authorization.

The Enterprise of Law, Justice Without the State by Bruce L. Benson. A powerful examination of how a privatized justice system would work—and how it used to work before the State got involved.

Other resources

Taming the Violence of Faith by Jay Stuart Snelson. After parting ways with Galambos in 1978, Snelson lectured extensively on a variety of topics, including a lecture series, Human Action Principles. Listing his primary influences as Ludwig von Mises, Andrew Galambos, and Robert LeFevre, Snelson spent his later years writing this book, which offers his own prescription for achieving peace, prosperity, and freedom. More about Snelson and his work can be found at www.jaysnelson.com

Thinking, Fast and Slow by Daniel Kahneman. This book is a popularized account of the research of Kahneman and his colleague Amos Tversky, psychologists who won the Nobel Prize in Economics. Entertaining and instructive in its own right, I offer it as part of the vast and rapidly growing body of knowledge of human behavior. As far as I know, nothing contradicts Galambos’ observations and hypotheses. Rather, such experimental and anecdotal evidence of which I am aware fully supports them. Although I believe that Galambos was wrong about a few factual matters where his inputs were either flawed or insufficient, in the 40 years since I first heard his ideas I have yet to learn of any significant error.

The Iron Web by Larken Rose. This suspenseful, action-packed novel is 100% pure when it comes to ending the State. It might be a good way to introduce some people to this view. Without giving anything away, a presidential election is a major theme. A good beach read, and it would make a heck of movie. Available at Amazon or www.larkenrose.com

Kicking the Dragon by Larken Rose. Mr. Rose first gained notoriety regarding his conflict with the IRS, which wound up with him going to prison. Wrongly labeled a “tax protestor,” Rose simply asked a single question, and was refused an answer. Expecting vindication in court by a jury of his peers, what he found was a rigged game from start to finish. If you think a Soviet-style show trial can’t happen here in the USA, think again. Available for $5.00 as an epub or mobi file here www.larkenrose.com

 

Original post and comments can be seen here.

If You Have A Tool, You’ll Probably Use it: On the Evolution of Tax-Supported Schools in Certain Parts of the United States


 

By Carl Watner

 

In 2008, I discovered a two-volume set of books entitled UNIVERSAL EDUCATION IN THE SOUTH (1936) by Charles Dabney. The author was the son of Reverend Robert Lewis Dabney (1820- 1898), who had been a professor at the Union Theological Seminary in Richmond and was especially well-known for his attacks on government education in 1876. Volume I, which covered “From the Beginning to 1900,” was so fascinating that I purchased my own used copy and began research on the rise of tax-supported schooling. As the sub-title of this article indicates, it does not relate to the activities of such people as Horace Mann, Calvin Stowe, and others who “imported’ the Prussian model of government schools into other parts of the United States. That has been dealt with elsewhere, such as in Samuel L. Blumenfeld’s IS PUBLIC EDUCATION NECESSARY? (1981). Dabney points out, “the idea of free universal education was practically unknown in the countries from which the early settlers came, and it developed very slowly in America.” [1] Where did this idea that schools should be funded by the government (in the Southern states) originate, and how did local Southern governments overcome their citizenry’s natural reluctance to pay taxes to support them? The purpose of this article is to shed some light on the answers to these questions, and to quote some of the rhetoric used to convince Southerners that taxation was in their best interests, and that they should rely upon governments, rather than voluntaryism, to direct the education of their children.

In early American colonial history, the formal provision of education was primarily a function reserved to the wealthy and upper classes of society. Among the lower classes, it was common for parents and ministers to supply the rudiments of learning. It was not until after the Revolutionary War that a major societal concern surfaced regarding education. Among the constitutions of the original thirteen states, only North Carolina’s and Pennsylvania’s mentioned the subject, authorizing the establishment of at least one school in each county, “with such salaries to the masters, paid by the public.” At that time, education was certainly not considered a function of the national government. There was no mention of the subject in either the Declaration of Independence or the federal Constitution. Here was an opportunity for voluntaryism to have flourished. As Dabney wrote:

A great advance in educational enterprises of a private and ecclesiastical character followed [the Revolution]. The wealthy established private schools. Academies and colleges were started wherever a few pupils could be gathered together and teachers found. A new ideal of education was in the making, but universal education at public cost, as a practical possibility, was still undreamed of. [2]

Perhaps the first well-known personage in this country to broach the idea of “free” government-provided schooling for all students was Thomas Jefferson. In 1779, he presented his “Bill for the More General Diffusion of Knowledge” to the Virginia Legislature. The bill provided for three years of elementary school training for all children, rich and poor (though slave children would have been excluded). Although Massachusetts claims to have enacted the first public school law in America in 1647, in New England public education was considered a function of the church, while in Virginia and the rest of the South it was considered a function of the state. [3] Jefferson’s view was that “The state must provide for the education of all its citizens and this it should do through local agencies.” [4]

To show the progression of this idea of “universal education at state expense for all” over the next one hundred years, we need to look no further than John B. Minor’s INSTITUTES OF COMMON AND STATUTE LAW, published in 1876. According to Minor,

There are but four modes of general education possible – namely:

1. Every parent may be left to provide for his children such instruction as he can, without the government concerning itself therewith.

2. The government may undertake to assist the indigent alone, leaving the rest of the community to shift for themselves.

3. The government may give partial aid to all, leaving each some additional expense, much or little, to bear, in the shape of tuition fee, or otherwise.

4. The government may provide, at the common expense, for the complete elementary instruction of all classes, just as it provides for the protection of all. [5]

The two basic assumptions embraced by the idea of universal public schools were: 1) “that education is a function of the State rather than a family or parental obligation;” and 2) “that the Sate has the right and power to raise by taxation” the funds required to adequately support the schools. [6] Some of the principal impediments to the implementation of these ideas were 1) the general public’s dislike of taxation; 2) parental rejection of the idea that the State should be responsible for their offspring; and 3) the humiliation attached to the idea that their children would be attending “free” public schools. (Hitherto, only the poorest of the poor would accept government handouts.) [7]

Minor’s analysis reveals that the opening wedge of government involvement in education was legislation regarding orphans and indigent children. Although in both England and its colonies it was common for wealthy benefactors to endow charity schools for the poor, government legislation required that the overseers of the poor obtain an order from their county court to place those children likely to become a burden to the parish (such as beggars, orphans, paupers, and illegitimate children) into apprenticeships. [8] Masters were not only responsible for teaching their charges a trade, but were obligated to instruct their apprentices in reading, writing, and common arithmetic. [9] The humanitarian movement, which advocated giving poor children an opportunity for education, supported the idea that the State was responsible for the education of those children whose parents were not likely to attend to the matter themselves. [10] As Edgar Knight, another historian of public schools in the South, observed: By the time of the American Revolution, “the theory was gaining that caring for and educating and training poor children were functions of the State.” [11]

Thomas Jefferson, however, approached universal education from another point of view. His belief was that it was the business of the State to educate because a free country required an intelligent citizenry. [12] “Enlighten the people generally and tyranny and oppressions … will vanish ….” “If a nation expects to be ignorant and free in a state of civilization, it expects what never was and never will be.” [13] According to Jefferson, “schools … must be provided by the state” because to give “information to the people … is the most certain, and the most legitimate engine of government.” [14]

After Jefferson was elected governor of Virginia in 1776, he became personally involved in the revision of the state’s laws. In June 1779, the committee of revision presented the legislature with one hundred and twenty-six bills, among which were some Jefferson himself had principally written. The two most germane to our discussion here are his “Bill for the More General Diffusion of Knowledge” and “A Bill for Establishing Religious Freedom.” In the former he proposed three years of government-paid elementary schooling for all children, rich and poor alike; college (high schools) for those requiring a middle level of instruction; and finally a state-sponsored university and library to complete the educational edifice. Each county was to be divided into wards or districts, and the voters of each ward were to tax themselves in order to support their own local schools. This thoroughly socialist plan is what Dabney described as “the first proposal ever made for local taxation for public schools” in America. [15] Another interesting aspect of Jefferson’s advocacy was his belief that those who could neither read nor write should be denied state citizenship and the right to vote. [16] Although Jefferson supported compulsory taxation to provide public schools, “he took a moderate position on compulsory education.” [17] Jefferson did not believe it was proper to force a parent to educate his child. As Jefferson wrote:

It is better to tolerate the rare instance of a parent refusing to let his child be educated, than to shock the common feelings and ideas by the [felonious removal of the child from the parent’s custody] and [by the] education of the infant against the will of the father. [18]

In contrast, in his bill for establishing religious freedom Jefferson took a very libertarian position against all the elements of a state religion. He rejected state-licensed clergy, he refused to endorse state-approved prayer, curriculum, textbooks, compulsory attendance laws, and state-compelled financing. One wonders why Jefferson did not realize that the same principles that apply to state religious establishments apply to state educational establishments. [19] For example, Jefferson held that religion was a natural right of mankind, just as he supported the “unalienable rights of parents to direct the education of their children.” [20] However, on the issue of public taxation to support the church and the school, Jefferson took contradictory positions. “He declared that ‘to compel a man to furnish contributions of money for the propagation of opinions which he disbelieves is sinful and tyrannical’ and ‘that even forcing him to support this or that teacher of his own religious persuasion, is depriving him of the comfortable liberty of giving his contributions to the particular pastor whose morals he would make his pattern,’ …” [21] Despite his realization that coercion was wrong in the case of religion, Jefferson did not recognize that it was “unjust to take the property of one man to educate the children of another. … In essence Jefferson didn’t apply his own professed principles against coercive financing” of religion when it came “to education like he [sh]ould have.” [22] This error, from its small beginnings in Jefferson’s legislative bill, has led to massive state-run educational establishments all across the United States.

Government legislation on the subject of the poor and of apprentices was based on several questionable assumptions. The first assumption was that such children were entitled to the basics of an education. If they were, then such a service must be provided by their parents, the government, or some charitable institution. [23] Most proponents of an educational entitlement thought that it should be the responsibility of the State to provide children with schooling. Finally, it was assumed that no other means of accomplishing this goal existed, even though there was plenty of evidence that various types of education were being provided under voluntaryism.

Jefferson and others after him extended the first assumption by claiming that all children had a right to an education. The only question to be answered was: At whose expense? Jefferson’s answer was that the citizens of the county or ward should be taxed to provide all the children in their local jurisdiction with schools. Why didn’t the church reformers, Jefferson, and others of the time eschew the State and depend upon voluntary efforts? The only answer I have is this: the State was there. The human tendency is to take the easy way out. If the State had not been there, those advocating schooling for the uneducated poor would have had to 1) either organize the State from scratch; 2) dig into their own pockets and help fund that which they were advocating; or 3) organize (themselves and in concert with others who shared their idea) the necessary number of charity schools to provide education for the poor. Given the existence of the State, its prior concern with the indigent and their education, they took the easy way out: they advocated taxation. Why Jefferson couldn’t see the parallels between state provision of religion and state provision of education is an unexplainable anomaly. It is comparable to his being an owner of slaves when writing that “all men are created equal” in the Declaration of Independence.

Despite Jefferson’s advocacy of public schools, the idea of universal, state-paid education did not come about quickly. Educational historians of the South, time and time again, repeat that many Southerners had a “natural reluctance to being taxed.” Furthermore, the historians note that many Southerners held to the idea that it was not the function of the State to educate; that education was not conducive to good citizenship, that State instruction was a usurpation of parental rights, and that Negroes should never be educated. [24]. Here are some additional commentaries:

Local taxation of property for the support of community schools, entirely free and open to rich and poor alike, was not a popular measure. Two centuries of apprenticeship and poor laws had not developed a strong enough demand for the new type of education to overcome the dread of cost in taxes or to enforce the acceptance of the principle that the [S]tate should compel a man to tax himself for the education of his neighbor’s children. [25]

“The traditional hatred of taxes was universal in the South.” The planters “looked upon internal improvements [roads] as they did upon education, as mere excuses for taxation, and all taxation to them was evil. [26]

All taxes were an abomination to early Americans and taxation for schools was unthinkable for the old Virginians. If there were to be schools and institutions for learning, the funds for them must be provided in some other way than through taxes on property. [27]

The provision of education by the state to paupers “expressed the prevailing idea of the people that a man’s children should be educated by himself in his own social status, if possible, and that only the poor should be provided with the elements of an education at the expense of the [S]tate. The ruling class believed that any extended education of the masses would lead to unrest, to disappointment and to what the aristocrats called “leveling.” Their view was that the [S]tate should not interfere in the education of the children except when charity absolutely demanded it. [28]

In 1872, James Killebrew was appointed assistant superintendent of schools in Tennessee. His salary was paid by the Peabody Education Fund . “The greatest obstacle to the establishment of a real system of schools, declared Killebrew, was the old idea that education should be left to private enterprise; that it was wrong to tax the rich for the education of the poor; that the [S]tate had no right to compel a father to educate his children, much less those of his neighbor; that such procedure would tend to destroy the sense of obligation of the citizens to the discharge of their duty to their children and those of their fellow citizens.” [29]

Aversion to taxation has been the great obstacle to the schools in the Southern States. Taxes are simply money paid for civilized government. The savage alone is exempt from taxation. We were formerly taught that the best government was that which levied the smallest taxes. The future will teach that liberal taxation, fairly levied and properly applied, is the chief mark of a civilized people. In the old days we heard that it was robbery to tax Brown’s property to educate Jones’ children. In the new day no one will question the right of the [S]tate to tax both Brown and Jones to develop the [S]tate through its children. [30]

It has often been said that one government intervention leads to another. In the historical case being examined here, we find this happening. When supporters of State education of the indigent discovered that “the poor would rather keep their children at home [rather] than to send them to free [State] schools where they were branded [as] paupers,” they argued that ALL children, not just poor children should be educated at the expense of the State. “The true policy of the State is to recognize no distinction betwixt the rich and the poor; to put them all upon the same footing; … .” [31] In other words, if children of poor parents will not attend State schools, force everyone to attend State schools in order to avoid the stigma of ‘pauper’ schools.

The supporters of State-provided education had another way of defusing the objection to ‘pauper’ schools. As John Minor observed: “the government may give partial aid to all” via general taxation but still make every able-bodied father pay some of the additional cost of educating his children. This mixed method of local taxation and family contributions was known as the rate-bill system. Here is how it worked. Local school trustees contracted with a teacher for a term of teaching. At the end of the term, “they g[a]ve him an order upon the town superintendent for such portion of money as may have been voted by the district. … If the public money [wa]s not sufficient to pay the teacher’s wages, the trustees proceeded to make out a rate-bill for the residue, charging each parent or guardian, according to the number of days’ attendance of his children.” [32] Indigent families were exempt from such additional taxation. In New York State, during the late 1840s, “something like 40 per cent of the resources of the schools came from rates charged parents.” [33]

The struggle for and against the rate-bill system ran in two directions. Parents who were assessed the extra charges wanted to foist those expenses upon the State in the form of general taxation upon everyone. On the other hand, the general taxpayers, especially those without children, wanted the families of students to pay as much as they could. Furthermore, since the rate-bill system required every family to pay in proportion to the attendance of their children, there was a great inducement for many parents to wink at the absence and truancy of their children from school. [34] The final outcome of the struggle against the rate-bill system was decided by the immigrants who crowded into the large cities, such as New York. “They were without property to be taxed, but many of them had a vote, and they demanded education.” [35] The preponderance of the citizenry was in favor of “free elementary schools for all” and the last state to use the rate-bill system abandoned this method in 1871. [36]

Those who agitated to eliminate the rate-bill system advocated what they called “the free school” idea. This was the principle “that the schools should be absolutely free to all and supported at public and general expense.” [37] No longer would individual parents be assessed for sending their children to a local government school. Taxpayers who had no children would be forced to bear part of the expense of paying for the education of children via general taxation.

Some of the rhetoric to bring about this change is very interesting. In North Carolina, Calvin Henderson Wiley was “one of the most devoted champions of universal education our country has ever produced.” [38] He promoted state legislation which authorized the formation of districts permitting the people to tax themselves for their local schools if they desired to have them. He also assisted in founding “Library Associations” to help teachers collect books and establish circulating libraries. “Out of them grew county associations to improve the teachers, to diffuse knowledge on educational subjects, to overcome the prejudices against public schools, and to educate the public to tax themselves.” [39] State officials and school superintendents were also notorious for wanting to expand the role of their states in educational endeavors. As one commentator noted: “One of the duties of … school officials was to create a public sentiment in favor of public schools.” [40] For example, we find in Gov. Reuben Chapman’s message to the Alabama legislature of November 18, 1849 the following:

The subject of the common schools deserves all the consideration and encouragement it is in the power of the assembly to bestow. The whole theory of our form of Government is based upon the capacity of the people. Without a general diffusion of intelligence among them, the machinery of a Government thus constituted can not be expected to move on successfully. The highest and most important of all the duties of a free Government is to advance the cause of education, and guard against that decline of liberty which results from neglecting the minds of the people. [41]

Fifty years later, State School Superintendent John W. Abercromie of Alabama speaking in 1900 said

[I]f we would properly qualify our people for citizenship [we must] give to counties, townships, districts, and municipalities the power of taxation for educational purposes. If the people of any county, township, district, city or town desire to levy a tax upon their property to build a schoolhouse, or to supplement the State fund, for the purposes of educating their children, they should have the … power to do it. …There should be no limit … to the power of the people who own property to tax themselves for the purpose of fitting the children of the State for intelligent and patriotic citizenship. [42]

Another organization that played a significant part in the expansion of government schools in the South was a charitable trust founded in 1867, by George Peabody (1795-1869), a wealthy Baltimore businessman. [43] The purpose of the Peabody trust was to encourage and promote schools in “those portions of our beloved and common country which … suffered … the destructive ravages … of civil war.” [44] Although there was no stipulation in the original bequest of one million dollars, the trustees of the George Peabody Educational Fund made the decision that they would disburse funds only to those communities which would help themselves by raising matching funds through taxation. The Peabody Fund did not give aid to private or religious schools, or to any schools not affiliated with their State’s system. [45] The Reverend Barnas Sears was named general agent of the fund and he became one of the leading agitators for free public elementary schools in the South after the Civil War. “Free schools for the whole people” became his motto. [46] According to Dabney. Dr. Sears “preached free public schools as a necessity in a democratic government.” [47] His stated goal was to teach the taxpayers of the South “that there is no more legitimate tax that can be levied on property than that for the education of the masses.” [48] Jabez Lamar Monroe Curry succeeded Sears in 1881. “When told that ‘the state had no right to tax one man to educate another man’s children, that it was dangerous to educate the masses, or that to educate a poor white or a Negro meant to make a criminal or to spoil a laborer’,” Curry’s reply was that “Ignorance is no remedy for anything. If the State has a right to live at all, it has a right to educate.” [49]

Conclusion

The State’s right to exist was certainly never called into question by any Southerners, even those who supported secession from the North. The idea of “educating men for the service of the [S]tate traces back to Plato.” [50] Karl Marx embraced the idea in the tenth plank of The Communist Manifesto, which he and Engels published 1848: “Free education for all children in public schools.” In 1855, William Henry Ruffner, a Virginian, pointed out that “state education is but educational communism,” but even he and other opponents of government-run education never objected on general principles to the concept of taxation. [51] For example, Herbert Spencer in his 1842 series of articles “On the Proper Sphere of Government” never once questioned the propriety or morality of forcing people to contribute funds to a government which would then “administer justice.” Coming from a dissenting family, Spencer did recognize “the injustice of expecting men to assist in the maintenance of a plan of instruction which they do not approve; and forcing them to pay towards the expences [sic] of teaching, from which neither they nor their children derive any benefit.” [52] But apparently Spencer had no problem with forcing men to pay for police protection, defense from foreign enemies, and the settlement of legal disputes. In short, he did not object to taxation when it was used to support some function of government which he thought necessary or of which he approved.

To the voluntaryist, on the other hand, the very concept of taxation is morally wrong. Taxation is theft. Government agents must initiate force, or the threat of force, upon those who refuse to pay. R. C. Hoiles, founder of the Freedom Newspapers, was probably the first libertarian in the 20th Century to oppose government schools on the basis that they were tax-supported. He used to argue: if it is morally wrong for A to take money from B against B’s will, then it is wrong for A and C to take money from B. It is still wrong if A and C associate with hundreds of thousands of others to rob B. As he used to ask, at what point does the number of people involved in an act of thievery turn it into a morally proper activity? The answer should be obvious: a wrong is a wrong even if everyone supports it. [53]

In an exchange of letters on “Why Homeschool” in 1993, I wrote that the only consistent way to oppose government schools is to oppose them because they are tax-supported. [54] That means opposing every service government provides because everything the government does – from police protection, roads, courts, defense against foreign enemies to schools – is paid for via taxation. In short, that means opposing the very concept of government itself because government could not exist without taxation. Government violates the property rights of all those from whom it collects taxes. If it gave people the choice to pay for a service, or order less of it, or decline its services altogether, without suffering any punishment, then there would be no difference in principle between such a government and a voluntary organization. People could shop for educational services wherever and however they chose. Yes, some people would remain unable to read or write, if they were not forced to attend schools, and if their parents were not forced to pay for their schooling. However, it is interesting to note that we have not overcome the problem of illiteracy even after a century and a half of educational coercion and government schools. On the other hand, we would have avoided all the ill-fated consequences of government in our lives and schooling.

Since voluntaryists are opposed to the use of coercion to support governments, the question of how government should spend its tax revenues disappears. Most voluntaryists support education, roads, and protection services. It is not these ends which they call into question, but rather the coercive means used by the State to provide them. Since taxation is theft, taxation cannot legitimately be used to attain any ends. And of one thing we can be certain: If you take care of the means, the end will take care of itself. And another: if you try to force the end, the means will destroy and vitiate whatever good intentions you start out with.

There is only one way to freedom and that is by voluntary means. All else will fail. But neither is there any guarantee that voluntaryism will succeed, but if it does, or at least to the extent that it does, we can be assured that it will depend on obtaining people’s willing cooperation. Compelling them to “cooperate” is not only contradictory, but it will never work.

End Notes

[1] Charles William Dabney, UNIVERSAL EDUCATION IN THE SOUTH In Two Volumes. All citations are to Volume I: From the Beginnings to 1900, Chapel Hill: The University of North Carolina Press, 1936, p. 3. On the influence of the Prussian educational system in Virginia in the late 1830s, see Charles William Dabney, “Dr. Benjamin M. Smith’s Report on the Prussian Primary School System,” in four installments beginning in XVI THE VIRGINIA TEACHER (September 1935), pp. 117-124.

[2] ibid., p. 4.

[3] ibid., p. 5.

[4] ibid., p. 8.

[5] John B. Minor, INSTITUTES OF COMMON AND STATUTE LAW, Volume I, Second Edition, Richmond: Printed for the Author, 1876, Book I, Chapter XVI, p. 384. It is interesting to note how governments expanded Jefferson’s idea of three months of schooling per year for three years to nine or ten months of government education per year for twelve years. Give governments an inch and they will take a mile!

[6] Edgar W. Knight, PUBLIC EDUCATION IN THE SOUTH, Boston: Ginn and Company, 1922, p. 161.

[7] ibid., p. 146.

[8] ibid., pp. 48-50 and p. 56.

[9] Minor, op. cit., p. 396.

[10] Marcus W. Jernegan, “Compulsory Education in the Southern Colonies, XXVII THE SCHOOL REVIEW (June 1919), pp. 405-425 at p. 414 and p. 422.

[11] Knight, op. cit., p. 56.

[12] John C. Henderson, THOMAS JEFFERSON’S VIEW ON PUBLIC EDUCATION, New York: AMS Press, 1970 (originally published 1890), p. 35.

[13] Dabney, op. cit., p. 5.

[14] ibid., pp. 19-20.

[15] ibid., p. 10.

[16] Henderson, op. cit., pp. 344-345.

[17] Dabney, op. cit., p. 13.

[18] Kerry L. Morgan, REAL CHOICE REAL FREEDOM IN AMERICAN EDUCATION, Lanham: University Press of America, 1997, p. 107 and p. 120 (Note 5).

[19] ibid., p. 106.

[20] ibid.

[21] ibid., p. 107.

[22] ibid., pp. 107-108.

[23] Dabney, op. cit., p. 27.

[24] John Furman Thomason, THE FOUNDATIONS OF THE PUBLIC SCHOOLS IN SOUTH CAROLINA, Columbia: The State Company, 1925, p. 223.

[25] William Arthur Maddox, THE FREE SCHOOL IDEA IN VIRGINIA BEFORE THE CIVIL WAR, New York: Teacher’s College, Columbia University, 1918. Reprint edition by Arno Press and the New York Times, 1969, p. 16.

[26] Dabney, op. cit., p. 30 and p. 31.

[27] ibid., p. 35.

[28] ibid., p. 40.

[29] ibid., p. 302.

[30] ibid., p. 204. This is a direct quote from Charles Duncan McIver, an agitator for public schools in North Carolina throughout the 1890s.

[31] ibid., pp. 228-229.

[32] James B. Conant, THOMAS JEFFERSON AND THE DEVELOPMENT OF AMERICAN PUBLIC EDUCATION, Berkeley: University of California Press, 1962, pp. 33-34.

[33] ibid., p. 35

[34] ibid., p. 34.

[35] ibid., p. 36.

[36] ibid.

[37] Andrew Sloan Draper, ORIGIN AND DEVELOPMENT OF THE COMMON SCHOOL SYSTEM OF THE STATE OF NEW YORK, Syracuse: C. W. Bardeen, Publisher, 1903, p. 52.

[38] Dabney, op. cit., p. 168.

[39] ibid., p. 170.

[40] Cornelius J. Heatwole, A HISTORY OF EDUCATION IN VIRGINIA, New York: The Macmillan Company, 1916, p. 228.

[41] Stephen B. Weeks, HISTORY OF PUBLIC SCHOOL EDUCATION IN ALABAMA, Washington, D.C.: U. S. Government Printing Office, 1915. Reprinted by Negro Universities Press, Westport, Connecticut, 1971, pp. 51-52.

[42] ibid., pp. 135-136. Also cited in Knight, op. cit., pp. 423-424.

[43] Dabney, op. cit., p. 106.

[44] Knight, op. cit., p. 384.

[45] Dabney, op. cit, p. 111 and p. 116.

[46] Knight, op. cit., p. 386. Barnas Sears (1802-1880) had been “the successor to Horace Mann in the office of the Board of Education of Massachusetts” (Dabney, op. cit., p. 111).

[47] Dabney, op. cit., p. 421.

[48] ibid., p. 119.

[49] ibid., p. 123 and p. 128.

[50] ibid., p. 13.

[51] William Henry Ruffner, “State Education Radically Wrong,” forthcoming in THE VOLUNTARYIST. Originally written and published anonymously in the PRESBYTERIAN CRITIC (1855) and reprinted 40 SOUTHERN PLANTER AND FARMER (April 1879).

[52] Herbert Spencer, THE PROPER SPHERE OF GOVERNMENT, with an Introduction by George H. Smith. Special reprint from RAMPART INDIVIDUALIST: A JOURNAL OF FREE MARKET SCHOLARSHIP, Vol. I, No. 1 & 2 (no date), p. 85. “The Proper Sphere of Government” was originally published in Edward Miall’s THE NONCONFORMIST in twelve parts, beginning in June 1842.

[53] “R. C. Hoiles Revisited,” forthcoming in THE VOLUNTARYIST. Originally printed in the Colorado Springs GAZETTE-TELEGRAPH, July 11, 1972, p. 6-A.

[54] “Why Homeschool?”, Excerpts of Correspondence between Helen Hegener and Carl Watner, Whole No. 65, THE VOLUNTARYIST, December 1993, and reprinted in Carl Watner, editor, I MUST SPEAK OUT, San Francisco: Fox and Wilkes, 1999, pp. 177-181.

Boxed quote to accompany this article:

There can be no greater stretch of arbitrary power than is required to seize children from their parents, teach them whatever the authorities decree they shall be taught, and expropriate from the parents the funds to pay for the procedure. … “Free education” [is] the most absolute contradiction of facts by terminology of which the language is capable. Everything about such schools is compulsory, not free; … . A tax-supported, compulsory educational system is the complete model of the totalitarian state.

– Isabel Paterson, THE GOD OF THE MACHINE (1943),

from Chapter XXI, “Our Japanized Educational System.” [Note: Ms. Paterson failed to observe that the expropriation was from all taxpayers, not just the parents.]

Schools For All


By Oscar B. Johannsen

Each individual is responsible for his own well-being. He feeds and clothes himself. Some do it better than others, but with the exception of the physically and mentally handicapped, there is no question of the individual’s obligation. Even in the case of the handicapped, he must care for himself to the extent he is able. Failure to allow him to do so to the limit of his capacity leads very often to a frustrated, sick man, ill in ways more serious than the infirmity itself.

Just as the individual is responsible for his own and his children’s physical well-being, he is likewise responsible for his own and his children’s education. The parent must pay to feed the child’s stomach. He must also pay to feed the child’s mind.

Had someone a hundred odd years ago persuaded people that the feeding and clothing of children was a duty of Government and this function was thereupon assumed by it, and if somebody today were to suggest that it actually devolved to the parents, objections would be raised. It would be claimed that the parents could not possibly bear the cost alone; that such action constituted an attempt to feed and clothe the children of the rich better than the rest; that this was not democratic; that this was striking the very foundations of society.

Fortunately, since no one did arise who could sell that idea to the people, the parents today do care for their children and do it reasonably well. Far from hurting society, this responsibility is necessary from the viewpoint of the children as well as the parents. It enhances the love and affection of the children and the parents; it brings happiness to the parents in the knowledge that by their efforts their children are fed and clothed; it increases the respect and love of the children, who are thereby made aware of their dependence on their parents – all of which makes for a better society.

Unfortunately, about 1830 some educators did arise who convinced many that education was a governmental responsibility, with the result that today, for all practical purposes, primary and secondary schools are a function of local government, the cost of which is borne by taxes. That being the case, whenever the proposition arises that parents should pay for the education as well as the physical care of their children, the objection is raised that they could not possibly afford to do so.

In large measure, however, they are paying for it now because the major portion of all taxes comes from the mass of the people and not from the few with large incomes. While any one person may only pay a portion of his children’s public school training, he does not stop when they graduate since his taxes continue. If the parents live the normal life span of years, no doubt they easily pay in taxes as much, if not more, as they would have paid for sending their children to private schools if public schools did not exist.

Just as no one wishes to pay for the care of someone else’s children, no one really wishes to pay for their education. Instinctively, it is felt that those who brought them into the world should bear their cost. If there is validity to the argument that society should pay for children’s education since well-educated children will bring about a better society, then since well-fed children will mean a healthier society, the cost of feeding them should also be society’s. For that matter, if this argument holds water, since health comes first, society should pay for their physical care and only after that has been attended to, pay for their education.

Putting education back into the hands of the people concerned will force them to be sure that their children are receiving the best of that which they are capable; will require the parents to take an active interest in choosing the proper school; will help engender mutual respect and love as parents and children work at solving this problem.

Actually, when all schools are private the cost of education is the least possible. Competition forces them to be highly efficient in order to keep the costs down, so that tuition fees will be low enough to attract customers – the pupils.

There will, of course, always be orphans and children of parents who cannot afford to defray the expenses of education. They will be aided by charitable organizations and private individuals, just as they are now helped in obtaining the proper physical necessities of life. Thus, no child need be denied the benefits of private school.

[Editor’s Note: These excerpts were taken from PRIVATE SCHOOLS FOR ALL, published by the Committee of One, Roselle Park, NJ. No date given, Section IV, pages 7-9.]

Voluntaryism in the European Anarchist Tradition


Carl Watner

Introduction

Voluntaryism, the doctrine that the State should be abolished through peaceful, non-electoral means, has been advocated by anarchists both in Europe and America. My earlier pamphlets, Voluntaryism in the Libertarian Tradition and A Voluntaryist Bibliography, Annotated generally dealt with the roots of the anti-electoral, voluntaryist tradition and its manifestations in the United States and England. This essay, however, deals primarily with the expression of this tradition by European anarchists. The picture presented here is not an exaggerated view of the anti-political nature of European anarchism, but it is one seen through a single lens. There are many other aspects and elements of European anarchism, which, although not examined here, are still important. Nevertheless, any historical judgment will credit anti-parliamentarianism as one of the most important and long-lasting aspects of the anarchist tradition, both in Europe and North America.

Although Emma Goldman was a naturalized U.S. citizen, her roots were European and many of the activities and debates she engaged in involved European affairs. Her appearance in this essay also epitomizes the difference in emphasis between individualist-anarchists and collectivist-anarchists. The former have approached libertarian history from the perspective of the self-ownership principle; that is anarchists and libertarians were usually defined by their adherence to the axiom that each person is a self-owner and should control his own person and justly owned property. Within the context of English and American history this primarily meant dealing with the radical individualists and radical abolitionists from the 18th, 19th, and 20th Centuries. However, the European anarchist tradition never fully developed this principle of self-ownership in the same manner as the individualist-anarchists in the English speaking world. It was always anti-authoritarian and had a more collectivist orientation towards property ownership than did the individualist tradition.

Anarchists of whatever persuasion always have and always will view the State as a criminal institution, as a band of thieves and robbers who violate the person and property rights of their victims. It is this anarchist insight into the nature of the State – that the State is inherently and necessarily an invasive institution – which distinctly identifies the anarchist, whether individualist or collectivist. What unites them is their commonly shared view of the State as a criminal gang and as the chief enemy and most dangerous enemy of all people in society. Where they differ is in their expectations regarding the form a future anarchist society will take. Since anarchism is the doctrine that all the affairs of the people should be conducted on a voluntary basis, it is up to the people who compose such a society to arrange their affairs as suits them. Many European anarchists anticipated a communal, or collectivist organization of society, once the State was abolished. However, as much as their future expectations differed from those of the individualists, their approach to social change was voluntaryist and anti-political. Although the European anarchist tradition was often looked upon as fraught with the violence of terrorists and war, it included many nonviolent revolutionaries among its ranks. As we shall see, the European experiences offer a rich buffet of historical lessons for all voluntaryists today.

Proudhon

Although one of the earliest popularizers of the term “anarchism” was Pierre-Joseph Proudhon (1809-1865), another Frenchman, Anselme Bellegarrigue, his contemporary, was the first to publish a periodical with an explicitly anarchist title. His L’Anarchie: Journal De L’Ordre, first appeared in April, 1850. Bellegarrigue was even more anti-electoral than Proudhon and was explicitly nonviolent. According to him, the task of abolishing governments “must be carried out neither by political parties, which will always seek to dominate, nor by violent revolution, which needs leaders like any other military operation. The people once enlightened will act for itself.” The people will make its own revolution, by the sole strength of right, the force of inertia, “the refusal to co-operate.” From the refusal to co-operate stems the abrogation of the laws that legalize murder and the proclamation of equity.

Both Bellegarrigue and Proudhon stressed the basic freedom and spontaneity of anarchism and saw that these elements precluded the use of rigid organizations, particularly anything like a political party, which sought to seize and hold power, for creating the future society. “All parties without exception, in so far as they seek for power, are varieties of absolutism”, said Proudhon, and none of his followers have departed from this position. From his own personal experiences in parliamentary affairs, Proudhon came to reject parliamentary institutions because “they mean that the individual abdicates his sovereignty by handing it over to a representative; once he has done this, decisions may be reached in his name over which he no longer has any control.” Proudhon opposed democratic parliaments as well as monarchs, such as Emperor Napoleon III, when he proudly declared: “Whoever puts his hand on me to govern me is an usurper and a tyrant; I declare him my enemy.”

Proudhon did not begin his “political” career with a rejection of electoral activity, however. In April 1848, he narrowly missed being elected to the Constituent Assembly, and in June of that same year he actually was elected. There is some speculation that he ran for office with the idea of gathering support for his People’s Bank, since he had already approached a government cabinet minister for assistance in promoting the project. His experience was disillusioning: “As soon as I set foot in the Parliamentary Sinai, … I ceased to be in touch with the masses; because I was absorbed by my legislative work. I entirely lost sight of the current of events.” It was soon clear that, he was completely out of place in the Assembly. As he recalled his election of 1848, a year afterwards Proudhon remarked with some justification:

When I think of all I have written and published for ten years on the role of the state in society, on the subordination of power and the revolutionary incapacity of government, I am tempted to believe that my election was the effect of a misunderstanding on the part of the people.

His biographer, George Woodcock, adds, “it seems to have been the effect of a misunderstanding on his own part as well.”

While still in Parliament, Proudhon was charged with sedition when he denounced Louis-Napoleon. His parliamentary immunity was waived by his colleagues, and he was sentenced to three years in prison and a fine of 3000 francs. Thus ended his first involvement in real politics. Years later, in 1863, when the Bonapartist government held elections, Proudhon became the center of an anti-voting movement. Committees of Abstention were set up in Paris and Bourdeaux and Proudhon penned a detailed exposition of his abstentionist arguments, which appeared in April 1863, under the title Les Democrates Assermentes et les Refractaires (Oath-Taking Democrats and Non-Jurors). Despite some little success, the Committee of Abstention disbanded after the election. “Yet it bequeathed to the movements that followed it, and particularly to anarchism and syndicalism, at least two important elements – the rejection of expediency as a dominant element in political behaviour, and the rejection of the democratic myth of the vote as a universal political panacea.”

Although Proudhon may not have totally rejected all forms of parliamentarism and voting, he believed that political parties were designed to serve the ruling classes. It is certain that his own political experiences “hardened his distrust of political methods and helped to create the anti-parliamentartianism that marked his last years and was inherited by the anarchist movement in general.” Besides Proudhon, there were several other European anarchists with similar electoral experiences. Karl Grun, one of the most ardent German converts of Proudhon, served “a short disillusioning period as a parliamentarian – in the Prussian National Assembly in 1849, …” Another anarchist with similar experience was the Dutchman, Ferdinand Domela Nieuwenhuis, who was also an extreme anti-militarist. He was elected to parliament in 1888, as a Socialist and he remained there for three years. Like Proudhon and Grun, he found it a saddening experience, and emerged a convinced anti-parliamentarian and began turning towards anarchism. (This also recalls to mind the British member of Parliament, Auberon Herbert, who evolved into a voluntaryist.)

The anarchist dissatisfaction with electoral politics was not totally a one way street. There were prominent anarchists who turned towards parliamentary socialism, as they became disillusioned with the possibilities of achieving the “anarchist revolution”. Paul Brousse (1844-1912) was one such personality. He had fallen under the influence of Bakunin in the early 1870’s and became one of the leading exponents of the anarchist “propaganda by deed” (acts of violent terrorism). After 1877, he became mainly concerned with the revival of the French socialist movement. “This revival, combined with the growing isolation and ineffectiveness of the anarchists, led Brousse to change his ideas on political tactics, and when he returned to France in 1880, he had abandoned the central tenet of anarchism, abstention from the use of the vote, although he continued to believe in the ideal of anarcho-communist society.”

In Brousse’s own case, he became disillusioned with the possibility of terror tactics winning a majority of the masses over to anarchism and thus became willing to experiment with electoral tactics instead. However previous to his “political” conversion, in 1875, he had written a pamphlet critical of universal suffrage, attacking it both on the basis of the French experience, as well as criticizing its theoretical shortcomings. In the words of his biographer, Brousse illustrated “how universal suffrage had been used throughout the century as an instrument of the bourgeoisie, while posturing as an expression of the will of the people.” Brousse concluded that electoral agitation would only confirm the bourgeoisie in power.

Despite his anti-electoral outpourings, Brousse swallowed his pride and turned to electoral action, when his anarchist strategies failed to bring about any immediate results. He joined with the socialists and became founder of a political party identified with the term “possibilism”. The “possibilists” had as their aim “to achieve as soon as possible the organization of public services for the immediate needs of the working class. One of the ways this could be achieved was through municipal action” and politics. The choice he made was a way out of the dilemma faced by anarchists in the late 1870’s and 1880’s. For many saw the dogma of electoral abstention only as a tactic and when it proved ineffective they were ready to resort to electoral efforts or trade unionism.

Syndicalism

The failure of terror tactics during the 1880’s and early 1890’s created a disillusionment in anarchist ranks, as we have seen. This resulted in large numbers of French anarchists becoming syndicalists and entering workers unions. Revolutionary trade unionism, or syndicalism as it became known, was premised upon the class struggle between wage earners (the proletariat) and the State, represented by property owners and the bourgeoisie. The outcome of the class struggle would result in a social revolution and the establishment of a socialist society, in which autonomous syndicates would control each industry. The syndicates in turn would be controlled by the workers of that particular branch of industry and would unite in general national federations. Syndicalists thus combined the Marxian elements of class struggle and distribution according to need with the collectivist concept of property and the anarchist idea of statelessness. Syndicates were unique in that they placed a distinctive emphasis on the role of the labor union in the struggle against the State and opposed parliamentary democracy and political weapons in the class struggle.

It was from the two makers of the anarchist tradition, Proudhon, and Michael Bakunin (1814-1876) that the French syndicalists inherited their “over-powering hatred of the centralized state, a sharp distrust of politicians, and a rudimentary conception of workers’ control in industry.” Imbued with strong anarchist tendencies, many of these unions came to regard the State with hostile eyes and to reject the conquest of political power. The general strike, comprising workers in all trade unions, rather than political parties, was to be the primary means of achieving the social revolution.

Many anarchists participated in syndicalist unions, and in fact it was their participation which largely prevented these unions from becoming subsidiary to the political parties in their respective countries. There was a clear distinction between parliamentary socialism and anarcho-syndicalism. The anarchists believed that the State could never become an instrument of emancipation even in the hands of a socialist government. These anarchists denounced parliamentary action as a “pellmell of compromise, of corruption, of charlatanism and of absurdities, which does no constructive work.” On the other hand, most European socialists called for the workingman to participate in parliamentary life. They didn’t think that political abstention was helpful or possible. The anarcho-syndicalists responded that “Politics can never be the way of emancipation for the workers. … You can change the form of political state, …, but it will still be coercive.”

There was always a danger of these anarchist unions being co-opted by political parties, socialist or Marxist. In 1907, a leading Italian anarchist, Errico Malatesta, (whose life and ideas will be examined in greater detail) cautioned anarchists “against entering unions infested with socialist politicians, lest they lose sight of the ultimate goal of a classless society. Fearful that syndicalism would sink into the morass of trade-unionist reformism and ‘bureaucratism’, Malatesta warned his anarchist comrades not to become union officials.” The distrust of parliamentary methods, particularly by the French syndicalists, was reinforced by the sell-outs performed by their top leaders. Many French anarcho-syndicalists felt that they were sold out when in 1899, Alexander Millerand accepted the post of Minister of Commerce.

This anti-political bias was the confirmed policy of nearly all the syndicalist unions all over Europe. Syndicalism was best known for its advocacy of direct action and the general strike. Workmen were warned against even accepting beneficial labor legislation since they would be reinforcing a power they wanted to destroy. Labor reform could only be obtained independently of parliamentarism.

The Italian Debate

From their very beginning, anarchists had argued that parliamentary activity by socialists would corrupt their principles, and that socialists in bourgeoisie legislatures could not sincerely and effectively work for the abolition of the State. In Italy, where Bakunin had spawned an active anarchist movement, there were echoes of this dispute for many decades. Much of the Italian working class was reluctant to participate in any kind of disciplined party activity and was against any kind of parliamentary life, for the very reasons cited by the anarchists. Workers elected to office soon became renegades to their cause.

These ideas and the defense of the anarchist abstentionist position were promoted by all of the prominent Italian anarchists during the last decade of the 19th Century. One of them, Luigi Galleani, in his recently translated The End of Anarchism?, wrote:

The anarchists’ electoral abstentionism implies not only a conception that is opposed to the principle of representation (which is totally rejected by anarchism), it implies above all an absolute lack of confidence in the State. And this distrust, which is instinctive … is for the anarchists the result of their historical experience with the State and its function. … Furthermore, abstentionism has consequences which are much less superficial than the inert apathy ascribed to it. It strips the State of the constitutional fraud with which it presents itself to the gullible as the true representative of the whole nation, and in so doing, exposes its essential character as representative, procurer, and policeman of the ruling classes.

Galleani’s book was written as a rebuttal to Saverio Merlino. At one time a very prominent Italian anarchist and lawyer, Merlino became dissatisfied with anarchism in the late 1890’s, and moved closer and closer to parliamentary socialism. He eventually became a politician himself. Merlino’s defection was a source of concern to those remaining within the Italian anarchist movement and some of its leading theoreticians, like Galleani and Errico Malatesta, engaged in long polemical discussions in order to counter the effect of Merlino’s defection.

Merlino had been living outside Italy until 1894, and when he returned to Naples he was arrested and imprisoned there to serve out an old sentence. He was freed in late 1896 or early 1897, and soon thereafter informed the conservative newspaper, Il Messaggero, that his political opinions had changed. This provoked a debate with Errico Malatesta, which continued until 1898, when Malatesta was arrested. Merlino concluded that he no longer considered himself an anarchist, and would rather define himself as a ‘libertarian socialist’.

Furthermore, he now approved of parliamentary action, so much so, that, in agreement with other friends, he proposed to present Galleani (who was then also confined as a political prisoner) as a candidate for Parliament on the Socialist Party ticket as a protest against political detention and as a means to set him free by popular request. Galleani refused the offer. He and other anarchist prisoners published a special newspaper, in which they rejected the use of electoral means, even as a way of freeing themselves. As anarchists they wished to assert, “once and for all their firm refusal to compromise, or in any way distort their opposition to the State – a fundamental tenet of their convictions.” The front page of their paper carried an editorial, signed by Galleani, titled, “The faith remains unshaken”. The hostages were determined to save the dignity of their principles and would rather remain in the squalor of their jails or their islands of confinement, at peace with themselves, “than return to the so-called free world by bowing down to their jailers – whom they despised with concessions they knew to be false and shameful.”

The debate between Merlino and Malatesta received wide-spread attention both in Italy and abroad. Emma Goldman summarized it years later when she stated her position that anarchists should not cooperate with communists in elections. She wrote to Alexander Berkman, that

You probably remember the controversy between Malatesta and Merlino. Of course fascism wasn’t known then. But black reaction was. And it was Merlino who argued that anarchists by joining the socialists during elections would help defeat the reactionary gang. I don’t know whether you remember Malatesta’s reply. It was to the effect that the anarchists would, as they had always done, merely get the chestnuts out of the fire for the socialists and liberals. And they would injure their ideas beyond repair.

Merlino’s basic thesis was that the struggle for liberty must be fought on all fronts, including electoral politics. Although he recognized that anarchists do not aspire to political power, he did not consider it contrary to their principles to participate in electoral struggles against reactionary regimes. It was better to support a republican or socialist candidate than a conservative one who was likely to impose martial law. Merlino looked with disfavor on the anarchist abstentionist position because he thought it had brought about two negative results: 1) the separation of the abstentionist anarchists from the most active and militant part of the populace; and 2) their abstention served to weaken them in front of the government.

In practice, Merlino saw nothing contrary to anarchist principles in the electoral struggle. He did refuse, however, to condone anarchists serving as ministers in the government. This did not preclude the election of deputies to parliament, who would probably always remain in the minority. Their election would be a method of popular agitation against a reactionary government; it would be their duty to speak out against the existing government, denouncing its arbitrariness. Finally Merlino conceded, that although parliamentary methods, as all things of this world, had their draw backs, it was a perfectly valid method of agitation and propaganda, suitable to be used by anarchists.

Malatesta bitterly opposed Merlino’s ideas. One of his main themes was that by getting people accustomed to voting and delegating authority they are made powerless in handling their own communal affairs. Since anarchists don’t aspire to power, there was no motive for them to assist those who do. Both Galleani and Malatesta rejected the use of protest candidates because they took away the unity of the struggle which constituted the characteristic opposition of anarchism to politics. For Malatesta, the essence of parliamentarism was that parliaments can make and impose laws. Contrary to Merlino, Malatesta thought that all anarchists had to fight this idea, as anarchists do not grant to others the ability to bind them. As Malatesta stated, “Parliamentarism is a form of government and government means legislative power, judicial and executive powers; it means violence and coercion, and the imposition of force and the will of the governors on the governed.” Thus it must always and firmly be rejected by anarchists.

Malatesta also argued that even if anarchists could win at electoral politics they would still not want to hold positions of power. “We are against the principle of government and we do not believe that participating in it is the way to renounce power.” Furthermore, he recognized that abstentionism, although a question of tactics, was integrally related to the question of anarchist principles. “When one renounces it [abstentionism] one ends with renouncing also the principles involved. And that happens because of the natural connection between means and ends.” Finally he argued that instead of legitimizing parliamentary government, anarchists should stand for its abolition. He wrote:

Our mission, as anarchists, instead is showing to the people that parliamentary government, although it is the least bad of the types of government, is still a government. THE REMEDY WILL NOT BE IN CHANGING THE FORM OF GOVERNMENT BUT IN ABOLISHING IT.

The Merlino-Malatesta debate foreshadowed the problems that 20th Century anarchists were to encounter in their efforts at political collaboration. We will find this true both in the case of the Russian and Spanish anarchists which will now be examined.

Anarchists And The Russian Revolution

The historian, Paul Avrich has noted that the anarchists in Russia had always set themselves apart from other radical groups by their “implacable opposition to the state in any form. Faithfully they cleaved to Bakunin’s dictum that every government, no matter who controls it, is an instrument of oppression. Nor did they exclude the ‘dictatorship of the proletariat’ from this indictment, …” Years before Bakunin had predicted the anarchists’ differences with Marx, when he had written in Statehood and Anarchy that the dictatorship of the proletariat would be “the most autocratic, the most despotic, the most arrogant, and the most contemptuous of all regimes.” Though the anarchists desired, along with Lenin, to destroy the Provisional Government, Bakunin’s warnings about the power hungry communists lingered in their minds.

When the Czar abdicated in mid-March, 1917, a Provisional Government was set up under Prince Lvov, who was superseded by Alexander Kerensky in July. When Kropotkin returned to Russia that summer, he was well received by the masses and the government. Kerensky offered the well-known libertarian a cabinet post as Minister of Education as well as a state pension, both of which Kropotkin declined. Kerensky certainly had had in mind capitalizing on the popularity of Kropotkin if he could.

Much to the dismay of the anarchists, the downfall of the Czar fell far short of their principal objective, which was the social revolution and abolition of the Russian government. Although the February revolution had overthrown the monarchy, it failed to eliminate the State. Some anarchists compared the February rising to a game of musical chairs, in which one ruler took the seat of another. Thus the immediate aims of both the Bolsheviks and the anarchists came to coincide since both desired the elimination of the Provisional Government. As the noted historian of this era, Paul Avrich, has written, this “was all they shared in common, however. Collaboration on this end, ultimately resulted in the destruction of anarchism in Russia.”

Kerensky’s Provisional Government had elections scheduled for October, and as the time drew near for the Constituent Assembly to be selected, “anarchist spokesmen poured forth a veritable torrent of invective on the subject of representative government.” Alexander Shapiro, whom we shall meet again in Spain, wrote that “no parliament can break the path toward liberty, that the good society can be realized only through ‘the abolition of all power’ … Bill Shatov, another Russian emigre anarchist, declared that political power in any shape … was not worth a rotten egg” and that “political power can give us nothing.”

When Lenin seized power in the November 1917 coup, he was readily assisted by the anarchists. The latter blindly hoped that no new government would take the place of the Provisional one. “Disregarding the preachments of Bakunin and Kropotkin against political ‘coups’, they had taken part in a seizure of power in the belief that power, once captured, could somehow be diffused and eliminated.” With the establishment of the Bolshevik government, they found that it was impossible to eliminate political power by capturing it. This … marriage of convenience” (as Paul Avrich termed it), between the anarchists and Lenin, lasted only as long as Lenin wanted it to. Lenin had used the anarchists to his own advantage and when he was finished with them, there was nothing more to do than to eliminate them, since they were truly a threat to the Communist Party.

The antagonism between the Soviets and the anarchists was further heightened when Lenin opened peace talks at Brest-Litovsk in the Spring of 1918. Many anarchists had become so disillusioned with Lenin, that they sought a complete break with him. The Bolsheviks, for their part, began to contemplate the suppression of their former allies, who had outlived their usefulness. A contemporary anarchist critique of Bolshevik power argued that it had offered abundant proof that “state power possessed inalienable characteristics; it can change its label, its theory, and its servitors, but in essence it merely remains power and despotism in new forms.”

Finally in April 1918, armed violence broke out between the Bolsheviks and anarchists when the government conducted a raid against 26 anarchist centers in Moscow. A dozen Cheka agents were slaughtered, about 40 anarchists were killed or wounded, and more than 500 were taken prisoner. Practically all the anarchist presses and periodicals were closed down and shortly afterwards, the Cheka conducted similar raids in Petrograd and the provinces.

The anarchists reacted by accusing the Bolsheviks of having acted as “Judases” and betrayers. They also turned to violence to defend themselves and counter-attack. Anarchist groups bombed the office of the Moscow Committee of the Communist Party while it was in session during 1919. Shortly before the bombing they had described the Bolshevik dictatorship as the worst tyranny in human history. The violence was denounced by most prominent anarchist leaders, but nevertheless the Soviet government used this violence as an excuse to make massive new arrests from anarchist ranks. “Bolshevik spokesmen maintained that with the survival of the revolution at stake, it was imperative to snuff out violent opposition from every quarter. No anarchists, they insisted, were being arrested for their beliefs, but only for their criminal deeds.”

Paul Avrich has written that, “The deepening of the Civil War of 1918-1921 threw the anarchists into a quandary over whether to assist the Bolsheviks in their internecine with the Whites. Ardent libertarians, the anarchists found the repressive policies of the Soviet government utterly reprehensible; yet the prospect of a White victory seemed even worse.” The anarchists realized that by refusing to come to the assistance of the Bolsheviks, they might help tip the scales in favor of the Whites. The anarchists were split apart by this issue opinions ranged all across the spectrum; from eager collaboration with the Communist Party to active, violent resistance against them. Some anarchists even became Communist Party members. In the end, a great many gave varying degrees of support to the regime. Nevertheless there there were a few anarchist stalwarts and die-hards who had utmost contempt for their renegade colleagues. They contemptuously labeled them “Soviet anarchists” and claimed they had succumbed to the blandishments of politics. “Again and again, they warned that political power is evil, that it corrupts all who wield it, that government of any kind stifles the revolutionary spirit of the people and robs them of their freedom.”

Lenin was impressed with the support provided by some of his “Soviet anarchists” and in 1919, he commented that many anarchists were becoming dedicated supporters of Soviet power. Bill Shatov was an outstanding example. Shatov, whose comments against political power we read earlier, served Lenin’s government as a military officer during 1919 (he took on a significant part of organizing the defense of Petrograd) and then as Minister of Transport in the Far Eastern Republic in 1920. Several years later he was sent to the East to supervise the construction of the Turk-Sib Railroad. (Perhaps it was poetic justice that Shatov was exiled to Siberia and was believed to have been shot during the purges of the late 1930’s.) Shatov justified his participation in the government by citing the danger of a reactionary takeover. Nevertheless, he admitted to Emma Goldman and Alexander Berkman, after their arrival in Russia in January 1920, that “the Communist State in action is exactly what we anarchists have always claimed it would be – a tightly centralized power still more strengthened by the dangers of Revolution.”

When Kropotkin died in February 1921, his funeral represented the last great anarchist gathering in Russia. Certain important anarchist political prisoners were released from Cheka prisons for the day and public support for the deceased “anarchist prince” was overwhelming. However, the following month, March 1921 witnessed the climax of the Soviet atrocities against the anarchists. The sailors and civilian population of Kronstadt, an island base in the Gulf of Finland, revolted against the Soviets. The rebels were suppressed by the Red Army, under the direction of Trotsky. Following the climax of the revolt, new raids against the anarchists swept the country. Few anarchists were left at large, their book stores were closed, and even the followers of the pacifist Tolstoy were imprisoned or banished. A number of pacifists had already been shot during the Civil War for refusing to serve in the Red Army.

It was at this time that Emma Goldman, Alexander Berkman and other foreign-born anarchists were in Russia, hoping to witness the revolution in practice. Their expectations were sorely disappointed. Emma Goldman threatened to stage a personal protest in order to call to Lenin’s attention the persecution of the anarchists in Russia. Many of them were already in jail (where they had participated in at least one prolonged hunger strike) and many others had been shot. Finally the Soviets granted amnesty to many of the better known anarchist prisoners who had no record of violent opposition to the Soviet government. These freed prisoners had to leave the country at once. Meanwhile, “Emma Goldman, Alexander Berkman, and Sanya [Alexander] Schapiro, profoundly disheartened by the turn the revolution had taken, had made up their minds to emigrate also.”

Emma Goldman: On Revolution And Elections

Goldman and Berkman had been in Russia for nearly two years (January 1920 to December 1921) and had seen the revolution in action. Emma Goldman’s reaction to that experience was recorded in her two books, My Disillusionment in Russia and in My Further Disillusionment in Russia. By the time of her departure from Russia she had become highly critical of Lenin and his regime. She knew that power corrupts anarchists and communists, just as it corrupted their opponents. Her outlook on social revolution had been refined as a result of her experiences. No longer did she look upon the violent destruction of an existing regime and the social revolution as synonymous. The failure of the Russian Revolution was that it took superficial political changes (the replacement of the Czar by Lenin) for an indication of systemic change. Nothing could have been further from the truth. As Emma Goldman wrote,

[In] its mad passion for power, the Communist State even sought to strengthen and deepen the very ideas and conceptions which the Revolution had come to destroy. … With the concept that the Revolution was only a means of securing political power, it was inevitable that all revolutionary values should be subordinated to the needs of the Socialist State; indeed exploited to further the security of the newly acquired governmental power.

The perversion of the revolution was crystallized for Emma Goldman by the “all-dominating slogan” of the Communist Party: “THE END JUSTIFIES ALL MEANS.” In a brilliant analysis of means and ends, Goldman asserted that,

There is no greater fallacy than the belief that aims and purposes are one thing, while methods and tactics are another. This conception is a potent menace to social regeneration. All human experience teaches that means cannot be separated from the ultimate aims. The means employed become, through individual habit and social practice, part and parcel of the final purpose; they modify it, and presently the aims and means, become identical. From the day of my arrival in Russia I felt it, at first vaguely, then ever more consciously and clearly. … The whole history of man is continuous proof of the maxim that to divest one’s methods of ethical concepts means to sink into the depths of utter demoralization. In that lies the tragedy of the Bolshevik philosophy as applied to the Russian Revolution.

One of her final comments on her Russian experience was summed up in 1936, at the time of the Stalinist purges, when she claimed that the anarchist criticism of Russia had been vindicated. “Our position,” she wrote, “as regards power and dictatorship has been strengthened by the events in Russia.” All the people being purged began their lives with an ideal for which they suffered prison and exile. “No sooner did they ascend to power than their past was wiped out and they became as savage in their persecution of their opponents as the enemies they came to destroy.” She concluded, “For nothing so corrupts and disintegrates as power itself.” The whole essence of the question about Russia was for her the fact that “you cannot educate men for liberty by making them slaves,” and this is what the Bolsheviks had tried to do.

During the mid-1930’s Emma Goldman was concerned not only with the direction of events in Stalinist Russia but also with the direction taken by the anarchist movement in Spain. She was to some extent intimately connected with the events in Spain, because of her contacts in the international anarchist movement, as well as her two visits to Spain during the Civil War. Evidence of her concern is found in her correspondence and published articles, particularly in her discussion of “anarchists and elections”. In an article by this title appearing in the June-July 1936 Vanguard, she proposed and answered the following questions:

1. [The] question as to whether the abstention from participation in elections is for Anarchists a matter of principle? I certainly think it is, and should be for all anarchists.
2. … [It] is but logical for Anarchists not to consider political participation as a “simple question of tactics.” Such tactics are not only incompatible with Anarchist thought and principles, but they also injure the stand of Anarchism as the one and only true revolutionary philosophy.
3. Can Anarchists, without scruple, and in the face of certain circumstances exercise power during a transition period? … I cannot understand how they can possibly aspire to power.

For Emma Goldman, it was “not the abuse of power” which corrupted everybody, but rather “the thing itself, namely power which is evil and which takes the very spirit and revolutionary fighting strength out of everybody who wields it.” Collaboration and cooperation in elections and with the Communists (as the anarchists were doing in Spain) did not meet with her approval.

I cannot agree with the suggestion that anarchists should in grave times co-operate with communists in elections. … I myself consider it not only inconsistent with our views of vesting power to politicians by means of voting for them. I also consider it highly dangerous. We insist, do we not, … that the means must harmonize as far as possible with the end. And our end being anarchism, I do not see how we can very well unite with any political party. … (With our past experience with socialists and communists, it seems folly to join them. But more important is my firm belief that we would be spitting ourselves in the face, if we approved participation in elections. Fighting ALL POWER AND ALL GOVERNMENT AS WE DO, how can we help by putting anyone into positions of power? … WE SIMPLY CANNOT AND SHOULD NOT MAKE THE PLUNGE. … We can only state our own position towards the fundamentals of anarchism. And that has always been opposition to the slick political machine that has ever corrupted the best of people or has paralyzed their efforts.

Anarchists and the Spanish Civil War (1936-1939)

Though Emma Goldman aided the Spanish anarchist movement during the Spanish Civil War, as her statements make clear, she disagreed with their participation in the Republican government. However, she stood behind them because they were fighting with their backs to the wall against the whole world. Their struggle was her second chance to see the revolution at last. She was in Spain from September 1936 until January 1937, at which time she went to London to help publicize the republican cause. She was continually embroiled in disputes over anarchist principles and their collaboration in Spain. Her appointment as a collector of relief funds for the Catalan government somehow seemed to show her complicity, however much she denied it. She was sickened by the farcical comedy of anarchist leaders defending government property, which occurred in the aftermath of the May crisis in Barcelona. She agreed with her former companion in Russia, Alexander Shapiro, who complained that “Anarchists in government will and ‘must’ act like all government officials and ministers.”

The important point about the Spanish Civil War is that for the first and only time in modern political history there were anarchist ministers serving in both provincial and federal cabinets. Nothing like this had ever transpired in anarchist history. The Spanish anarchists had caused a terrible breach among both their international comrades and their principles. It is important to understand what motivated the Spaniards into holding office and participating in governments, and what, if any lessons, are to be learned from their experiences.

The anarchist tradition in Spain has a long and rich history, mostly embroidered with violence and terrorism. By the first two decades of the 20th Century, the anarchist presence in Spain was a significant element, particularly among the working classes and their syndical trade unions. The CNT (Confederacion Nacional del Trabajo or National Confederation of Labor) had been founded in 1910 and was a national trade union. The influence of the anarchists saved it on various occasions from falling into the hands of other political organizations. In 1927, the anarchists founded their own trade union, the FAI (Federacion Anarquista Iberica or Anarchist Federation of Iberia) in an effort to radicalize their own movement. It was hoped that the FAI would act as a “radical” watchdog to correct the deviationist tendencies present within the CNT.

The CNT and FAI shunned parliamentary activity and in contrast to other labor parties, held no seats in the central or local government and refrained from nominating candidates for parliament. They followed a syndicalist line, believing that direct action and strikes were necessary to accomplish the social revolution. The FAI, the more radical organization of the two, made no distinction between governments of the right or the left, just as they made no distinction between individual politicians. For them, all politicians were equally bad.

Post-World War I Spain had suffered a series of military coups and rebellions and experienced continual struggle against the monarchy. In December 1931, a new constitution was adopted after the dissolution of the royal throne. The Republican government of Azana was hard pressed by discontent, especially in the autonomous province of Catalan, which was granted home rule in late 1932. In early 1933, there was a large uprising in Barcelona, sparked by anarchist and syndicalist unrest with the progress of social reform. In November of that year the first regular elections for the Cortes were held.

The anarcho-syndicalists generally took a hard line, abstentionist approach to this election. Both the CNT and FAI had urged their members not to vote. Tierra y Libertad (Land and Liberty) declared a month before the elections in November: “Our revolution is not made in Parliament, but in the streets.” “We are not interested in changing governments,” Isaac Puente, an influential anarcho- syndicalist, had written at the same time: “What we want is to suppress them. … Whatever side wins, whether the right or the left will be our enemy, … and will have at its disposal the truncheons of the assault guards.” A few days before the election, Tierra y Libertad editorialized:

Workers! Do not vote! The vote is a negation of your personality. Turn your backs on those who ask you to vote for them. They are your enemies. … As far as we are concerned they are all the same; all politicians are our enemies whether they be Republicans, monarchists, Communists, or Socialists. … Parliament … is a filthy house of prostitution toying with the interests of the country and the people.

The November 1933 election for the Cortes resulted in giving the Parties of the Right 44% of the seats. Throughout 1934 and 1935, social and political unrest continued to plague Spain. Catalan sovereignty was proclaimed and its independence suppressed by military efforts. Finally in January 1936, the Cortes was dissolved and new elections were called for February. These elections were lukewarmly endorsed by many Spanish anarchists, after the Popular Front coalition promised to free all political prisoners. It was largely the support of the anarchists and syndicalists which enabled the Popular Front to come to power. This combination of Republicans, Socialists, Syndicalists, Communists and anarchists won a decisive victory over their political opponents.

The new Popular Front government which took power proclaimed an amnesty as it had promised, but soon faced the Civil War, which broke out on July 18, 1936, as the result of a rebellion by military chiefs in Morocco. The Popular Front government held its own in Madrid and Barcelona but the nationalist forces made advances in other parts of the country. Catalan, which had already previously regained autonomous status, immediately sought anarchist participation in the existing provincial government, the Generalitat.

The CNT had its largest following in Catalan and it was logical that the existing provincial government would want to take advantage of its presence. Luis Companys, President of the Generalitat, summoned representatives of the CNT-FAI to his office as soon as the uprising had been defeated (July 20, 1936) in order to obtain anarchist and syndicalist legitimization of his rule. Garcia Oliver and Diego Abad de Santillan became ministers in the government of the Catalan Generalitat. Santillan saw no other choice than for anarchists to share the administrative power with the Companys government in Catalan. Paralysis of the federal government in Madrid and continued advances by the nationalist forces threatened to envelop Spain in fascism. It was up to the anarchists to transform the militia committee of Catalan into a truly revolutionary body. Regarding his experience as a minister in the Catalan government, Santillan, in 1938, wrote: “Simply as governors we [the anarchists] were no better than anyone else, and we have already proved that our intervention in governments served only to reinforce governmentalism.”

Meanwhile, the rebel, nationalist forces had made further advances into Republican Spain and on September 4, 1936, the Popular Front formed a new government under the leadership of Largo Caballero, a former socialist minister. If the Caballero government was to be more than a government in name, it would have to “assume control of all the elements of state power. … The work of reconstructing state power could not be achieved or at least would be extremely difficult to achieve without the participation in the government of the extreme wing of the libertarian movement, …” This part of the movement was represented by the anarchist oriented CNT and FAI.

Although views differed, most of Caballero’s colleagues advised his seeking the participation of the libertarians in the government. The advantages of having them share the responsibility for its measures would be indubitable. “The entry of representatives of the CNT into the present Council of Ministers would certainly endow the directive organ of the nation with fresh energy and authority,” wrote Claridad, one of Largo Caballero’s journals on October 25, 1936, especially “in view of the fact that a considerable segment of the working class, now absent from its deliberations, would feel bound by its measures and authority.” What Caballero’s advisers could not guess was whether or not the anarcho-syndicalists would wish to become ministers in the government and share in the reconstruction of the State. This was questionable even though quite recently they had violated their principles by joining the Catalan regional government. Furthermore, Largo Caballero had tried, when forming his cabinet in September 1936, to secure the participation of the anarcho-syndicalists by offering them a single ministerial seat without portfolio. Burnett Bolloten has noted that, Caballero “needed their participation in the belief that they would feel themselves bound by his government measures and authority.” However at that time, they rejected his offer based on their traditional anti-governmental stand and their personal distrust. (Caballero had been responsible for persecution of anarchists, earlier in his political career.)

The CNT had not been ready to enter the Madrid government in September but in October 1936 a plenary session of the regional federations of the CNT was held for the purpose of discussing the matter further. The result was that the CNT authorized its representatives to “conduct negotiations for bringing the CNT into the government.” The CNT justified its position by stating: “… in order to win the war and to save our people and the world, it is ready to collaborate with any one in a directive organ, whether this organ be called a council or a government.” In their negotiations with Caballero, the CNT representatives asked for five ministries including war and finance, but he rejected their demand. Finally, on November 3, (1936), they accepted four: justice, industry, commerce, and health, none of which, however, was vital. Furthermore, the portfolios of industry and commerce had previously been held by one minister. The four CNT members named to the government were: Juan Garcia Oliver (justice), Juan Lopez (commerce), Federica Montseny (health and public assistance), and Juan Peiro (industry).

As we have seen, Caballero was partly motivated by his desire to invest his government with greater authority. President Azana, who had to sign the decrees appointing the anarchist ministers, was hesitant to do so. Caballero claimed that Azana did not see the significance of getting the anarchists into office. “From terrorism and direct action, it [Spanish anarchism] had moved to collaboration and to sharing the responsibilities of power. … It was a unique event in the world and would not be sterile. I [Caballero] told him [Azana] that if he did not sign the decrees, I would resign.”

The Communists also had a similar, ulterior motive in drawing the anarchists into the government. They hoped to bolster their own power. The Communists were concerned with world opinion, particularly in France, Britain, and America. They wished to give an appearance of legality to the Spanish Republic. Thus they hoped that the participation of the anarcho-syndicalists in the government would placate foreign opinion and enhance their prospects of receiving military assistance from these Western powers. Furthermore, after the war, it was revealed that the Communists hoped to create a breach in the ranks of the anarchists and syndicalists by drawing the CNT into government collaboration.

In fact, there was a discord in the ranks of the anarchists and syndicalists because nearly everyone was unhappy with what they recognized to be a compromise. Their justification was simply that if the anarchists did not take a role in the Republican government, a dictatorship worse than Russia would result and that trip prospects of a fascist regime were more unacceptable to them than the act of collaboration with the existing government.

Reluctant criticism, both within Spain and outside Spain, was immediately forthcoming from anarchists. Emma Goldman, who had argued with Federica Montseny for hours against collaboration, “believed that the anarchists had abandoned political principle to save Spain from further foreign intervention. Such a course was not surprising in the context of Spanish history, but the real tragedy of the anarchists was that they were pulled further and further into the mire of compromise.” The December 1936 Vanguard carried remarks on the Spanish situation, translated from a French anarchist journal. The author, Luigi Bertoni, wrote, partly in justification and partly in recognition of the anarchists departure from principle.

The present Spanish government does, indeed, differ considerably from any ordinary government; that is especially evident from the hostility shown towards it on the part of governments all over the world. But it is still essentially and practically a government, and must therefore contain to a considerable extent the faults inherent in it. Thus it is not without apprehension that I view the discharging of ministerial functions on the part of our four comrades, despite the complete confidence we have in them. … Rather than ‘governmental anarchists’, I should call them ‘revolutionary anarchists’.

Another outspoken critic of anarchist collaboration was Camillo Berneri, an Italian anarchist living in Barcelona. Robert Kern, a historian of this era, has noted that beginning October 1936, Berneri wrote “vitriolic articles in his Guerra Di Classes demanding, among other things, development of an international revolutionary campaign as the prime defense of the republic. He also attacked the mood of anarchist collaboration. Difficulties in Aragon did not necessitate a total capitulation to the Communists. Membership in the Popular Front cabinet, far from solving anything, would only put anarchists under extreme coercion to maintain unanimity in Madrid. All differences of ideology would eventually be extinguished and Stalinist statism imposed – a tragic end to a long anarchist tradition.” Before Berneri was assassinated in 1937 (for his anticommunist attacks), he wrote an “Open Letter to Federica Montseny” in which he claimed that the acceptance of the ministerial posts had no direct bearing on the war effort or upon the problems that the anarchists hoped to solve by joining the cabinet. In his open letter Berneri asked, “The hour has come to enquire whether the Anarchists are in the Government for the purpose of being the vestals to serve as a Phrygian Cap for some of the politicians flirting with the enemy or with the forces anxious to restore ‘The Republic of all Classes’.”

Federica Montseny, one of the four who had accepted ministerial positions in the Madrid government of Caballero, was one of their most outspoken defenders. She and her family represented several generations of radical anarchist activism in Spain.

Federica was born in 1905, the daughter of Federico Urales, who was one of the most well-respected anarchist theoreticians and journalists in Spain during the first two decades of the century. In the early 1920’s, she and her father renewed publication of a famous anarchist journal, La Revista Blanca. Federica was editor of the journal and an author of many novels. By the Fall of 1936, she was one of the most popular anarchist leaders and theoreticians in Spain. At the age of 31, she accepted the ministerial post for health and public assistance, becoming the first woman ever to hold a ministerial office in a Spanish national government.

There is little doubt that Montseny was a purist, at least in principle. In a 1934 article in La Revista Blanca, she wrote that all governments are evil: “It became obvious that no theory justified the existence of any state. Be it socialist, communistic, democratic, or fascistic, they were all the same – they were states. Each kind of state possessed the same purpose: the promotion of friends, the suppression of the workers by keeping them submissive, and the exploitation of the many by the few.” A state in all places and at all times represented “oppression and the annihilation of man. … [A state was] incarnated in armed organisms which sustain through the method of terror and force, the Power which dominates, robs, and which kills.”

As her biographer adds, “Montseny insisted” that her view of the State applied not only to traditional governments, but to revolutionary ones as well. So it is clear that Montseny understood that ALL governments were evil even though she became a minister in one.

The underlying justification for her action was that she saw the Nationalists as a greater threat to anarchist ideals than any liberal republican government. She felt it foolish to allow oneself to be drowned by the tide of fascism. The retrograde nature of fascism demanded a new approach. Anarchists were among the first to realize that the struggle against fascism was of utmost importance. In a 1937 talk, she said, “We think [by cooperating with Caballero] we will avoid a repetition of the fate of the anarchist movements in other countries where Communists assumed direction of the revolution.”

It was not without trepidation that she entered the government in November 1936. In a speech she made in France in 1945, she reportedly said of her doubts about becoming a governmental minister: “I asked for twenty-four hours to think over the matter. I consulted my father who, thoughtfully, said, ‘You know what this means. In fact it is the liquidation of anarchism and of the CNT. Once in power you will not rid yourselves of power.’ …” After she resigned from the cabinet in mid-1937, she declared: “As a daughter of veteran anarchists, … I regarded my entry into the government, my acceptance of the post to which the CNT had assigned me, as having more significance than the mere appointment of a minister. … What inhibitions, what doubts, what anguish I had personally to overcome in order to accept the post! … [For] me it implied a break with my life’s work, with a whole past linked to the ideals of my parents. It meant a tremendous effort, an effort made at the cost of many tears.” She also noted that the complicity of anarchists in government would, as she put it, “ruin many of us morally.” Its safe to conclude that ultimately she regretted her departure from principle and her involvement in the government. She had not accomplished anything lasting by her efforts.

The Caballero government managed to sustain itself in power until May 1937, at which time it was succeeded by that of Negrin which excluded the anarcho-syndicalists from participation. The four anarchist ministers had done little to strengthen the position of the anarchist movement during their time in office and had irreparably injured anarchist ideas. This realization burst upon the libertarian movement in 1938, as Franco came nearer and nearer to total victory.

During the last two weeks of October 1938, national plenary meetings of the regional federations of the libertarian movement were held in Barcelona. Three major divisions of opinion were to be found among those present. A majority held that the libertarian movement should participate in politics, as they had already done. Two minority views existed: 1) that the FAI should be converted into a political party of the CNT and attempt to represent the libertarian movement in the government once again, and 2) the view, represented rather feebly by the Young Libertarians of Catalan, “that all participation in government should be renounced.” During one of the sessions of the Young Libertarians, their views came across rather picturesquely. “To try to join the State in order to destroy it is like taking your wives and sisters to brothels in order to abolish prostitution.”

The result of the plenary meetings were resolutions in favor of political participation. One resolution read: “Our direct participation in the administrative bodies of political, economic, and military life … was motivated by our high sense of responsibility and the need for co-operation in the fight against fascism … in order to facilitate a victory. … [This participation] has not been a correction of our tactics but rather an intelligent addition to our methods in accord with the circumstances and in response to an abnormal situation in the life of the people.” However, in an effort to purify their intentions, another resolution read: “The Libertarian Movement, having taken part in politics in violation of its tradition, declares: the political Power, the State, will always be the antithesis of Anarchism, and [our] circumstancial participation in Power has been … for the purpose of opposing to the greatest possible extent, from a position in Power and from everywhere else, the strangulation of the revolution.”

Many historians agree that the collaboration of the CNT and FAI in the republican government failed to improve the military situation during the their time in power. Vernon Richards, another historian of this era, concluded that “it certainly added prestige to the Government.” In his opinion, there is little question that the anarchists were “out-witted and outmaneuvered by the politicians on every issue. Equally significant is that their contact with politicians had no ideological influence on the politicians whereas a number of leading members of the CNT were in the end won over to the very principles of government and centralize authority, …” They became victims of the false belief that “power was only evil when in the ‘wrong hands’, and for a ‘wrong cause’, and not that ‘power tends to corrupt and absolute power corrupts absolutely’, …”

If we had measured the number of anarchists in Spain by their refusal to collaborate in electoral politics, then we would probably have found very few of them there. Moreover, it seems that few of them understood the implications of their philosophy, which was not only anti-electoral but anti-war. One of the most basic contradictions faced by the Spanish anarchists was the fact, as John Brademas put it, that they “sought to make war and social revolution at the same time.” This was impossible in theory and contradictory in practice. The choice between fighting the forces of Franco, on the one hand, and fighting for the revolution, on the other hand, seemed to be answered by violence, no matter which way they turned. Before the Civil War broke out, there had been interest (by some Spanish anarchists) in the ideas of the French anarchist, Sebastien Faure, who was strongly anti-nationalist and anti-militaristic. Faure’s non-violence … attracted Spaniards fighting a military dictatorship. Faure believed that organizing masses of everyday people into a Gandhi-like campaign of public non-violence would render military power useless.” However, Faure’s ideas were not followed up and here lies at least part of the real tragedy of Spanish anarchism.

The Spaniards did not see the incongruity of trying to wage war on the basis of anarchist principles. War and anarchism are simply repugnant; one is destruction and extermination, and the other is mutualistic voluntaryism. The anarcho-militias, manned by anarchists during the Civil War, were full of problems, for the simple reason that the individual anarchist soldier refused to recognize any authority. He took a dim outlook on rank, military titles, and regimentation. As one anarchist commentator on the Civil War noted, “War has always been a tomb, never a means of revolution.”

The ultimate problem of violence and social revolution facing the Spanish anarchists was that an anarchist society could not be established and maintained on the basis of coercion. Recourse to violence was always an indication of weakness not strength. The revolution with the greatest possibility of success would be the one which was brought about peacefully. Only then would there be any valid sign of unanimity among the population on the objectives of the revolution.

One of the chief justifications of the Spanish anarchist participation in government and war was that they were choosing the lesser of two evils. During the events leading up to the elections of February 1936, Diego Abad de Santillan observed this very thing, that:

“participation in the elections was advisable. We gave power to the leftists, convinced that under the circumstances they were the lesser evil.”

In an astute analysis of this justification, Murray Bookchin observed:

This could be construed as a reasonable and honest statement if action based on the “lesser evil” was seen for what it really was – a distinct departure from principle, openly admitted to be such, a bitter pill to be swallowed to deal with an acute illness. … But after this has been said, one must emphasize that it would have been preposterous to expect a “lesser evil” to behave with a noble virtue. … The best the CNT and FAI could have hoped for from the newly elected state would have been neutrality; to base one iota of their policy on active state support was not only absurd, but marked the initial steps toward the “politicalization” of the Spanish anarchist movement and its eventual conversion into a political party. … The Anarchists … were slowly becoming clients of the creature they most professed to oppose: the state power itself. … Having taken to the vote, they began to take to politics.

Concluding Remarks

This review of the European anarchist tradition has offered many reasons for the rejection of electoral participation and political power by voluntaryists today. Malatesta was the best spokesman for the non-electoral anarchists, having defended that position against Merlino, as early as 1897. Malatesta saw not only the dangers of electoral politics, but he foresaw the dangers of war and revolutionary violence years before they developed in Spain. In 1930, regarding anarchism and revolutions, he wrote:

I incline to the view that the complete triumph of anarchy will come by evolution, gradually rather than by violent revolution. … In any case, if we take into account our sparse numbers and the prevalent attitudes among the masses, and if we do not wish to confuse our wishes with the reality, we must expect that the next revolution will not be an anarchist one, and therefore what is more pressing, is to think of what we can and must do in a revolution in which we will be a relatively small and badly armed minority. … But we must, however, beware of ourselves becoming less anarchist because the masses are not ready for anarchy. If they want a government, it is unlikely that we will be able to prevent a new government being formed, but this is no reason for our not trying to persuade people that government is useless and harmful or of preventing the government from also imposing on us and others like us who don’t want it. … If we are unable to prevent the constitution of a new government, if we are unable to destroy it immediately, we should in either case refuse to support it in any shape or form. Disobedience on principle, resistance to the bitter end against every imposition by the authorities, and an absolute refusal to accept any position of command. … In this way we shall not achieve anarchy, which cannot be imposed against the wishes of the people, but at least we shall be preparing the way for it.

And again in 1932, he wrote:

The primary concern of every government is to ensure its continuance in power, irrespective of the men who form it. If they are bad, they want to remain in power in order to enrich themselves and to satisfy their lust for authority; and if they are honest and sincere they believe that it is their duty to remain in power for the people. … The anarchists … could never, even if they were strong enough, form a government without contradicting themselves and repudiating their entire doctrine; and, should they do so, it would be no different from any other government; perhaps it would even be worse.

Wherever and whenever anarchists have engaged in war and/or electoral politics they have inevitably failed both militarily and politically. One cannot remain an anarchist and take part in war or government. By compromising one’s anarchism this way, one does not make failure less certain; only more humiliating. That is the lesson of anarchist history.


SHORT BIBLIOGRAPHY

Introduction:
Carl Watner, Voluntaryism in the Libertarian Tradition, Baltimore: The Voluntaryists, 1982.
Carl Watner, A Voluntaryist Bibliography: Annotated, Baltimore: The Voluntaryists, 1982.Proudhon:
George Woodcock, Anarchism: A History of Libertarian Ideas and Movements, Cleveland: Meridan Books,1970.
George Woodcock, Pierre-Joseph Proudhon: His Life and Work, New York: Schocken Books, 1972.

Syndicalism:
Louis Levine, Syndicalism in France, New York: Columbia University Press, 1914.
Lewis Lorwin, “Syndicalism,” in Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences, Vol. 13, New York: The Macmillan Company, 1959.
J. Ramsay MacDonald, Syndicalism: A Critical Examination, London: Constable & Co., 1913.
David Stafford, From Anarchism to Reformism: A Study of the Political Activities of Paul Brousse With the First International and the French Socialist Movement 1870-1890. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1971.

The Italian Debate:
Luigi Galleani, The End of Anarchism?, Orkney: Cienfuegos Press, 1982.
Richard Hostetter, The Italian Socialist Movement, Princeton: D. Van Nostrand Co., 1958.
Errico Malatesta and Francesco Saverio Merlino, “Anarchismo e Democracia,” in Collana “La Rivolta” No. 27, Ragusa, November, 1974.
David Roberts, The Syndicalist Tradition and Italian Fascism, Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1979.

Anarchists and the Russian Revolution:
Paul Avrich, The Russian – Anarchists, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1967.
Emma Goldman, Living My Life, Garden City: Garden City Publishing Co., one volume edition, 1934.

Emma Goldman: On Revolution and Elections:
Richard and Anna Marie Drinnon, Nowhere at Home, Letters from Exile of Emma Goldman and Alexander Berkman, New York: Schocken Books, 1975.
Emma Goldman, MY Further Disillusionment in Russia, Garden City: Doubleday, Page & Co., 1924.
Emma Goldman, “Anarchists and Elections, Vanguard, June-July 1936, pp. 19-20.
Emma Goldman, “The Soviet Executions,” Vanguard, Oct.-Nov. 1936, p. 10.

Anarchists and the Spanish Civil War (1936-1939):
Camillo Berneri, “An Open Letter to Federica Montseny,” Spain and the World, June 1937, pp. 1-4.
L. Bertoni from “Le Reveil Anarchists,” Nov. 28, reprinted in Vanguard, Dec. 1936, p. 12.
Burnett Bolloten, The Spanish Civil War: The Left and the Struggle for Power During the Civil War, Chapel Hill: The University of North Carolina Press, 1979.
Murray Bookchin, The Spanish Anarchists: The Heroic Years 1868-1936, New York: Free Life Editions, 1977.
John Brademas, “A Note on the Anarcho-Syndicalists and the Spanish Civil War,” II Occidente No. 2 (Torino) 1955, p. 128.
Shirley Fredericks, “Social and Political Thought of Federica Montseny, Spanish Anarchist 1923-1937,” PhD. dissertation, May 1972, University of New Mexico.
Robert Kern, Red Years / Black Years, A Political History of Spanish Anarchism 1911-1937, Philadelphia: Institute for the Study of Human issues, 1978.
Robert Kern,”Anarchist Principles and Spanish Reality: Emma Goldman as a Participant in the Civil War 1936-1939,” 11 Journal of Contemporary History (1976) pp. 237-259.
Jose Peirats, Anarchists in the Spanish Revolution, Toronto: Solidarity Books, 1974?.
Vernon Richards, Lessons of the Spanish Revolution, London: Freedom Press, 1972.

Concluding Remarks:
Marcus Graham, “Behind the Lines in Spain,” Man, Oct.-Nov. 1936, p. 2.
Vernon Richards (Ed.), Errico Malatesta: His Life and Ideas, London: Freedom Press,1965.

A Voluntaryist Bibliography, The Short List


Prepared by Carl Watner, July 2009
(With suggestions by subscribers)

 

I. Books that helped me evolve into a voluntaryist

  • Ayn Rand, ATLAS SHRUGGED
  • Ayn Rand, FOR THE NEW INTELLECTUAL
  • Leonard Read, GOVERNMENT – AN IDEAL CONCEPT
  • Murray Rothbard, MAN, ECONOMY, AND STATE
  • Lysander Spooner, NO TREASON, NO. 6
  • William Graham Sumner, THE FORGOTTEN MAN, THE CHALLENGE OF FACTS, WAR, EARTH-HUNGER AND OTHER ESSAYS (4 vols.)
  • Morris and Linda Tannehill, THE MARKET FOR LIBERTY
  • Ludwig von Mises, HUMAN ACTION
  • William Wooldridge, UNCLE SAM, THE MONOPOLY MAN

II. Other books that I would recommend to those interested in voluntaryism

  • Bruce Benson, THE ENTERPRISE OF LAW: Justice Without the State
  • Etienne de La Boetie, THE POLITICS OF OBEDIENCE
  • Robert LeFevre, THE FUNDAMENTALS OF LIBERTY
  • Albert Jay Nock, OUR ENEMY, THE STATE
  • Jim Payne, PRINCESS NAVINA VISITS VOLUNTARIA
  • Robert Ringer, RESTORING THE AMERICAN DREAM
  • Murray Rothbard, FOR A NEW LIBERTY
  • Mary Ruwart, HEALING OUR WORLD IN AN AGE OF AGGRESSION
  • Lysander Spooner, THE LYSANDER SPOONER READER
  • Henry David Thoreau, “Civil Disobedience”
  • Benjamin Tucker, INSTEAD OF A BOOK
  • Carl Watner, I MUST SPEAK OUT

III. Economics for those interested in voluntaryism

  • Walter Block, DEFENDING THE UNDEFENDABLE
  • Elgin Groseclose, MONEY AND MAN
  • Henry Hazlitt, ECONOMICS IN ONE LESSON
  • Murray Rothbard, POWER AND MARKET
  • Murray Rothbard, THE CASE FOR A 100 PER CENT GOLD DOLLAR
  • Murray Rothbard, WHAT HAS GOVERNMENT DONE TO OUR MONEY?

IV. Reading Lists

  • www.mises.org/story/1830: David Gordon, “The Meaning and History of Liberty: An In-Print Bibliography”
  • www.tolfa.us/read.htm: Jim Davies, The On Line Freedom Academy
  • “The Literature of Liberty,” by Tom G. Palmer in David Boaz (ed.), THE LIBERTARIAN READER (1997), pp. 415-453.

V. Suggestions added by subscribers since June 2012

  • Mark Kurlansky, NONVIOLENCE
  • Michael Huemer, THE PROBLEM OF POLITICAL AUTHORITY
  • Ayn Rand, THE VIRTUE OF SELFISHNESS
  • Larken Rose, THE MOST DANGEROUS SUPERSTITION
  • Butler Shaffer, BOUNDARIES OF ORDER
  • Gene Sharp, THE POLITICS OF NONVIOLENT ACTION
  • Marc Stevens, ADVENTURES IN LEGAL LAND
  • Carl Watner, RENDER NOT: THE CASE AGAINST TAXATION

 

A Voluntaryist Bibliography, Annotated (1982)


by Carl Watner

General Introduction And Purpose Of This Bibliography

 

 

The Voluntaryists are a newly formed group of libertarians who have organized to promote non-political strategies to achieve a free society. We have chosen to label ourselves Voluntaryists because the term “libertarian” has become too closely associated with the Libertarian Party. We believe that all efforts to elect libertarians to political office conflict with libertarian principles and that such efforts are strategically unsound. Engaging in political action, running candidates for office, and encouraging people to vote must inevitably sabotage the Voluntaryist goal of delegitimizing the State. The only long-range and lasting way to curtail State power is to dissolve the illusion of legitimacy which all States must have in order to sustain themselves. Libertarians must come to act consistently with the Voluntaryist insight: that all State power ultimately depends on the sanction and cooperation of its victims.

The Voluntaryist Insight

The Voluntaryist insight, that all State power is grounded on general popular acceptance, was first formulated by Etienne de la Boetie (1530-1563). In his Discourse on Voluntary Servitude, which was probably written during the 1550’s, la Boetie discussed one of the most critical problems of political philosophy; namely, the question of civil obedience. “Why in the world do people consent to their own enslavement?” he asked. “Why do the bulk of the people acquiesce in their own subjection?” La Boetie answered these questions by explaining the governmental mystique created by the rulers and their intellectual apologists. By relying on custom, by providing both bread and circuses to the citizenry, and by creating a vast network of governmental supporters dependent on political plunder, governments were able to engineer and sustain their own popular acceptance among the populace.

La Boetie was also the first political philosopher to move from an emphasis on the importance of consent to the strategic question of toppling tyranny by leading the public to withdraw their consent. He saw that violence was not necessary:

“Obviously there is no need of fighting to overcome the tyrant, for he is automatically defeated if the country refuses to consent to its own enslavement: it is not necessary to deprive him of anything, but simply to give him nothing; … is therefore the inhabitants themselves who permit, or, rather, bring about, their own subjection, since by ceasing to submit, they would put an end to their servitude”(p. 50). Realizing the great value of natural liberty, la Boetie called for a thorough process of educating the public to the truth, a process which would give back to the people a knowledge of the the myths and illusions fostered by the State. The primary task of the opponents of State power is therefore an educational one: to alert the public to their despotic condition and then to demystify and desanctify the entire State apparatus.

There are two English language editions of la Boetie’s essay readily available. The best, and the one quoted from above, was prepared by Free Life Editions of New York in 1975 with the title of The Politics of Obedience: The Discourse of Voluntary Servitude. (See rear of this pamphlet for ordering instructions.) Despite his advocacy of libertarian political activity, Murray Rothbard’s introduction for this edition, “The Political Thought of Etienne de la Boetie”, gives a great deal of support to the ‘Voluntaryist critique of political action. Political activity not only unnecessarily reinforces the image of State legitimacy, which, as la Boetie points out, we must destroy, but it is also unlikely to end State power. La Boetie’s analysis implies that educational activities and non-violent resistance to the State (such as occurred in India during the Gandhian campaigns against the British) are sufficient to topple States. The other edition of The Discourse was prepared by William Flygare and is accompanied by a preface from James Martin. It is titled The Will to Bondage (Colorado Springs: Ralph Myles Publisher, 1974). Included is the original French version of the essay, along side the first English translation, which was prepared in 1735. The Free Life edition carries a 1942 translation, so it is worthwhile to compare the two.

There is not, a great deal of secondary material concerning la Boetie and his Discourse in English. The two best general discussions have been prepared by Nannerl O. Keohane and James Brown Scott. Scott includes a chapter entitled “Le Contr ‘Un de la Boetie – Tyrannicide through the Ages” in his The Catholic Conception of International Law (Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press, 1934). La Boetie’s essay is treated as part of the historical tradition of tyrannicide. Scott refers to it as “a literary exercise in behalf of liberty in which he [la Boetie] condemns tyranny in any and all of its forms as ruinous alike to the tyrant, the state, and the people” (p.299). He aptly summarizes la Boetie’s position: “He does not require of the people that they shall violently overthrow the tyrant, but merely that they shall cease to support him, whereupon he will fall of his own dead weight” (p.302). Keohane’s discussion of la Boetie originally appeared as “The Radical Humanism of Etienne de la Boetie” (38 Journal of the History of Ideas, Jan. – March, 1977, pp. 119-130) and then was condensed for his book, Philosophy and the State in France: The Renaissance to the Enlightenment (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1980) as “On Voluntary Servitude: La Boetie” (pp. 92-98). Keohane places la Boetie in the historical perspective of 16th Century France by pointing out that la Boetie was both a lawyer and member of parliament. Despite his place in the State apparatus, Keohane regards la Boetie’s premises as basically anarchistic, because they lead to the conclusion that no man or group of men should have authority over other individuals.

In his newly published The Ethics of Liberty (Atlantic Highlands: Humanities Press, 1982), Murray Rothbard devotes some space to the Voluntaryist insight in his chapter on “The Nature of the State”. The latter half of this chapter deals explicitly with la Boetie and generally discusses the significance of State legitimacy. Rothbard shows how the State has historically aligned itself with the Church, and that when this became no longer possible,how the State assumed control over public education. The State is thus able to “mould the minds of its subjects” from kindergarten to graduate school in order to foster this voluntary servitude. In a footnote Rothbard cites two other disparate thinkers who have understood the importance of majority consent to governmental tyranny. He quotes from David Hume’s essay “On the First Principles of Government” (see any edition of David Hume, Essays, Literary, Moral and Political). Hume, who was no libertarian wrote: “Nothing appears more surprising … than the easiness with which the many are governed by the few, and the implicit submission with which men resign their own sentiments … to those of their rulers. … [W]e shall find that, as ‘force’ is always on the side of the governed, the governors have nothing to support them but opinion. It is, therefore, on opinion only that government is founded; Rothbard also cites Ludwig von Mises, Human Action (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1949, p. 188ff).

Voluntaryism From A Historical Perspective

The Voluntaryist insight and the general non-political approach to social change which it suggests has a long standing place in the libertarian tradition. For a general discussion see Voluntaryism in the Libertarian Tradition (Baltimore: The Voluntaryist, 1982) by Carl Watner. (See reverse of this pamphlet for ordering instructions.) Any late 19th Century encyclopedia should have an entry under “Voluntaryism”, since the term originated back in the early 1820’s when it was used in the religious disputes between established churchmen in England and the dissenters. Typical of such articles is the one found in Chambers’ Encyclopedia at volume 10, page 23 (Philadelphia: J. P. Lippincott and Co., 1882). During the 1830’s and until the 1850’s, the term Voluntaryism was applied to the advocates of private schools in England. These voluntary educationists saw a religious threat in State controlled education and many believed that the law of supply, and demand, or the voluntary principle, as they termed it, would provide for the education of the whole English people. Edward Miall, a well known publisher and dissenter wrote a book, entitled Views of the Voluntary Principle (London: Aylott and Jones, 1845) which characterized the meaning of Voluntaryism for mid-19th Century England.

Auberon Herbert attempted to repopularize the term Voluntaryism during the 1880’s and 1890’s in his voluntaryist journal Free Life. Herbert was a supporter of voluntary taxation and one of the last projects of his life was the preparation and publication of “A Plea for Voluntaryism” which appeared in The Voluntaryist Creed (Oxford, 1908). Both the “Plea” and “The Principles of Voluntaryism and Free Life” by an American supporter of Herbert have been reprinted in Eric Mack’s collection The Right and Wrong of State Compulsion and Other Essaysby Auberon Herbert (Indianapolis: Liberty Classics, 1978).

Another classical example of Voluntaryism at work in England is to be found in William Godwin’s Enquiry Concerning Political Justice which first appeared in 1793. The best introduction to Godwin is found in the 1946 reprint edition by F.E.L. Priestley (Toronto: University of Toronto Press.) Godwin believed that physical force was too uncertain in its results and that peaceful resistance to tyrannical government was more desirable and effective. Godwin argued for reasonable discussion and disciplined non-cooperation as the means of fighting authority. In Book II, Chapter III, and Book IV, Chapter I, he urged that “All government is founded on opinion. Men at present live under any particular form, because they conceive it their interest to so do. …Destroy this opinion, and the fabric which is built upon it falls to the ground.” “Make men wise, and by that very operation you make them free. Civil liberty follows as a consequence of this; no usurped power can stand against the artillery of opinion.”

Godwin, in one important particular, was at variance with the main tradition of dissent in the 18th Century. A large body of dissenters thought in terms of politics; they tended to see problems as political and to seek political solutions. They favored associations and the normal methods of bringing political pressure to bear; they looked to legislative action for a solution of problems. Godwin, on the other hand, looked only to the reformation of the individual, objected to political parties, and had no faith in political solutions of what were for him simply moral problems. The voluntaryistic dissenters believed that moral agitation was always more effective and more proper than political activity.

The 19th Century abolitionists both in England and the United States, struggling to abolish slavery and the slave trade, were faced with similar problems. Was slave-holding to be abolished by moral suasion or political means? Should abolitionists participate in party politics or should they hold aloof from such controversies? Should they create their own organizations to propagate the abolition of slavery? Should they use political action to achieve their goals? The problems faced by the 19th Century abolitionists were very similar to the ones faced by 20th Century libertarians in their struggle to achieve a free society.

William Lloyd Garrison, Wendell Phillips, and Henry Clarke Wright were the leaders of the radical abolitionist movement in America. These men and their followers in the New England Non-Resistance Society held that all office holding and voting was morally wrong and reprehensible. Ultimately, the Garrisonians came to see the Constitution as a document which supported slavery and one to which they could not swear personal allegiance. These abolitionists suggested many of the arguments used by anti-political libertarians today. For example, they raised the issue of personal integrity. How could any abolitionist (read, libertarian) accept a government salary or swear a public oath of allegiance to the Constitution, or uphold laws which violate personal liberty? Garrison argued that political parties alter one’s fundamental outlook towards the State. The Liberty Party, which had been purposely formed as an anti-slavery party in 1840, appalled Garrison, both as a matter of theory and of tactics. He claimed that an anti-slavery party would split the movement and dilute anti-slavery principles by dragging them into the political gutter.

The Garrisonian ideas were propagated in many forums. Garrison engaged in a debate with James Birney, soon to be head of the Liberty Party in the 1830’s. In their A Letter on the Political Obligations of Abolitionists(Boston: Dow and Jackson, 1839) Garrison argued that moral suasion, not political action, was needed to reform public sentiment. Both of Garrison’s chief helpers, Phillips and Wright, independently expressed their anti-political views. Wright authored a small book entitled Ballot Box and Battlefield (Boston: Dow and Jackson, 1842) in which he claimed that the ballot box was only a make shift substitute for the violence of bullets on the battlefield. Wright held that no man could honestly undertake to become a voter and then vote against the existence of government. “May a man consent to be invested with power to do an evil?”, he asked. Wright claimed that a man may never rightfully consent to do what he thinks wrong. He who would do so proves himself dishonest. “He consents to be vested with power to do what he acknowledges to be wrong, and swears to do it. Such a man is unworthy of any trust.” Thus Wright concluded the fact that any man, knowing the nature and duties of a Congressman or President, “will consent to hold these offices, is of itself sufficient evidence that he is not a true and good man.” Wright summarized his argument by stating that he would not vote, even if by his one vote he could free all the slaves. Wendell Phillips considered the question: Can an Abolitionist Vote or Take Office Under the United States Constitution? (New York: American Anti-Slavery Society, 1845) and concluded quite straight forwardly that they could not.

The secondary literature dealing with the abolitionist position on voting is quite extensive and certainly much easier to locate than some of the primary materials. Two standard discussions of the voting controversy can be found in Aileen Kraditor, Means and Ends in American Abolitionism (New York: Pantheon Books, 1969) and in Lewis Perry, Radical Abolitionism: Anarchy and the Government of God in Antislavery Thought (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1973). Another excellent discussion of the “Garrisonian Critique” of politics can be found in William Wiecek, The Sources of Antislavery Constitutionalism in America, 1760-1848 (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1977). Some of Henry Clarke Wright’s writings (see the index for the entries under Wright), as well as excerpts from the Garrison-Birney exchange (see pp. 153-160), can be found in Truman Nelson’s Documents of Upheaval, Selections From Willaim Lloyd Garrison’s The Liberator 1831-1865 (New York: Hill and Wang, 1966).

Another very interesting aspect of the abolitionist movement is to be found in the writings of Henry David Thoreau and his close friend Charles Lane. Lane was an Englishman attracted to this country through his friendship with Bronson Alcott (another close friend of Thoreau). Both Alcott and Lane were arrested for refusal to pay their town taxes and their examples served to spur Thoreau onto his well known example of tax resistance. All three were opposed to voting and made their views, widely known. Lane wrote an extensive series of letters which appeared in Garrison’s The Liberator in 1843. They were entitled A Voluntary Political Government and have been recently reprinted (Carl Watner, editor, St. Paul: Michael Coughlin, Publisher, 1982). In the letters, Lane advocated a totally voluntary, anarchistic society. Lane’s aversion to politics is apparent in many of the letters and he realized that governmental control rests on the acquiescence of the citizenry. “This mixture of education with politics [by which he meant public schooling] is only a contrivance to gild the iron chains by which men are so despotically bound.” In his third letter, Lane urged us to go as far as possible from human governments. Participation in politics is evil. “Like all our enemies, State oppression will die of itself if we meddle not with it,” and do not support it. Disown the government and do not support it with your taxes. Enlighten the oppressed as to their own self-imposed servitude, but stay away from the State for it will only contaminate you. The similarity between Lane’s answer and Thoreau’s solution in Thoreau’s own “Resistance to Civil Government” (better known as his essay on “Civil Disobedience”) (Aesthetic Papers, Boston: Elizabeth Peabody, 1849) is quite striking:

“When the subject has refused allegiance, and the officer has resigned his office, then the revolution is accomplished.”

Lysander Spooner, the famous individualist-anarchist and constitutional lawyer, also played a prominent role in the abolitionist movement. Before he evolved into an outright anarchist, Spooner wrote some trenchant and logical attacks against the Garrisonian claim that the Constitution supported slavery. These are reprinted in The Collected Works of Lysander Spooner (Charles Shively, editor, Weston: M & S Press, 1971) and appear as The Unconstituionality of Slavery (Boston: Bela Marsh, Part I – 1845 and Part II – 1847). Spooner’s famous An Essay on Trial By Jury (Boston: John Jewett and Co., 1852) and his attacks on the Fugitive Slave law were all written to show why the common law, when uncorrupted by State legislation, upheld individual rights and destroyed slavery. There are some brilliant passages in all these works upholding natural rights, and especially the rights of all citizens to resist unjust acts of oppression perpetrated by the government (see his A Defence For Fugitive Slaves, Boston: Bela Marsh, 1850, Chapter II, “The Right of Resistance, and the Right to have the Legality of that Resistance judged of by a Jury”).

After the Civil War, and as a result of having lived through a domestic rebellion in which all the ideals of the American Revolution were totally ignored, Spooner became an anarchist. In his No Treason (1867 and 1870) series Spooner showed that the U.S. government could not claim either voting or tax-paying as proof that individuals consented to the government. Neither were evidence of any single person’s consent to the Constitution as a legal document. Spooner claimed that both paying taxes and voting were done under indirect threats, and therefore, were to be construed as acts of self-defense. However, Spooner never maintained that people should vote or that voting was proper or that he personally would ever take any part in the political process. Rather, he argued that when and if people vote, their actions were not to be interpreted as evidence that they actually supported the Constitution. Spooner eventually concluded that no one should have the right to vote or make laws. “No human being, nor any number of human beings, have any right to make laws, and compel other human beings to obey them. To say that they have is to say that they are masters and owners of those whom they require such obedience.” Spooner’s final conclusions on voting were expressed in his piece “Against Woman Suffrage”, which was reprinted in Benjamin Tucker’s Liberty (June 10, 1882, No. 22, p. 4) and in Rampart Individualist (Vol. 1, No. 1 and 2, Winter and Spring 1981, pp. 53-55).

Many other 19th Century individualist-anarchists supported Spooner’s position against political involvement. Josiah Warren, for example, one of the earliest American anarchists, rejected politics and engaged in a life long quest for the development of anarchist communities. Benjamin Tucker, the student of both Warren and Spooner, and editor of the famous journal Liberty (1881-1908), compiled his views on anarchist methods in a section of his book, Instead of a Book (originally published 1893, and reprinted by Haskell House Publishers, New York, 1969). The best of Tucker’s anti-political views are presented in a short editorial called “The Method of Anarchy” (Liberty, June 18, 1887; Haskell House edition, p. 415). Tucker advocated passive resistance as the superior alternative to either ballots or violent revolution.

Referring to the Voluntaryist insight, Tucker claimed that passive resistance (which hereafter shall be referred to as non-violent resistance) was … the most potent weapon ever wielded by man against oppression”. “Power feeds on its spoils, and dies when its victims refuse to be despoiled. They can’t persuade it to death; they can’t vote it to death; they can’t shoot it to death; but they can always starve it to death. When a determined body of people, sufficiently strong in numbers and force of character to command respect and make it unsafe to imprison them, shall agree to quietly close their doors in the face of the tax collector… government … will go by the board.” Tucker cited the near success of the Irish Land League and No Rent Movement in Ireland as examples of non-violent resistance campaigns.

Francis Tandy (a follower of Tucker) in his chapter on “Methods” in Voluntary Socialism (Denver: by the author, 1896) reiterated the strength of Tucker’s argument for non-violent resistance. “To gain anything by political methods, it is first necessary to gain a majority of the votes cast, and even then you have to trust to the integrity of the men elected to office. But with non-violent resistance this is unnecessary. … A strong, determined and intelligent minority, employing methods of non-violent resistance, would be able to carry all before it.” Tandy astutely pointed out the important relationships between means and ends in libertarian thought. Non-violent “resistance can never pass a law. It can only nullify laws. Consequently, it can never be used as a means of coercion and is particularly adapted to the attainment of Anarchy. All other schools of reform propose to compel people to do something. For this they must resort to force, usually by passing laws. These laws depend upon political action for their inauguration and physical violence for their enforcement. Anarchists are the only reformers who do not advocate physical violence. Tyranny must ever depend upon the weapon of tyranny, but Freedom can be inaugurated only by means of Freedom.” Tandy realized that when non-violent resistance is practiced, attention is drawn to its underlying principles. “Thus education and non-violent resistance go hand in hand and help each other, step by step, towards the goal of human Freedom.” A good discussion of late 19th Century individualist-anarchist strategy will appear in the forthcoming Liberty centennial volume in the chapter by Morgan Edwards, “Neither Bombs Nor Ballots: Benjamin Tucker and the Strategy of Anarchism” (Los Angeles: by the author, 1981).

During the first half of the 20th Century, the few well known libertarians actually followed the anti-political pattern set by Spooner, Tucker, and Tandy. Albert Jay Nock’s overall attitude certainly precluded political action. In his essay “What The American Votes For”, (reprinted in Snoring as a Fine Art and Twelve Other Essays, Freeport: Books for Libraries Press, 1971) which originally appeared in The American Mercury of February 1933, Nock claims that the only time he ever voted he cast a write-in ballot for Jefferson Davis on the basis that “if we can’t have a live statesman, let us by all means have a first-class corpse” (p. 90). In his essay “Anarchist’s Progress” (reprinted in On Doing The Right Thing and Other Essays, Freeport: Books for Libraries Press, 1971, first published 1928) Nock points out why it is impossible for the best intentioned office holder not to sell out to the system: Suppose that you put a Sunday school superintendent in charge of a whorehouse. “He might trim off some of the coarser fringes of the job, …and put things in … a state of ‘outward order and decency'”, but he must run a whorehouse, or he would promptly hear from the owners. The voters elect politicians to administer the State, not to destroy it. In the final analysis, Nock thought that “great and salutary social transformations, such as in the end do not cost more than they come to, are not effected by political shifts, by movements, by programs and platforms, least of all by violent revolutions, but by sound and disinterested thinking.”

H. L. Mencken, despite his outward appearances as a newspaperman, had some rather acerbic thoughts on the political system. His book Prejudices: Fourth Series (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1924) carries two implicitly anti-political essays, “The Politician” and “On Government.” Mencken begins his analysis of the politician by pointing out the assumption of the great majority of American voters: that politicians are divided into two classes, and that one of those classes is made up of good ones. Hence the American public thinks that every time they turn one set of politicians out of office, they will get better ones in their place. But how wrong they are, as history has proved: the “primary error lies in making the false assumption that some politicians are better than others” (p. 133). Obviously they are not. “Politics, as hopeful men practice it in the world, consists mainly of the delusion that a change in form is a change in substance” (p. 227).

Frank Chodorov really got to the heart of the matter when he declared that “the state itself, regardless of its composition, is an exploitative institution” (Fugitive Essays, Selected Writings of Frank Chodorov, selected by Charles Hamilton, Indianapolis: Liberty Press, 1980, p. 91). No matter who operates a whorehouse (to use Nock’s metaphor’) still operates a whorehouse; and any class of politician, even if they call themselves libertarians, are still politicians. It makes little difference whether libertarians, socialists, Democrats, or Republicans are in office; the State is still nothing more than a criminal gang. In his essays “On Underwriting an Evil” (in Out Of Step, New York: Devin-Adair, 1962) and “If We Quit Voting” (pp.200-205 of Fugitive Essays), Chodorov advocated staying away from the polls. “Why should a self respecting citizen endorse an institution grounded in thievery?” A voter’s boycott, unlike other revolutions, but much like non-violent resistance campaigns, “calls for no organization, no violence, no war fund, and no leader to sell it out.”

Other more recent libertarians have similarly called for mass non-participation in the electoral process. Robert LeFevre engaged in lengthy correspondence with a number of Congressional representatives and senators during 1972 in an effort to determine the legitimacy of their participation in government. Drawing much on Spooner’s analysis of elected representatives, LeFevre demonstrates in his The Power of Congress (As Congress Sees It) (Los Angeles: R. S. Radford, 1976) that the theory of electoral representation has no firm basis. His correspondents could not agree “whether representatives should really be agents of their electors and varied widely in the interpretation of their own function and authority.” LeFevre contends that because of the secret ballot and the structure of our political institutions elected office holders are in fact representatives of no one. They had best all pack up and go home!

Sy Leon in his None of the Above – The Lesser of Two Evils . . . is Evil (Santa Barbara: Fabian Publishing, 1976) attacks majority rule as a violation of individual rights and opposes the political vote. Voting is wrong because it does not give individuals the right to express their true opinions about the politicians. The politicians do not dare insert “None of the Above” on the ballot for fear that no politician would be elected to office. Robert Ringer in his bestseller, Restoring the American Dream (New York: QED, 1979) cites Leon favorably and makes some telling comments about the Libertarian Party and voting in general:”When you vote for a candidate, you are voting to put someone in a position to rule the lives of your fellowman – men who either do not want that candidate to rule them or do not want anyone’ to rule them” (p. 285). “The most disconcerting thing about the Libertarian Party is that it ‘is’ a political party” (p. 288). Every political party and every politician is subject to the historical law of corruption: Power corrupts and absolute power corrupts absolutely.

Among the younger generation of contemporary libertarians, Samuel Edward Konkin III and George H. Smith have led the attack against political action. Konkin’s magazine New Libertarian and his “Movement of the Libertarian Left” have long criticized the Libertarian Party. “He who serves the Party serves the State” because it is impossible to destroy the system by joining it. Konklin’s emphasis on counter-economics and agorism, as alternatives to political strategies, is set forth in his New Libertarian Manifesto (Box 1748, Long Beach, California 90801, published 1980). Smith, too, has tried to convey the message that Politics and libertarianism are inconsistent. One of his earliest attacks on the Libertarian Party was a satirical “Victory Speech of the Libertarian Party President-Elect, 1984” which appeared in Supplement 4 of New Libertarian Weekly (no. 46, October 31, 1976). Smith tried to show why a Libertarian President would be involved in all sorts of philosophical predicaments (how would he deal with tax evaders, drug smugglers, victims of victimless crime laws, etc.?). This criticism was followed up by a seriously theoretical piece entitled Party Dialogue (New Libertarian, Vol. 4, No. 8, Dec. 1980 – Feb. 1981; and reprinted Baltimore: The Voluntaryists, 1982; see reverse of this pamphlet for ordering instructions) and by an exchange of letters to the editor between Less Antman, a well-known member of the California LP and Smith, in New Libertarian (Vol. 5, no. 9, April-June, 1981). His most recent foray against the LP occurred at the California LP Convention on board the Queen Elizabeth II in February 1982. Here he continued his debate with Antman under the title “Political Action vs. Non Political Action” in which they exchanged their views on the validity of political action for libertarians. (See Tapes 651 A and B by Liberty Audio Forum, 824 West Broad Street, Richmond, Va. 23220.) Smith’s efforts against the LP have been instrumental in the formation of The Voluntaryists, whose purpose is to spread the message that libertarianism must be propagated by non-political means.

This brings to a conclusion our survey of literature which deals with the Voluntaryist insight and the question of anti-political and non-political activity. As can be seen from the suggestions of Tucker and Tandy, non-violent resistance is a very useful tool for Voluntaryists to embrace. It is hoped that the efforts put forth in this bibliographic essay will spark libertarians to at least investigate the merits and demerits of non-violent resistance, which itself has an extensive body of literature built up around it. The findings of such a study should be of great interest to all Voluntaryists and we hope it is not long forthcoming.

Voluntaryism in the Libertarian Tradition


by Carl Watner

 

 

Voluntaryism figures prominently in the libertarian tradition in three distinct ways. First, voluntaryism represents the final goal of all libertarians. After all, libertarianism is the doctrine that all the affairs of people, both public and private, should be carried out by individuals or their voluntary associations. Second-ly, voluntaryism is a realization about the nature of political society. The voluntaryist approach rests on the crucial, theoretical insight that all tyranny and government are grounded on general popular accept-ance. The primary responsibility for the existence and continuation of any political system rests on the majority of the population, who willingly acquiesce in their own subjection. Thirdly, voluntaryism represents a way of achieving significant social change without resort to politics or violent revolution. Since voluntaryists realize that government rests on popular consent, they conclude that the only way to abolish government power is simply for the people at large to withdraw that consent. As a means, voluntaryism calls for peaceful persuasion, education, civil disobedience, and non-violent resistance to the State. To libertarians, volun¬taryism thus represents a means, an end, and an insight. Only voluntary means can be used to attain the truly voluntary society, based on the insight that existing tyrannies depend on the voluntary submission of the governed. The purpose of this essay is to elucidate the history, the development, and the actual practice of these ideas within the context of the libertarian tradition.

These three aspects of voluntaryism mutually reinforce each other. The very goal of an all-voluntary society suggests its own means. The means are the seeds which bud into flowers and come into fruition. It is impossible to plant the seed of coercion and reap the flower of liberty. Thus politics and government, which libertarians view as essentially coercive processes, can never legitimately be used to attain libertarian goals. The non-voluntaryist always proposes to compel people to do something; usually by passing laws or electing politicians to office. These laws and officials depend upon political action and physical violence. Voluntaryist means, like non-violent resistance, for example, violate no one’s rights. They only serve to nullify laws and politicians by ignoring them. Voluntaryism does not require of people that they shall violently overthrow their government or even use the electoral process to change it; but merely that they shall cease to support their government, whereupon it will fall of its own dead weight.
Etienne de la Boetie (1530-1563), the first libertarian political philosopher in the Western world, was largely responsible for the original statement and elaboration of the voluntaryist principle. In his DISCOURSE ON VOLUNTARY SERVITUDE, probably written during the mid-1550s, la Boetie discussed one of the most critical problems of political philosophy; namely, the question of civil obedience. “Why in the world do people consent to their own enslavement?,” he asked. “Why do the bulk of the people acquiesce in their own subjection?” La Boetie answered these questions by explaining the governmental mystique created by rulers and their intellectual apologists. By relying on custom, by providing bread and circuses to the citizenry, and by creating a vast network of governmental supporters dependent on political plunder, governments were able to engineer and sustain their own popular acceptance among the populace.

La Boetie’s voluntaryist insight, that consent is brought about largely by government propaganda, speaks sharply to the problem of strategy. It leads directly to the conclusion that mass civil disobedience and mass non-violent resistance are the only true methods for overthrowing tyranny. Realizing the great value of natural liberty, la Boetie called for a thorough process of educating the public to the truth, a process which would give back to the people a knowledge of the blessings of liberty and a knowledge of the myths and illusions fostered by the State. The primary task of opponents of tyranny is an educational one: to alert the public to their despotic condition, to demystify and desanctify the entire State apparatus. La Boetie was thus the first political philosopher to move from an emphasis on the importance of consent to the strategic importance of toppling tyranny by leading the public to withdraw their consent.

The value of la Boetie’s insights were somewhat lost to the 16th and 17th Century English, yet voluntaryism played a significant part in the struggle between Church and State during these centuries. During the mid-17th Century, the English Independents were moving towards a completely voluntaryist conception of the Church. They considered that maintenance of churches by tithes and State support ought to be done away with. This was no new idea and for a long period there had been Inde­pendents who realized that this was the logical outcome of their views of separation of Church and State. For example, a petition circulated in London in 1647, demanded that “tithes and all other enforced maintenance may be forever abolished, and nothing in the place thereof imposed; but that all ministers be paid only by those who voluntarily chose them and contract with them for their labors.” By substituting ‘taxes’ for ‘tithes’ and ‘governmental officials’ for ‘ministers,’ we realize how close these early religious dissenters were to espousing the ideas of a truly voluntary State. The early advocates of Church-State separation were in the vanguard of the libertarian tradition because they took one of the first steps necessary to separate the State from all the rest of society.

In these religious controversies, the term ‘voluntaryism’ was representative of those who advocated complete separation of Church and State. The term itself came into common usage during the extensive disputes between the Churchmen and dissenters in Scotland during the second decade of the 19th Century. It was then picked up by the English non-conformists during the 1830s, and applied to their agitation to keep the English government out of the educational process. The ‘voluntary educationists’ saw a religious threat in State-controlled education and many believed that the law of supply and demand, or the voluntary principle, as they termed it, would provide for the education of the whole English people. Auberon Herbert attempted to repopularize the term during the 1880s and the 1890s in his voluntaryist journal, FREE LIFE.

William Godwin, author of an ENQUIRY CONCERNING POLITICAL JUSTICE in 1793, offers a good example of voluntaryist thinking in late 18th Century England. It is interesting to note that revolutionary violence never became a serious threat to England because of the influence of the religious non-conformist teachings among the working classes. Godwin, among other extreme political thinkers of that era, believed that physical force was too uncertain in its results and that peaceful resistance was more desirable and effective. Godwin argued for reasonable discussion and disciplined non-cooperation as the means of fighting against authority. In POLITICAL JUSTICE (Book II, Chap. III, and Book IV, Chap. 1) he urged that “all government is founded in opinion. Men at present live under any particular form, because they conceive it their interest to do so. … Destroy this opinion, and the fabric which is built upon it falls to the ground.” “Make men wise and by that very operation you make them free. Civil liberty follows as a consequence of this; no usurped power can stand against the artillery of opinion.”

Godwin, in one important particular, was at variance with the main tradition of dissent in the 18th Century. A large body of dissenters thought in terms of politics; they tended to see problems as political and to seek political solutions. They favored associations and the normal methods of bringing political pressure to bear; they looked to legislative action for a solution of problems. Godwin, on the other hand, looked only to the reformation of the individual, objected to political parties, and had no faith in political solutions of what were for him simply moral problems. The voluntaryist dissenters believed that moral agitation was always more effective and more proper than political activity.

The 19th Century abolitionists both in England and the United States, struggling to abolish slavery and the slave trade, were faced with similar problems. Was slave-holding to be abolished by moral suasion or political means? Should abolitionists participate in party politics or should they hold aloof from such controversies? Should they create their own third party organizations to propagate the abolition of slavery? The radical abolitionists were on the cutting edge of the libertarian movement because they viewed slavery as the worst form of stealing. Slavery was called ‘man-stealing’ because it reflected the theft of a person’s self-ownership rights. The problems faced by the 19th Century abolitionists, both in terms of goals and strategy, have much to say about the place of voluntaryism in the libertarian movement today.

William Lloyd Garrison led one wing of the abolitionist movement, and it is his views which we shall first examine. By the mid 1840s, Garrison and his chief lieutenants, Wendell Phillips and Henry Clarke Wright, had come to the conclusion that all office-holding and voting was wrong and morally reprehensible. These men arrived at their views in two different ways. During the 1830s, Garrison had addressed himself to the issues of perfectionism and non-resistance. He and his fellow non-resistants rejected not only war, but the entire apparatus that sustained government in power. He summarized their position in the 1838 Declaration of Sentiments adopted by the Peace Convention held in Boston that year. Non-resistants renounced all allegiance to human governments and disabled themselves from holding any political office. This carried with it a rejection of voting. “If we cannot occupy a seat in the legislature or on the bench, neither can we elect others to act as our substitutes in any such capacity.”

In 1841, Garrison and his followers underwent a further transformation, which led to a reinforcement of their beliefs against political action. The Liberty Party, which had been purposely formed as an anti-slavery party in 1840, appalled Garrison, both as a matter of theory and tactics. He claimed that an anti-slavery third party would split the movement and dilute anti-slavery principles by dragging them into the political gutter. Nearly at the same time, the Garrisonians came to the realization that the Constitution was actually a pro-slavery document and that disunion should be the rule of the day. They came to see the Constitution as “a covenant with death and an agreement with hell” and therefore advocated personal disallegiance from the federal government and sectional disunion from the South.

This outlook on the Constitution was only developed after the Garrisonians had been preaching their non-resistance and no-voting theories for a number of years. Since Garrison took all of these demands seriously, he came to condemn voting not only for all non-resistants but for all enfranchised citizens. He took the ground that to vote for any public officer, local, state, or federal, would be to endorse someone who would have to take an oath to uphold the United States Constitution which supported slavery. Any act of allegiance to a government whose constitution supported slavery “means either to undertake to execute the law which I think wrong or to appoint another to do so” for me.

The Garrisonian ideas were propagated in many forums. Garrison himself engaged in a debate with James Birney, soon to be head of the Liberty Party, in the late 1830s. In his “Letter on the Political Obligations of Abolitionists,” Garrison maintained that the political reformation which would bring about the abolition of slavery “is to be expected solely by a change in the moral vision of the people; – not by attempting to prove that it is the duty of every abolitionist to be a voter, but that it is the duty of every voter to be an abolitionist.” It was, in his opinion, the general object of the antislavery movement to so “affect public sentiment …and alter the views and feelings of the people in regard to the crime of slave holding, that all classes of society… may be induced to rally together en masse for the entire abolition of slavery.” Garrison’s field was not the field of political action but that of moral suasion. In seeking to reform public sentiment that lay behind laws and constitutions, Garrison was striking at the heart of the problem.

Both of Garrison’s chief helpers, Phillips and Wright, independently expressed their anti-political views. Phillips wrote of his “No-Voting Theory” in THE LIBERATOR during the 1844 and then further clarified his views in his 1845 pamphlet, “Can Abolitionists Vote or Take Office under the United States Constitution?” Henry Clarke Wright had earlier formulated his views in his 1841 booklet on “Ballot Box and Battle Field.” Wright maintained the non-resistant position, claiming that the ballot box was at most only a make-shift substitute for the violence of bullets on the battle field. According to his lights, no man could honestly accept the office of voter and then vote against the existence of government. “May a man consent to be invested with power to do an evil and swear to do it, even for the purpose of abolishing that evil?” he asked. Wright claimed that a man may never rightfully consent to do what he thinks wrong. He who would do it proves himself dishonest. “He consents to be vested with power to do what he acknowledges to be wrong, and swears to do it, and then gravely assures us that he never intended to do it. Such a man is unworthy of any trust.” Thus Wright concluded the fact that any man, knowing the nature and duties of a Congressman or President, “will consent to hold these offices, is of itself sufficient evidence that he is not a true and good man.” Wright summarized his argument by stating that he would not vote, even if by his one vote he could free all the slaves.

Wendell Phillips in his consideration of the question if abolitionists can vote or take office under the Constitution came to a very simple conclusion: namely, that they could not. The position of non-voter and conscientious objector to the government was to be jealously guarded. In a land where the ballot is idolized, the non-voter “kindles in every beholder’s bosom something of the warm sympathy which waits on the persecuted, carries with it all the weight of a disinterested testimony to truth and pricks each voter’s conscience with an uneasy doubt, whether after all voting is right. There is constantly a Mordecai in the gate.” Phillips sustained his claim that “it is by no means necessary that every man should actually vote, in order to influence his times,” by citing the historical examples of conscientious objectors who wielded a moral influence widely disproportionate to their numbers.

Other wings of the radical abolitionist movement supported the no-voting stance taken by the Garrisonians. Nathaniel Peabody Rogers, long-time editor of the New Hampshire Anti-Slavery Society journal, HERALD OF FREEDOM, noted that men in this country have been brought up to believe that nothing can be accomplished except by political methods. “They cannot understand how any sane mind can discern any other way to any end.” The only object of party politics, for Rogers, was power. “To get it or preserve it is the only possible motive.” Rogers realized that the vote which a man casts is but a very insignificant emblem of his political power. “The influence which goes out from every man, whether for good or evil, can be but very imperfectly measured by the standard of a ballot. What he seems to lose by the withdrawal of his single vote, is gained 100 fold in the increased force which is given to the testimony of the lips and of the life by that disinterested act. … We only know that we are following the dictates of plain, practical common sense, in refusing to commit what we see to be a crime, in order to extirpate another crime. We will not consent to obtain power by false pretenses, even for the purpose of abolishing slavery.” Rogers realized the futility of gaining power temporarily; for what can be voted up today, may be voted down tomorrow.

Lysander Spooner was another radical abolitionist who totally rejected voting and political party activity. Prior to the Civil War, Spooner had been asked to lend his support to the Liberty Party. He refused in no uncertain terms in his letter of March 12, 1856:

I feel at liberty – standing outside of the Constitution and knowing that government of some kind will be carried on in the name of the Constitution – to interpret the Constitution, on those points wherein it is right, and then appeal to those, who professed to be governed by it, to act up to their own standard. I do this on the same principle that, standing outside the Mohammedan religion, I should feel at liberty to interpret the Koran, and appeal to believers to act up to their own creed, wherein it was right. It is on this ground that I write about the Constitution, and not because I ever intend to take any part, directly or indirectly, in administering it. I think no robbery is more flagrant or palpable – nor hardly any more unjus­tifiable – than taxing men for the support of government, without their personal consent. … Such taxation is not only robbery in itself, but it supplies the means for, and is the legi­timate parent of, nearly all the other tyranny, which governments practice. You will see therefore that it is impossible for me to sup­port any government that acts on that prin­ciple, or to act with any party that adopts it.

Spooner echoed Henry Clarke Wright’s analysis of voting and consent. Wright wrote that “when a man consents to receive and exercise the right of suffrage … he consents that a majority shall rule and pledges himself to aid in executing the will of the majority. Whether he votes with the majority or not, by consenting to vote at all, he becomes responsible for whatever it does.” Spooner wrote, “I would advocate natural law and constitutional law, wherever I could get an audience to listen; because all men in office and out of office are bound by them without regard to minorities or majorities among the people. But I do not rely upon ‘political machinery’ (although it may or may not do good, according as its objects are, or are not legal and constitutional) – but I do not rely upon it as such – because the principle of it is wrong. For it admits (and this is my objection to it) that even under a constitution, the law depends upon the will of majorities, for the time being, as indicated by the acts of the legislature. It admits the right of majorities – even under a constitution which purports to fix men’s rights – to make and unmake laws at pleasure – or at least with very little limitation.”

After the Civil War, Spooner wrote in his NO TREASON pamphlets that voting and tax-paying were not legal evidence of assent to the Constitution. Both were done under duress and were, in effect, acts of self-defense. Spooner never maintained that people should vote or that voting was proper. Rather he argued, that when and if people vote, their actions were not to be interpreted as unquestioning obedience to the Constitution. Spooner eventually concluded that no one should have the right to vote or make laws. “No human being, nor any number of human beings, have any right to make laws, and compel other human beings to obey them. To say that they have is to say that they are masters and owners of those whom they require obedience.” In the final analysis, Spooner rejected the Constitution and politics entirely: “This much is certain – the Constitution either authorized such a government as we have had, or has been powerless to prevent it. In either case, it is unfit to exist.”

Henry David Thoreau, the famous civil resistant, was most sympathetic to the abolitionist cause. Thoreau was influenced by his friendship with Ralph Waldo Emerson, who in turn was an admirer of William Lloyd Garrison. All three shared in common the idea of individual conscience standing in opposition to the State. The core of Thoreau’s argument is that men become machines when they obey orders without thinking or when they give the government authority to speak or act on their behalf. “Must the citizen … resign his conscience to the legislator?” Thoreau asked. “Why has every man a conscience, then? I think that we should be men first. … It is not desirable to cultivate a respect for the law, so much as for the right. … Law never made a man a whit more just; and, by means of their respect for it, even the well-disposed are daily made the agents of injustice.” Thoreau was speaking out against slavery as well as against the American invasion of Mexico, which took place in 1846.

Thoreau was particularly out-spoken against voting. He saw voting as a sort of gaming. “The character of the voters is not staked. … Even voting for the right is doing nothing for it. … A wise man will not leave the right to the mercy of chance, nor wish it to prevail through the power of the majority. There is but little virtue in the action of masses of men.” Thoreau recognized the importance of civil disobedience, both as an individual moral statement and tactical position. Referring to his own short imprisonment and his influence, Thoreau wrote: “If any think that their influence would be lost [in prison], and their voices no longer afflict the ear of the State, …they do not know how much truth is stronger than error, nor how much more eloquently and effectively he can combat injustice who has experienced a little in his own person.”

Adopting la Boetie’s strategic outlook, he then wrote: “Cast your whole vote, not a strip of paper merely, but your influence. A minority is powerless while it conforms to the majority; it is not even a minority then; but it is irrestible when it clogs by its whole weight. … If a thousand men were not to pay their tax-bills this year, that would not be as violent and bloody a measure, as it would be to pay them, and enable the State to commit violence and shed innocent blood. This is, in fact, the definition of a peaceable revolution, if any such is possible. If the taxgatherer, or any other public officer, asks me, as one has done, ‘But what shall I do?’ my answer is, ‘If you really wish to do anything, resign your office.’ When the subject has refused allegiance, and the officer has resigned his office, then the revolution is accomplished.”

Thus concludes our brief survey of voluntaryism in the libertarian tradition. Voluntaryism has a revolutionary potential that has not been adequately recognized. If we wish to remain true to our libertarian heritage, it is clear that voluntaryism as a means, an end, and an insight, deserves our support.

Short Bibliography

  • Etienne de la Boetie, THE POLITICS OF OBEDIENCE: THE DISCOURSE OF VOLUNTARY SERVITUDE, Introduction by Murray N. Rothbard, Translated by Harry Kurz, New York: Free Life Editions, 1975.
  • Chambers’s Encyclopedia, “Voluntaryism,” Vol. X, p. 23, Philadelphia: J.B. Lippincott & Co.,1882.
  • William Godwin, ENQUIRY CONCERNING POLITICAL JUSTICE AND ITS INFLUENCE ON MORALS AND HAPPINESS, Critical Intro­duction by F.E.L. Priestley, Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1946.
  • Lewis Perry, RADICAL ABOLITIONISM: ANARCHY AND THE GOVERNMENT OF GOD IN ANTI-STAVERY THOUGHT, Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1973. See esp. pp.198-205 on Spooner.
  • Nathaniel Peabody Rogers, A COLLECTION FROM THE MISCELLANEOUS WRITINGS OF NATHANIEL PEABODY ROGERS, Boston: Ben­jamin B. Mussey, 1849.
  • Lysander Spooner, THE COLLECTED WORKS OF LYSANDER SPOONER, Introductions by Charles Shively, Weston, Mass.: M & S Press, 1971.
  • Henry David Thoreau, WALDEN AND ON THE DUTY OF CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE with an After­ward by Perry Miller, New York:The American Library, 1960.
  • William Wiecek, THE SOURCES OF ANTI-SLAVERY CONSTITUTIONALISM IN AMERICA, 1760-1848, Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1977. See esp. Chap. 10 on “The Garrisonian Critique.”
  • George Woodcock, CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE, Toronto: Canadian Broadcasting Corp., 1966, Esp. good on Thoreau, Gandhi, and the “Tradition of English Dissent.”

[This piece first appeared as No. II in THE VOL­UNTARYIST SERIES, First Printing – May 1982.]

H.L. Mencken on Public Education


[Editor’s Note: The following excerpts are taken from Volume XXVIII, Number 110 of THE AMERICAN MERCURY (February 1933). They appeared in a column titled “What Is Going On In The World”. Mencken begins his comments by pointing out that government expenditures on the public schools had grown from about $ 5 per pupil in 1880 to $ 100 per pupil in 1933 (now in excess of $12,000). He then questions what these gun-run schools have accomplished. Contemporary critics of public schools present an ever more detailed view of their history and current effects. For example, see the work of Brett Veinotte; Richard Grove’s production of John Taylor Gatto’s “Ultimate History Lesson”, or John’s website. For John’s article, “Why Schools Don’t Educate,” see issue 53 of THE VOLUNTARYIST, page 8, voluntaryist.com ].

There is, indeed, very little evidence that they have ever actually earned the money they have demanded and got, either in 1914 or since. If their fundamental aim is to provide the country with an enlightened electorate, they have failed completely and miserably, for the electorate is no more enlightened today than it was before they were ever set up. On the contrary, there is plausible reason for believing that it has gone backward in intelligence, for it handles its business, not with increasing prudence, but with increasing imbecility. The American people of a hundred years ago, when public schools were still few and meager, might have been described plausibly as notably political-minded: they were ardently interested in public affairs, and intervened in them, on the whole, with quick understanding and sound judgment. But today they are so lethargic that it takes a calamity to arouse them at all, and so stupid that it becomes more nearly impossible every year for intelligent and self-respecting men to aspire to public office among them.

I believe that it would be rational to argue that the public school, far from combating this immense increase in stupidity, has been very largely responsible for it. For the true aim and purpose of the pedagogue, and especially of the pedagogue who is also a bureaucrat, is never to awaken his victims to independent and logical thought; it is simply to force them into a mold. And that mold is bound to be a cramped and dingy one, for the pedagogue is a cramped and dingy man himself. The office he fills, in its potentialities, is an immensely important one, but in its daily business it is puerile and uninspiring, and so it is seldom filled by a man (or woman) of any genuine force and originality. In all ages pedagogues have been the bitterest enemies of all genuine intellectual enterprise, and in no age have they warred upon it more violently or to sadder effect than in our own. More than any other class of blind leaders of the blind they are responsible for the degrading standardization which now afflicts the American people. They would have done even worse, I believe, if it had been in their power. They failed only because a sufficient number of their victims have always been too intelligent to succumb to them, and because even the stupid majority yet preserves a saving skepticism about their ridiculous arcane. …

The basic trouble with the public schools is that they have fallen into the hands of a well-organized and extremely ambitious bureaucracy, and that machinery for curbing its pretensions has yet to be devised. In every American municipality, though all of them are desperately hard up and many are hopelessly bankrupt, it has resisted every effort to cut down its demands on the public treasury, and in this black year of 1933 it will actually get a larger relative share of the public money than ever before. It has thrown the grotesque mantle of Service about its extortions, and convinced millions of the unthinking that they are essential to the public good. Let any rash fellow challenge it, and he is denounced at once as an enemy to the true, the good and the beautiful. Operating impudently and over a generation of time, it has deluded the great majority of Americans into accepting its brummagem values unquestioningly, and filled them with the superstition that if the public schools were shut down the country would at once go to pot. …

The first grand effect of universal free education in the United States was to turn the American people, once so independent and self-reliant, into a race of shameless mendicants, looking to the government, as to some cosmic Santa Claus, for all their needs. And its second effect, now more horribly visible every day, has been to ram them all into a single mold, and that a mold shaped by silly babus, so that the test of Americanism comes to be the extent to which every American thinks and feels, aspires and exults like every other American, and all approach as closely as possible to the ideas and emotions, aspirations and exultations of a jackass. …

The notion that they [the public schools] have done and are doing any ponderable good is mainly a delusion. What they have actually done is a lot of harm. They have taken the care and upbringing of children out of the hands of parents, where it belongs, and thrown it upon a gang of irresponsible and unintelligent quacks. They have filled multitudes of the uneducable with ideas that make them uncomfortable, and are useless to them, and unfit them for the inevitabilities of their lowly station. They have supported every sort of nonsense that has afflicted the country, from the hog-wallow imbecility of Prohibition to all the more florid and degrading varieties of patriotism. They are responsible, more than any other agency, for the present pathetic helplessness of the American people, stunned and made ridiculous by a common misfortune that other peoples tackle in a realistic and rational manner. Altogether, they have pretty well smeared the United States. It has been going downhill ever since the pedagogues grabbed their first billion [dollars].

The Reluctant Anarchist


By Joe Sobran

December 2002

My arrival (very recently) at philosophical anarchism has disturbed some of my conservative and Christian friends. In fact, it surprises me, going as it does against my own inclinations.

As a child I acquired a deep respect for authority and a horror of chaos. In my case the two things were blended by the uncertainty of my existence after my parents divorced and I bounced from one home to another for several years, often living with strangers. A stable authority was something I yearned for.

Meanwhile, my public-school education imbued me with the sort of patriotism encouraged in all children in those days. I grew up feeling that if there was one thing I could trust and rely on, it was my government. I knew it was strong and benign, even if I didn’t know much else about it. The idea that some people — Communists, for example — might want to overthrow the government filled me with horror.

G.K. Chesterton, with his usual gentle audacity, once criticized Rudyard Kipling for his “lack of patriotism.” Since Kipling was renowned for glorifying the British Empire, this might have seemed one of Chesterton’s “paradoxes”; but it was no such thing, except in the sense that it denied what most readers thought was obvious and incontrovertible.

Chesterton, himself a “Little Englander” and opponent of empire, explained what was wrong with Kipling’s view: “He admires England, but he does not love her; for we admire things with reasons, but love them without reason. He admires England because she is strong, not because she is English.” Which implies there would be nothing to love her for if she were weak.

Of course Chesterton was right. You love your country as you love your mother — simply because it is yours, not because of its superiority to others, particularly superiority of power.

This seems axiomatic to me now, but it startled me when I first read it. After all, I was an American, and American patriotism typically expresses itself in superlatives. America is the freest, the mightiest, the richest, in short the greatest country in the world, with the greatest form of government — the most democratic. Maybe the poor Finns or Peruvians love their countries too, but heaven knows why — they have so little to be proud of, so few “reasons.” America is also the most envied country in the world. Don’t all people secretly wish they were Americans?

That was the kind of patriotism instilled in me as a boy, and I was quite typical in this respect. It was the patriotism of supremacy. For one thing, America had never lost a war — I was even proud that America had created the atomic bomb (providentially, it seemed, just in time to crush the Japs) — and this is why the Vietnam war was so bitterly frustrating. Not the dead, but the defeat! The end of history’s great winning streak!

As I grew up, my patriotism began to take another form, which it took me a long time to realize was in tension with the patriotism of power. I became a philosophical conservative, with a strong libertarian streak. I believed in government, but it had to be “limited” government — confined to a few legitimate purposes, such as defense abroad and policing at home. These functions, and hardly any others, I accepted, under the influence of writers like Ayn Rand and Henry Hazlitt, whose books I read in my college years.

Though I disliked Rand’s atheism (at the time, I was irreligious, but not anti-religious), she had an odd appeal to my residual Catholicism. I had read enough Aquinas to respond to her Aristotelian mantras. Everything had to have its own nature and limitations, including the state; the idea of a state continually growing, knowing no boundaries, forever increasing its claims on the citizen, offended and frightened me. It could only end in tyranny.

I was also powerfully drawn to Bill Buckley, an explicit Catholic, who struck the same Aristotelian note. During his 1965 race for mayor of New York, he made a sublime promise to the voter: he offered “the internal composure that comes of knowing there are rational limits to politics.” This may have been the most futile campaign promise of all time, but it would have won my vote!

It was really this Aristotelian sense of “rational limits,” rather than any particular doctrine, that made me a conservative. I rejoiced to find it in certain English writers who were remote from American conservatism — Chesterton, of course, Samuel Johnson, Edmund Burke, George Orwell, C.S. Lewis, Michael Oakeshott.

In fact I much preferred a literary, contemplative conservatism to the activist sort that was preoccupied with immediate political issues. During the Reagan years, which I expected to find exciting, I found myself bored to death by supply-side economics, enterprise zones, “privatizing” welfare programs, and similar principle-dodging gimmickry. I failed to see that “movement” conservatives were less interested in principles than in Republican victories. To the extent that I did see it, I failed to grasp what it meant.

Still, the last thing I expected to become was an anarchist. For many years I didn’t even know that serious philosophical anarchists existed. I’d never heard of Lysander Spooner or Murray Rothbard. How could society survive at all without a state?

Now I began to be critical of the U.S. Government, though not very. I saw that the welfare state, chiefly the legacy of Franklin Roosevelt’s New Deal, violated the principles of limited government and would eventually have to go. But I agreed with other conservatives that in the meantime the urgent global threat of Communism had to be stopped. Since I viewed “defense” as one of the proper tasks of government, I thought of the Cold War as a necessity, the overhead, so to speak, of freedom. If the Soviet threat ever ceased (the prospect seemed remote), we could afford to slash the military budget and get back to the job of dismantling the welfare state.

Somewhere, at the rainbow’s end, America would return to her founding principles. The Federal Government would be shrunk, laws would be few, taxes minimal. That was what I thought. Hoped, anyway.

I avidly read conservative and free-market literature during those years with the sense that I was, as a sort of late convert, catching up with the conservative movement. I took it for granted that other conservatives had already read the same books and had taken them to heart. Surely we all wanted the same things! At bottom, the knowledge that there were rational limits to politics. Good old Aristotle. At the time, it seemed a short hop from Aristotle to Barry Goldwater.

As is fairly well known by now, I went to work as a young man for Buckley at National Review and later became a syndicated columnist. I found my niche in conservative journalism as a critic of liberal distortions of the U.S. Constitution, particularly in the Supreme Court’s rulings on abortion, pornography, and “freedom of expression.”

Gradually I came to see that the conservative challenge to liberalism’s jurisprudence of “loose construction” was far too narrow. Nearly everything liberals wanted the Federal Government to do was unconstitutional. The key to it all, I thought, was the Tenth Amendment, which forbids the Federal Government to exercise any powers not specifically assigned to it in the Constitution. But the Tenth Amendment had been comatose since the New Deal, when Roosevelt’s Court virtually excised it.

This meant that nearly all Federal legislation from the New Deal to the Great Society and beyond had been unconstitutional. Instead of fighting liberal programs piecemeal, conservatives could undermine the whole lot of them by reviving the true (and, really, obvious) meaning of the Constitution. Liberalism depended on a long series of usurpations of power.

Around the time of Judge Robert Bork’s bitterly contested (and defeated) nomination to the U.S. Supreme Court, conservatives spent a lot of energy arguing that the “original intent” of the Constitution must be conclusive. But they applied this principle only to a few ambiguous phrases and passages that bore on specific hot issues of the day — the death penalty, for instance. About the general meaning of the Constitution there could, I thought, be no doubt at all. The ruling principle is that whatever the Federal Government isn’t authorized to do, it’s forbidden to do.

That alone would invalidate the Federal welfare state and, in fact, nearly all liberal legislation. But I found it hard to persuade most conservatives of this. Bork himself took the view that the Tenth Amendment was unenforceable. If he was right, then the whole Constitution was in vain from the start.

I never thought a constitutional renaissance would be easy, but I did think it could play an indispensable role in subverting the legitimacy of liberalism. Movement conservatives listened politely to my arguments, but without much enthusiasm. They regarded appeals to the Constitution as rather pedantic and, as a practical matter, futile — not much help in the political struggle. Most Americans no longer even remembered what usurpation meant. Conservatives themselves hardly knew.

Of course they were right, in an obvious sense. Even conservative courts (if they could be captured) wouldn’t be bold enough to throw out the entire liberal legacy at once. But I remained convinced that the conservative movement had to attack liberalism at its constitutional root.

In a way I had transferred my patriotism from America as it then was to America as it had been when it still honored the Constitution. And when had it crossed the line? At first I thought the great corruption had occurred when Franklin Roosevelt subverted the Federal judiciary; later I came to see that the decisive event had been the Civil War, which had effectively destroyed the right of the states to secede from the Union. But this was very much a minority view among conservatives, particularly at National Review, where I was the only one who held it.

I’ve written more than enough about my career at the magazine, so I’ll confine myself to saying that it was only toward the end of more than two happy decades there that I began to realize that we didn’t all want the same things after all. When it happened, it was like learning, after a long and placid marriage, that your spouse is in love with someone else, and has been all along.

Not that I was betrayed. I was merely blind. I have no one to blame but myself. The Buckley crowd, and the conservative movement in general, no more tried to deceive me than I tried to deceive them. We all assumed we were on the same side, when we weren’t. If there is any fault for this misunderstanding, it is my own.

In the late 1980s I began mixing with Rothbardian libertarians — they called themselves by the unprepossessing label “anarcho-capitalists” — and even met Rothbard himself. They were a brilliant, combative lot, full of challenging ideas and surprising arguments. Rothbard himself combined a profound theoretical intelligence with a deep knowledge of history. His magnum opus, Man, Economy, and State, had received the most unqualified praise of the usually reserved Henry Hazlitt — in National Review!

I can only say of Murray what so many others have said: never in my life have I encountered such an original and vigorous mind. A short, stocky New York Jew with an explosive cackling laugh, he was always exciting and cheerful company. Pouring out dozens of big books and hundreds of articles, he also found time, heaven knows how, to write (on the old electric typewriter he used to the end) countless long, single-spaced, closely reasoned letters to all sorts of people.

Murray’s view of politics was shockingly blunt: the state was nothing but a criminal gang writ large. Much as I agreed with him in general, and fascinating though I found his arguments, I resisted this conclusion. I still wanted to believe in constitutional government.

Murray would have none of this. He insisted that the Philadelphia convention at which the Constitution had been drafted was nothing but a “coup d’etat,” centralizing power and destroying the far more tolerable arrangements of the Articles of Confederation. This was a direct denial of everything I’d been taught. I’d never heard anyone suggest that the Articles had been preferable to the Constitution! But Murray didn’t care what anyone thought — or what everyone thought. (He’d been too radical for Ayn Rand.)

Murray and I shared a love of gangster films, and he once argued to me that the Mafia was preferable to the state, because it survived by providing services people actually wanted. I countered that the Mafia behaved like the state, extorting its own “taxes” in protection rackets directed at shopkeepers; its market was far from “free.” He admitted I had a point. I was proud to have won a concession from him.

Murray died a few years ago without quite having made an anarchist of me. It was left to his brilliant disciple, Hans-Hermann Hoppe, to finish my conversion. Hans argued that no constitution could restrain the state. Once its monopoly of force was granted legitimacy, constitutional limits became mere fictions it could disregard; nobody could have the legal standing to enforce those limits. The state itself would decide, by force, what the constitution “meant,” steadily ruling in its own favor and increasing its own power. This was true a priori, and American history bore it out.

What if the Federal Government grossly violated the Constitution? Could states withdraw from the Union? Lincoln said no. The Union was “indissoluble” unless all the states agreed to dissolve it. As a practical matter, the Civil War settled that. The United States, plural, were really a single enormous state, as witness the new habit of speaking of “it” rather than “them.”

So the people are bound to obey the government even when the rulers betray their oath to uphold the Constitution. The door to escape is barred. Lincoln in effect claimed that it is not our rights but the state that is “unalienable.” And he made it stick by force of arms. No transgression of the Constitution can impair the Union’s inherited legitimacy. Once established on specific and limited terms, the U.S. Government is forever, even if it refuses to abide by those terms.

As Hoppe argues, this is the flaw in thinking the state can be controlled by a constitution. Once granted, state power naturally becomes absolute. Obedience is a one-way street. Notionally, “We the People” create a government and specify the powers it is allowed to exercise over us; our rulers swear before God that they will respect the limits we impose on them; but when they trample down those limits, our duty to obey them remains.

Yet even after the Civil War, certain scruples survived for a while. Americans still agreed in principle that the Federal Government could acquire new powers only by constitutional amendment. Hence the postwar amendments included the words “Congress shall have power to” enact such and such legislation.

But by the time of the New Deal, such scruples were all but defunct. Franklin Roosevelt and his Supreme Court interpreted the Commerce Clause so broadly as to authorize virtually any Federal claim, and the Tenth Amendment so narrowly as to deprive it of any inhibiting force. Today these heresies are so firmly entrenched that Congress rarely even asks itself whether a proposed law is authorized or forbidden by the Constitution.

In short, the U.S. Constitution is a dead letter. It was mortally wounded in 1865. The corpse can’t be revived. This remained hard for me to admit, and even now it pains me to say it.

Other things have helped change my mind. R.J. Rummel of the University of Hawaii calculates that in the twentieth century alone, states murdered about 162 million of their own subjects. This figure doesn’t include the tens of millions of foreigners they killed in war. How, then, can we speak of states “protecting” their people? No amount of private crime could have claimed such a toll. As for warfare, Paul Fussell’s book Wartime portrays battle with such horrifying vividness that, although this wasn’t its intention, I came to doubt whether any war could be justified.

My fellow Christians have argued that the state’s authority is divinely given. They cite Christ’s injunction “Render unto Caesar the things that are Caesar’s” and St. Paul’s words “The powers that be are ordained of God.” But Christ didn’t say which things — if any — belong to Caesar; his ambiguous words are far from a command to give Caesar whatever he claims. And it’s notable that Christ never told his disciples either to establish a state or to engage in politics. They were to preach the Gospel and, if rejected, to move on. He seems never to have imagined the state as something they could or should enlist on their side.

At first sight, St. Paul seems to be more positive in affirming the authority of the state. But he himself, like the other martyrs, died for defying the state, and we honor him for it; to which we may add that he was on one occasion a jailbreaker as well. Evidently the passage in Romans has been misread. It was probably written during the reign of Nero, not the most edifying of rulers; but then Paul also counseled slaves to obey their masters, and nobody construes this as an endorsement of slavery. He may have meant that the state and slavery were here for the foreseeable future, and that Christians must abide them for the sake of peace. Never does he say that either is here forever.

St. Augustine took a dim view of the state, as a punishment for sin. He said that a state without justice is nothing but a gang of robbers writ large, while leaving doubt that any state could ever be otherwise. St. Thomas Aquinas took a more benign view, arguing that the state would be necessary even if man had never fallen from grace; but he agreed with Augustine that an unjust law is no law at all, a doctrine that would severely diminish any known state.

The essence of the state is its legal monopoly of force. But force is subhuman; in words I quote incessantly, Simone Weil defined it as “that which turns a person into a thing — either corpse or slave.” It may sometimes be a necessary evil, in self-defense or defense of the innocent, but nobody can have by right what the state claims: an exclusive privilege of using it.

It’s entirely possible that states — organized force — will always rule this world, and that we will have at best a choice among evils. And some states are worse than others in important ways: anyone in his right mind would prefer living in the United States to life under a Stalin. But to say a thing is inevitable, or less onerous than something else, is not to say it is good.

For most people, anarchy is a disturbing word, suggesting chaos, violence, antinomianism — things they hope the state can control or prevent. The term state, despite its bloody history, doesn’t disturb them. Yet it’s the state that is truly chaotic, because it means the rule of the strong and cunning. They imagine that anarchy would naturally terminate in the rule of thugs. But mere thugs can’t assert a plausible right to rule. Only the state, with its propaganda apparatus, can do that. This is what legitimacy means. Anarchists obviously need a more seductive label.

“But what would you replace the state with?” The question reveals an inability to imagine human society without the state. Yet it would seem that an institution that can take 200,000,000 lives within a century hardly needs to be “replaced.”

Christians, and especially Americans, have long been misled about all this by their good fortune. Since the conversion of Rome, most Western rulers have been more or less inhibited by Christian morality (though, often enough, not so’s you’d notice), and even warfare became somewhat civilized for centuries; and this has bred the assumption that the state isn’t necessarily an evil at all. But as that morality loses its cultural grip, as it is rapidly doing, this confusion will dissipate. More and more we can expect the state to show its nature nakedly.

For me this is anything but a happy conclusion. I miss the serenity of believing I lived under a good government, wisely designed and benevolent in its operation. But, as St. Paul says, there comes a time to put away childish things.


See also, How To Vote For Liberty by Joe Sobran.

Joe Sobran is an author, syndicated columnist, and editor of a monthly newsletter, SOBRAN’S. See www.sobran.com for a free sample or call 800-513-5053.

This article is reprinted with permission. Read the article online at http://www.sobran.com/reluctant.shtml.

Copyright © 2004 by The Vere Company,
All rights reserved.

 

Voluntary Government as a Marketable Service: Reminiscences on the History of an Idea


By Alvin Lowi [1]

Back in 1954, when he was at the Foundation for Economic Education at Irvington-on-Hudson, New York, economist Baldy Harper called the idea of voluntary government a most radical one. [2] At that time, Harper said he could count on the fingers of one hand all the people he knew in the world who entertained the notion of a “total alternative” to tax-funded government. Spencer Heath, Spencer MacCallum, Robert LeFevre, and Murray Rothbard were the only ones who came to his mind. [3] Today, given the Internet, there are probably tens of thousands, maybe even millions, who entertain this notion, at least furtively. Yet, the history of the idea, its inception and spread, is sketchy and tentative.

My encounter with this idea began when my friend and colleague, Andrew J. Galambos, introduced me to Spencer Heath. [4] At the time, 1961, I was associated with Galambos and his Free Enterprise Institute. There, I was privileged to observe and participate in the development and exposition of such ideas. I had always known this was a unique opportunity, but until recently had not thought to memorialize the experience. I was prompted to do so when I recently discovered a reprint of J. Huston McCulloch’s 1977 translation from the French of a remarkable essay entitled THE PRODUCTION OF SECURITY. [5] I found the essay, written in 1849, a most compelling read in itself, and the inspiring introduction by Murray Rothbard made it virtually irresistible to put down. It brought to mind some of the experiences I had almost forgotten.

The author of the essay was an obscure laissez-faire economist from Belgium named Gustave de Molinari (1819-1912), a contemporary and intellectual kin of the better known French liberal political economist, Frederic Bastiat. Born in Belgium and educated there in the new academic field of economics, Molinari was associated with the French économistes, a group of laissez-faire liberals recognizable nowadays as a rare breed: pro-capitalist, non-political libertarians. Throughout his long life (he was 92 when he died), Molinari argued for peace, free trade, freedom of speech, freedom of association, and liberty in all its forms.

Molinari was unique among economists in his conviction that the economy did not need the slightest vestige of political protection, not even as represented by constitutionally limited, representative republican government. He was apparently the first person to realize that the market economy contained the means for its own protection and to advance a theory of a society entirely devoid of political regimentation, which is to say, a society without a state.

Molinari envisioned a stable and humane social paradigm. He took individual human liberty to the limit to see if it could stand on its own legs. Libertarians nowadays call this position individualist anarchy, market anarchism, or anarcho-capitalism. Society without political statecraft has also been referred to variously as economic government, voluntary government, or government via market-delivered property protection services.
The Free Enterprise Institute

My colleague Galambos came to think like Molinari about a century later . He did so apparently without a prompt from Molinari – but not without some prompting from his students. Even so, this was a remarkable transition for Galambos, who had no academic preparation in the humanities. He was an astronomer and astrophysicist who left the government-dominated defense industry in 1959, during the height of the Cold War, to return to academia to make the world safe for astrophysicists. In 1960, while still a tenured physics professor, he launched his campaign, “Capitalism, The Key to Survival.” This was a short-lived seminar at Whittier College where he taught, but it was soon transformed into a profit-seeking educational enterprise in Los Angeles under the banner of The Free Enterprise Institute (FEI) and continued for several decades. Galambos died in 1997 after a long illness. In 1999, some of his taped FEI lectures were transcribed and published in a volume entitled SIC ITUR AD ASTRA.

On founding FEI, Galambos embraced the limited government framework of classical liberalism. He was an enthusiastic promoter of the writings of Mises, Read, Hazlitt, Harper, Hayek, and Rothbard. In the early 1960s, he brought Read, Mises, and Harper to Southern California for well-attended seminars. Galambos was obsessed with American constitutionalism. He had a strong sentimental attachment to the American Revolution as fomented by Thomas Paine, which represented for him the break with old-world political despotism and elitism and especially the break-through in social technology that resulted, enabling the liberation and growth of humanity. He subscribed to the thesis of Alexis de Tocqueville and other admirers of this “American phenomenon.” [6]

Galambos approached the subject of government as an exercise in constitutionalism. This exercise he played as an intellectual game with organizational structures and political contrivances for limiting the scope of monopoly political government in keeping with the sentiments of the Declaration of Independence and other classical liberal arguments. However, no matter how liberal, creative, or ingenious were his schemes for controlling the political Leviathan, they were inevitably political and therefore authoritarian and collectivistic. The implications were not lost on Galambos’ students. And curiously, it was just such implications in Ayn Rand’s so-called “objective law,” republicanism, and Leonard Read’s libertarian GOVERNMENT: AN IDEAL CONCEPT, that later alienated Galambos from those otherwise congenial social movements. [7]

Galambos defended his approach to constitutional political government with the claim that adherence to scientific method could be relied upon to avert the usual political outcomes. The physicist cum economist would see to it, so he dreamed. He made the separation of economy and state a central feature of his scheme, which was an intriguing beginning. But the clincher would call for a lot more authentic social science not immediately in evidence and perhaps never forthcoming – at least to the extent that force could ever be justified.

Reading Molinari’s essay reminded me of the debates among Galambos’ students in those early days. Logical extrapolations of his teachings had begun to reveal inconsistencies in the classical liberal treatment of society in the tradition of John Locke, which called for a modicum of political government to maintain a legal framework of order based on private property protection. But such protection, predicated on a monopoly of institutionalized coercion, required an authority that was intrinsically superior to the market and the individual humans comprising it. More specifically, it called for a political state, a supernatural authority, which is alien to individual humans. The dilemma arose – how could mere humans delegate to a committee of other humans, authority they never possessed in the first place? In America, “The Constitution” replaced the king as the symbol of this supernatural authority, invoking as it did the myth of the omniscient and omnipotent majority.

About 1963, Robert LeFevre came onto the Free Enterprise Institute scene. His arguments reduced all political proceedings to absurdity. [8] They had been heard already by some of Galambos’ students who went to Colorado to attend LeFevre’s lectures at the Freedom School. Afterwards, these students introduced LeFevre’s arguments into the discussions at FEI class meetings. Galambos’ constitutionalism was severely tested.

But Galambos’ conception of government was fundamentally nothing more than the collection of services devoted to the protection of private property. [9] It should not have been such a huge leap of faith to dump the political paradigm altogether in favor of property protection services rendered volitionally for profit in the marketplace by competitive private enterprise, based on the authority of proprietorship. Yet, Galambos was not the first to leap. This idea began to catch on first among his students. The awakening began soon after the first offering of his Course 100 in which he had sanctioned limited political government. A sequence of discoveries occurred soon thereafter somewhat as follows.

Spencer Heath, author of CITADEL, MARKET AND ALTAR (1956) had already begun espousing government by proprietary administration, based on maintaining the integrity of private property by contract. His grandson, anthropologist Spencer Heath MacCallum gave a guest course for FEI in 1963 in which he introduced the idea of the proprietary community. [10] His approach followed the work of his grandfather, who would have presented the concept to Galambos’ students a year earlier but for the intervention of a health crisis that ended his long life. [11] MacCallum also introduced other provocative ideas of voluntary social organization to the FEI market, particularly those of E.C. Riegel, who suggested that laissez-faire competition in the marketplace is necessary and sufficient government. [12] Riegel was also the first to call for the complete separation of money and state and develop a concept of private enterprise money.[13]

In his FEI guest lectures that same year, F.A. Harper introduced Molinari’s vision of an unregimented society to Galambos’ market. He was able to offer the attendees of his seminar some rare copies of Molinari’s only book in English at the time, entitled SOCIETY OF TOMORROW. [14] Harper billed Molinari’s proposal as a “total alternative” to the status quo – an emergent “grand alternative” to political government.
The Insurance Industry

Out of this general exploration of the idea of a free market for government services there rapidly developed various private-enterprise extrapolations into community service and property protection. First, to my knowledge, was “the insurance industry as government” proposition of physicist-mathematician, entrepreneur-businessman and FEI contractor Piet (Peter) B. Bos. [15] Electrical engineer, entrepreneur, and FEI contractor Charles R. Estes next offered his vision of competing companies providing arbitration, dispute resolution, patrol, security technology, and bounty hunting services for fee or subscription. Estes also proposed various private-enterprise money and property restitution ventures. [16] Electrical engineer and FEI lecturer Richard A. Nesbit described a private-enterprise primary school system venture which he and several partners and their wives had set up in Southern California and were now operating as a business.

The following year, 1964, some FEI contractors teamed up with me and FEI to bring Robert LeFevre back to Los Angeles to give his freedom seminar. [17] By this time, many of Galambos’ students had already shunned political government, even as a transient lesser evil. Preferring to take their chances with self-government in the marketplace, they were enjoying a bonanza of leisure time liberated from the tedium of political participation in the Republican effort to elect Goldwater that year.

Galambos, himself, finally abandoned all political artifice. All constitutional games with incipient political despotism were demolished, as was any inclination to participate in politics. By the end of 1964, he was espousing purely free-market social organization in which government was defined as follows:
A government is a person or an organization that offers for sale products or services designed to protect property, to which the owner of that property may voluntarily subscribe. [18]
Galambos called attention to his use of the article “a” in this definition – “a” government, not “the” government, emphasizing the absence of monopoly as an essential attribute.

Then Galambos came out with his Course V-201 – “The Nature and Protection of Primary Property,” which he came to call his most important – out of the dozens developed in the years afterward. The course was controversial with existing students because of a new strict non-disclosure requirement. Here he brought out his concept of the pure contractual corporation operating a clearinghouse for businesses utilizing intellectual property for profit. This invention was to supersede coercive patent and copyright privileges issued by political governments, which his for-profit corporations would displace forever. In 2001, FEI contractor Robert Klassen published his treatise, ECONOMIC GOVERNMENT, showing in one of his chapters how Galambos’ royalty-clearinghouse business might be implemented with the aid of new computer technology. [19]

Up to the time of McCulloch’s translation of Molinari’s essay (1977), Galambos and Rothbard had been ideologically and intellectually congenial in most respects, but they became estranged over the fundamental question of politics and its place in the liberty movement. Their differences came into focus in the light of Molinari’s “two ways of considering society.” Molinari saw politics and society (force versus voluntary exchange) as worlds apart. That is where they belonged, according to Galambos, who was aligned on this point with his predecessor, Spencer Heath. [20] Galambos had developed similar notions to Heath’s non-political methodology in his business of promoting freedom. [21] Rothbard, on the contrary, had turned to politics for social salvation. He was influential in the formation of the Libertarian Party. [22].

While Rothbard and his libertarian colleagues were preoccupied with their political projects, Galambos was building a business developing ideological momentum for his non-political “natural republic” (a name which I had suggested). He described the “natural republic” as the societal condition comprised of voluntary entrepreneurial behavior based on economic and ethical knowledge developed via an authentic social science (dubbed “volitional science” by Jay S. Snelson, the Senior Lecturer at FEI for many years). Galambos believed his society of the future would be a technological achievement, one that would result in a wholly voluntary society in which every person would have 100% control over his or her own property, a condition which he defined as freedom.

Galambos envisioned society as an evolutionary process of voluntary human action developing entrepreneurially-delivered property protection services that would gradually supersede all coercive political institutions. The “natural republic” would be built in a step-by-step process according to a design rendered beforehand, much as an architect would build a skyscraper – an analogy Galambos attributed to his architect father, Joseph B. Galambos. [23] The builders of this social architecture would come to the task by way of an ideological program offered by the architect as a proprietary product, which as I have mentioned, Robert Klassen subsequently labeled “economic government.”

Although the nature of man and his government is a long-studied subject in the human curriculum, only a few original thinkers have contributed to Molinari’s blockbuster discovery that political government must be abandoned in favor of private enterprise property protection for a free society to prevail. Galambos was one of few thinkers who conceived of private, profit-seeking businesses providing comprehensive property protection services as the keystone of human society. His reliance on competitive private enterprise to deliver protective services – for a profit – is a monumental idea. While the practice is yet to come to fruition on a large scale, we now know that it is the only reliable method of obtaining property protection consistent with liberty. Since Galambos is no longer with us, it is up to us to pass along his ideas and manner of thinking to the next generation.

Readers of this article may be interested in this other historical essay dealing with related themes.
End Notes

[1] Alvin Lowi is a mechanical engineer and thermodynamicist in private practice in Rancho Palos Verdes, CA. This article was originally prepared in October 2014, and revised with help from Richard Boren and Carl Watner. Alvin Lowi has written many articles on free-market subjects. He was a friend, colleague, and business associate of Andrew J. Galambos for many years and lectured for Galambos’ Free Enterprise Institute in Los Angeles from 1961 to 1969. He taught Galambos’ original course “Capitalism, the Key to Survival” from 1961 through its final offering in 1965. That course was superseded by Galambos’ and Snelson’s more familiar Courses V-50 and V-201.
[2] F. A. “Baldy” Harper was professor of marketing at Cornell University and the first staff economist with the Foundation for Economic Education (FEE). He founded the Institute for Humane Studies, a community of libertarian scholars originally located in Menlo Park, California, now at George Mason University in Virginia.
[3] Spencer H. MacCallum, in a personal communication, wrote that he was present when Harper made this statement. Acknowledging the difficulty of tracing the propagation of ideas back to their source, Harper thought this perspective had come to him from a typescript of Heath’s CITADEL, MARKET AND ALTAR that John Chamberlain had sent him. He said the idea ruminated in his mind a full year before it became clearly planted. So the chain of custody may have been from Heath to Baldy and thence to LeFevre and Rothbard. Baldy suggested MacCallum ask Rothbard whether he thought the idea had come to him from Baldy, but MacCallum never did.
[4] Alvin Lowi, “The Legacy of Spencer Heath: A Former Student Remembers the Man and Offers Some Observations on the Scientific Orientation of His Work,” January 3, 2001. Available from alowi@earthlink.net.
[5] “Weekend Read, MisesDailyArticle.org, March 25, 2006. The complete essay in English is at http://mises.org/story/2088#6.
[6] Alexis de Tocqueville, DEMOCRACY IN AMERICA, Vintage Books, 1945.
[7] Leonard Read, GOVERNMENT – AN IDEAL CONCEPT, New York: The Foundation for Economic Education, 1954.
[8] Robert LeFevre, “Must We Depend on Political Protection? – ‘Yes,’ Edmund A. Opitz; ‘No,’ Robert LeFevre,” STUDIES IN HUMAN ACTION, Vol. II, No, 1, Colorado Springs: The Freedom School, Pine Tree Press, 1962.
[9] Andrew J. Galambos, SIC ITUR AD ASTRA, San Diego, CA: Universal Scientific Publishing Co., 1999, p. 29. See http://www.amazon.com/Sic-Itur-Ad-Astra-Volition/dp/0880780045/sr=1-2/qid=1160671190/ref=pd_bbs_2/102-3770766-9772913?ie=UTF8&s=books.
[10] Spencer H. MacCallum, THE ART OF COMMUNITY, Menlo Park, CA: Institute for Humane Studies, 1970.
[11] Spencer Heath, CITADEL, MARKET AND ALTAR, Baltimore: Science of Society Foundation, 1956.
[12] E.C. Riegel, THE NEW APPROACH TO FREEDOM, San Pedro, CA: Heather Foundation, 1976.
[13] E.C. Riegel, FLIGHT FROM INFLATION: THE MONETARY ALTERNATIVE, Los Angeles: Heather Foundation, 1978.
[14] Gustave de Molinari, THE SOCIETY OF TOMORROW, London: T. Fisher Unwin, 1904.
[15] Peter B. Bos, “The Societal Implications of Risk Sharing,” Draft of December 20, 1998. Available from Pbbos@aol.com.
[16] Charles R. Estes, VOLUNTARY EXCHANGE: KEYSTONE OF CIVILIZATION, San Diego, CA: Mary L. Estes, 1997.
[17] Robert LeFevre, “The Thinking Man’s Guide to Politics” Seminar, Los Angeles: Free Enterprise Institute, May 2, 1964.
[18] Galambos, op. cit, p. 138.
[19] Robert Klassen, ECONOMIC GOVERNMENT, San Jose: WRITERS CLUB PRESS, 2001.
[20] Spencer Heath, POLITICS VERSUS PROPRIETORSHIP, Self-published 1936. Available from Spencer H. MacCallum, sm@look.net. Heath was a lecturer at the Henry George School under the direction of Frank Chodorov in New York City at this time.
[21] Galambos actually launched his freedom business out of a licensed securities and insurance business, Universal Shares, Ltd., from which he sold mutual fund shares and insurance policies as a means of making money while selling laissez-faire capitalism along with personal property and financial security.
[22] J. Michael Oliver and Donald C. Stone, “Exclusive Interview with Murray Rothbard,” http://www.lewrockwell.com/rothbard/rothbard103.html. Originally published in The NEW BANNER: A FORTNIGHTLY LIBERTARIAN JOURNAL, February 25, 1972, Columbia, SC: New Banner Institute.
[23] Suzanne Galambos, MORE LASTING THAN BRONZE, Coronado, CA: Universal Scientific Publishing Co., 1991.

Two Kinds of Protection by Robert Lefevre


Two Kinds of Protection by Robert Lefevre[Editor’s Note: The following two editorials ( Two Kinds of Protection by Robert Lefevre ) appeared in the Colorado Springs GAZETTE-TELEGRAPH, page 11, on September 6, 1957. They were penned by Robert Lefevre. Although Gustave de Molinari’s article in 1849, “The Production of Security,” is probably the earliest description of competing defense agencies providing protective services, these sister editorials may be the earliest expression of the idea that free market insurance companies could be the major providers of defense services in a stateless society.]

 

Two Kinds of Protection by Robert Lefevre

Protection is one of man’s basic requirements. From earliest days man has been interested in preparing against assault, whether the attack he anticipated might come from weather, beasts or other men. Man’s ability to protect himself against any and all of his enemies is responsible for his survival.

At best, this is an unfriendly world, and one must prepare in peace and calm for the storm and strife which surely will come.

In very ancient times men turned for their protection to the strong. They looked about for a bandit chieftain, mighty and resourceful, on whom they could depend for safety. They knew when they did so, that the bandit was a villain. But they hoped, by paying him in taxes or in tribute, to make him their villain. It was wise, men reasoned, to have a powerful and unscrupulous leader on their side. Such a leader could be counted on, they felt, to offset the fury of some other bandit leader against whom they would be powerless.

The search for protection among the ranks of the bandit chiefs provided men with government. And so long as a particular bandit remained loyal to his own people, men felt secure. They reasoned that it was better to pay a known and limited amount of plunder to their own bandit chieftain than to be compelled in suddenness to surrender everything they had in the dark of night to some other bandit not in their own pay.

The trouble has always been that a bandit is still a bandit, however he is paid. And bandits, like their fellows, are ambitious. Hence, with dreadful regularity, bandit leaders turn upon their own people time after time. They become dissatisfied with the tribute rendered to them voluntarily for protection. They begin by raising the amounts of that tribute according to their own selfish desires of supremacy and vainglory. They end by preying upon their own supporters in a manner not unlike the conduct of the very bandits they have been hired to combat.

When such a practice rises to its zenith, the people who pay become dissatisfied. They deem it disastrous to keep a particular bandit in power. They look back upon the good old days when their particular bandit was tractable and satisfied with smaller sums. And in the end they change their patronage.

Which is to say that by elections or revolutions they overwhelm the bandit chief of the moment to replace him by another bandit chief who gives promise of more moderate ways. But moderation is not a strong point with bandits. And so the endless story is repeated, over and over again. People rise up and do away with one particular bandit, and fly to the arms of another for protection.

Such changes in the long run provide little in the way of actual change. Only the names are different. The practice of banditry is still the general rule. And it should be noted that this reliance upon banditry is a reliance upon physical force and violence, however friendly such force and violence can be made to appear at a given moment.

In relatively recent years, a new mode of protection has made its appearance, in the market place. Foregoing force and violence, the insurance idea was born. It was and is the contention of insurance experts, that men can secure protection by translating the protection desired into terms of money. Insurance men know that people cannot be protected against the inevitable. Fire, flood, storm, drought, accident and even death are always with us. The insurance idea is that the possible amount of damage can be calculated in advance in terms of money. The person desiring insurance can pay to the insuror a sum of money which in toto will be but a fraction of the loss he might experience if one of these dread enemies should strike. Then, altho he is still subject to disaster, he can indemnify himself against the frightful financial loss such disaster might represent.

This is a free market idea. The growth of insurance companies since the first marine coverage to the present time, is ample evidence that the idea of protection is marketable on a voluntary basis. Unlike the bandit chieftains, the insuror does not make his coverage mandatory. He indemnifies only those who patronize him. Those who wish to be covered, pay in advance. Those who do not wish to be covered, pay nothing.

But there is a notable difference in the manner in which each of these protection agencies functions. Surpluses collected by bandit chiefs are spent in a vast and lordly fashion on all sorts of silly and irresponsible projects. Surpluses collected by insurors are invested in free enterprise, thus enhancing the market place, increasing financial responsibility and otherwise strengthening freedom and voluntarism. The bandit chiefs still rely on force. The insurors rely upon arithmetic and logic and use no force. Yet, both sell protection. To us the voluntarism of insurance is vastly superior to any kind of banditry.

Superior Protection

In the preceding editorial we have discussed two types of protection: that provided by bandits who make their protection mandatory once they have been hired and that provided by insurance companies which use voluntary, free market practices and protect only those who wish to be protected. And we have commented that to us the voluntarism of the insurance idea is superior to the involuntarism of banditry.

We might also show that with the passing of the last half century, the bandit idea, while sustained in most minds, has resulted in a mammoth debt of such magnitude that serious students are wondering if the sum can ever be repaid, whereas the insurance idea, while not universally adopted has resulted in such surplus that insurance companies are now among the largest repositories of funds throughout the world. Bandits, relying on physical force, have constantly betrayed their own payees. Insurors, relying on nothing but honesty and the voluntary way, have met their obligations cheerfully and promptly. This provides. a curious contrast.

It is clear that insurance is a successful and worthy enterprise. Grave questions have still to be answered as to the success and the worth of universal plunder even when such plundering is sponsored by our political friends.

So, in very recent times, the bandits have recognized the value of the insurance idea. And, having recognized it, they have turned to it to practice it. But in so turning they have retained their basic character. Thus nowadays, certain of our group of world bandits have sought to employ the insurance idea as their own. But they cannot rid themselves of the curse of compulsion. Thus, when our own group of political thugs undertook the largest and most expansive program of insurance in world history ­ the Social Security scheme ­ they brought to it their own ideas of banditry and made Social Security a matter of compulsion. Most were not asked if they wanted such government insurance. Instead, at the point of the tax gun, they were compelled to take it. And the money collected by our bandits was used just as any other money they collected. It was poured into any number of the numerous rat holes of political expediency maintained by the bureaucracy of banditry, so that our bandit insurance is naturally dependent upon its income from banditry and not at all upon its investments, which are nil.

Thus we see that a merger of an insurance idea with banditry is of little merit. But such a merger gives rise to the thought that it might be possible for the insurance idea, maintained without banditry, to be expanded into the areas now presumably protected by bandits. In other words, might we not ask if it is not possible that some of the vaunted protection we are still paying for from bandits could not be purchased in a voluntary manner from insurors?

If protection against fire, flood, accident and death can be purchased by those who wish such protection; why cannot those who wish it, purchase protection from the thief, the liar and the cheat? Perhaps, if we put our minds to it, we might even devise a type of protection which could be purchased from an insuror against banditry itself. Here is a thought to conjure with.

Perhaps it would not be so difficult an accomplishment as it now seems. If the protection furnished us by our bandit friends were to be placed on a voluntary basis, with each person paying for exactly the type and amount of such protection he deemed useful and wise, then the insurance idea would have, in large measure, supplanted the bandit idea. And what would be wrong with that?

It seems to us that civilization itself is voluntary association. Barbarism is involuntary association. Civilization begins with the first voluntary action. If it ends, it will end with the last voluntary action. And if we wish civilization to expand as well as continue had we not best be advised to study ways and means of supplanting compulsion with voluntarism?

Perhaps there are areas of protection open to us thru voluntary means which we as yet have not explored. Surely, it would pay us to commence the exploration. In the end, if necessary, we can always go back to the bandits. Why not try a superior way first? You know, it might work.

-End (Two Kinds of Protection by Robert Lefevre)

Insurance Companies as Competing Governments: Whose Idea Was It?


By Richard Boren

The article ( Insurance Companies as Competing Governments: Whose Idea Was It? ) below was first published in Issue 167, 4th Quarter, 2015.

[Editor’s Note: As some of you may know, I operate a small retail tire store and auto service center. Several problems in the store involve questions regarding the sale of used tires and the proper way to repair punctured tires. If a customer brings in a tire with plenty of tread, but which was manufactured ten years ago, is it safe to install? Should a tire be ‘plugged’ from the outside or must it be inspected and repaired from the inside? These are questions the tire industry is struggling to answer. Many leading tire associations look to the federal and/or state governments to offer legislative and regulatory solutions. When I suggested to the editor of a tire magazine that the insurance companies should set these standards, he responded: “Where did you ever get that idea from?” Well, I got it from several decades of studying and thinking about voluntaryist solutions to societal problems.

In a state-free market economy it would only be natural for insurance companies to establish safety and procedural standards for those that they insure. Among other things they would probably fund organizations like Underwriters Laboratory and Consumers’ Union to test products and to establish minimum requirements for obtaining insurance. Thus, rather than the state dictating the rules regarding tire aging, tire repair, (and thousands of other standards, such as the way to store explosive fertilizers or the use of seat belts and air bags in autos), it would be the insurers of these products and procedures that would be responsible. After all, they would have a large amount at stake should an insurable event occur and cause them a loss.

In a voluntaryist world, by definition, all products and services would be provided via private, voluntary action. Gustave de Molinari (1819-1912) was probably the first person to envision the role that private defense and protection agencies might play in a state-free world. (See his 1849 monograph, THE PRODUCTION OF SECURITY, partially reprinted in Issue 35 of THE VOLUNTARYIST.) However, Molinari made no mention of the role of insurance. That idea appears to have first been expressed more than 100 years later by someone else, as will be described below.

When I received a copy of an email from subscriber Richard Boren in September 2014, I had already been thinking about the pivotal role that defense and insurance companies would play in a state-free society. Richard had written that email to Hans-Hermann Hoppe, the author of a book, DEMOCRACY, THE GOD THAT FAILED, he had recently read. That book, first published in 2001, placed heavy emphasis on the role of insurance companies in a free society. In it Hoppe gave credit to Morris and Linda Tannehill for their “brilliant insights and analysis” in that regard, as expressed in their 1970 book, THE MARKET FOR LIBERTY. The purpose of Boren’s email to Hoppe was to suggest that perhaps the Tannehills were not the true source of the ideas he so greatly admired. I suggested to Richard that he write an article on the history of the insurance concept, and he offered me the following.]

I first heard the idea that insurance companies would play an important role in a state-free society in 1975, while taking Course V-50 at the Free Enterprise Institute (FEI). The concept had been taught there for over 10 years, which is to say about five years before the Tannehills published their book. My instructor was Senior Lecturer Jay Stuart Snelson (1936-2011). He did a superb job of teaching concepts innovated by Andrew J. Galambos (1924-1997) and others in what was labeled the Science of Volition. Galambos had founded the Institute, a profit-seeking venture, in the early 1960s. I was so taken by what I learned there that I took classes continually for four years, all but the first taught personally by Galambos. FEI operated under Galambos’ direct management until the mid-1980s when he was sidelined by Alzheimer’s disease.

Prior to reading Hoppe’s book, I had never heard of the Tannehills but was inspired to purchase their book. What they had written about insurance companies sounded a lot like what I had learned from Galambos. I tried to find out more about the authors but hit a dead end. I could find no mention of them anywhere, other than references to their book. It didn’t appear that they had written anything before THE MARKET FOR LIBERTY, or anything since. Apparently the book was quite successful in libertarian circles when it first came out. I asked myself, “Who comes out of nowhere, writes a well-received book, and then disappears?” The answer, as far as I know, is pretty much limited to J.D. Salinger and Harper Lee. I began to suspect that the Tannehills might not have existed, and were the pennames of someone else. However, thanks to the help of Brian Doherty of REASON, I learned that the Tannehills were real, as evidenced by an interview with Linda Tannehill in the March 1991 issue of LIBERTY MAGAZINE. But still, their appearance out of nowhere to write a book of great substance, including the blockbuster insurance idea, was suspicious. Who in that position doesn’t remain active on the scene? Was the work really theirs?

In the “Acknowledgments” section of their book, the Tannehills expressed gratitude to “Skye d’Aureous” and “Natalee Hall.” I learned that these were the pseudonyms of Durk Pearson and Sandy Shaw. I knew these names because of their prominence in the health-food, life-extension book and lecture business.

And then I learned something else. In the late 1960s, immediately preceding the 1970 publication of the Tannehill’s book, Mr. Pearson was a student of Andrew J. Galambos. In fact, Pearson was described as a “precocious” student by Alvin Lowi, Jr., who had close business and personal ties to both Galambos and Pearson.

The insurance-as-government concept was central to the state-free society that Galambos wanted to develop. He lectured for hours on how to build such a society, and Pearson could not have been a Galambos student, let alone a precocious one, without learning about the central role of insurance. Could it be that Pearson gave those ideas to the Tannehills?

Galambos recorded all of his lectures on audiotape, and made the recordings available to new students so that he wouldn’t have to deliver the same course over and over. He gave Course V-50 for the last time in 1968. After that, new students either heard that recording or attended the live presentations by Jay Snelson, as I did. Galambos also promised to write a book containing the ideas of V-50 and of a more advanced course, V-201, but never did. However, he pre-sold the book to a number of students (I am one of them) and promised that in the event of his death or other inability to write, his trustees would publish a transcript of his lectures to satisfy the book obligation. Galambos died in 1997 (after many non-productive years due to his disease) and in 1999 his trustees published Volume One of his book, consisting of a lightly edited transcription of the 1968 rendering of Course V-50. These are the ideas that Durk Pearson would have heard in person.

Galambos was an excellent lecturer, seemingly speaking without notes. V-50 was a 16 session course, with each session lasting about three hours. Anyone who can hold an audience’s attention for that long must have been doing something right. Nevertheless, a transcription is not as good as a carefully written book, but it had to do. The transcription of V-50 was released as an 800+ page book titled SIC ITUR AD ASTRA (This is the Way to the Stars). The title reflected astrophysicist Galambos’ desire to be involved in proprietary space travel. He would quip that he was “trying to make the world safe for astrophysicists.”

Galambos, in endeavoring to create a bona fide science of volition, insisted on developing and using a precise, uniform vocabulary. In the same way that physicists have standard, universally-used terms such as “mass” and “energy,” Galambos developed precise definitions of such words as “freedom” and “property.” He distinguished between “state” and “government” and gave credit to Albert Jay Nock and his book, OUR ENEMY THE STATE, for sensitizing him to that distinction. Galambos defined “state” as “any organized coercion which has general accreditation and respectability by the people; a monopoly of crime.” Then, rather than abandoning the word “government” in favor of something with no negative connotation, he attempted to rehabilitate it by defining it as “a person or organization which offers services or products for sale for the purpose of protecting property, to which owners of property may voluntarily subscribe.” He said, “Please note the indefinite article: ‘a’ government, not ‘the’ government. It’s not a monopoly. It is not unique.” He counted lock makers and fence makers and private detective agencies as government. But, he added, “… the highest form of government available in this world is the insurance company. If all else fails, and you do lose your property, they’ll pay you the financial value for which you have insured it, and that is a government service.”

He called insurance “one of the great inventions of all time. It compares in importance with the invention of the wheel.” In his book, over 7,000 words are devoted to the concept of insurance companies providing services traditionally assigned to government. Galambos pointed out that an insurance company has a proprietary interest in its customers’ well-being, meaning that a customer’s loss would be the insurance company’s loss. The insurance company was a “totally impersonal organization operated by total strangers” but highly motivated to prevent the loss in the first place, and, in the case where there was a loss, to apprehend the person responsible and recover that loss.

In explaining this to students, Galambos emphasized that under the state the highly regulated insurance industry offers nothing like what it would in a state-free society. The service provided by insurance companies competing in a voluntary society would be vastly better than under state supervision. Many more insurance options would be available, and most people would insure a wide variety of things, out of habit, without thinking much about it.

As a requirement of attending classes at FEI, Galambos required students to sign a non-disclosure agreement. This policy has been attacked by some of his detractors – people who never took a course from him. I will not discuss it here other than to say that the point was to help ensure proper use and dissemination of knowledge, not to suppress it. Durk Pearson would have had to have signed such an agreement, and would have been in violation of it if he had disclosed the insurance concepts to the Tannehills without Galambos’ permission. Although the evidence is circumstantial, and I am speculating, I suspect that this is what happened. Galambos would never have given permission for anyone to publish his ideas before he had done so himself. So, since Pearson couldn’t legitimately write about the ideas, he used a pseudonym and gave them to the previously and subsequently unremarkable Tannehills.

Carl Watner reports having correspondence with Morris Tannehill in 1969, a period when Tannehill must have been thinking about and even writing the book, but there was no mention of insurance. It’s hard to imagine someone coming up with a big idea like that and not mentioning it, especially since Watner was not yet convinced of the state-free solution, and the idea goes a long way toward making that feasible. Once someone hears the idea and “gets it,” it is a fairly mechanical process to think of numerous applications. Readers of the Tannehills’ book will see that, as will those who are fortunate to read Galambos.

But where did Galambos get the insurance idea? I always assumed it was his, but came to learn that was not the case. As a working astrophysicist, in the early 1960’s he began giving freedom-oriented lectures to his colleagues and his following grew. One way of reaching students with his original course, Course 100, was to have his friend and colleague Alvin Lowi, Jr. listen to each session, take notes, and then deliver that session to another group a week later. In one of those other groups was Peter B. Bos, an MIT aeronautical engineering graduate with a blossoming interest in libertarian issues.

According to Bos, he never took a course from Galambos, his exposure coming through Lowi. Like every person considering the idea of limiting or even eliminating the state, he had the usual questions about how the state’s putative function of the protection of life and property would be performed. At some point he had the insight that there was no need to invent something new because the answer already existed in a well-established, well-capitalized industry: insurance. For anyone who has ever tackled any project, there’s nothing better than realizing that the thing needed to solve a problem already exists and can be taken off the shelf and used. It was a “Eureka!” moment for Bos.

Bos realized that when it came to protecting your life and property, there would be no better ally than someone who would suffer a loss if you suffered a loss. Bos saw that insurance companies had a proprietary interest in your well-being – something the state does not. In fact the state does not even have a legal responsibility to keep you safe. However, if you are insured, then your insurance company must pay you if you come to harm. Therefore, the insurance company, in its own interest, has a motivation to keep you from having a loss of life or property in order to keep itself from suffering a monetary loss. There are many things an insurance company might do in this regard including, but not limited to, the production of physical defense. To Bos, the insurance company was the ideal replacement for the state because it has an incentive to do the things that make up the main reason for the state’s existence – the protection of life and property, but which the state routinely doesn’t deliver.

As witnessed by Lowi, Bos presented this idea at the 1963 FEI Alumni Meeting with Galambos in attendance. Galambos, who was in the middle of his own fundamental shift from promoting a society with a limited state to one that was state-free, soon incorporated the insurance idea into what became Course V-50. Perhaps fortuitously, Galambos himself was licensed to sell insurance and investments, and did so, but gave up that business to devote full time to FEI. He went on to develop Course V-30, Investments and Insurance, in which fundamental concepts were brilliantly explained. Galambos clearly had a deep understanding of insurance. However, the idea that competing insurance companies could and should take the place of the state came from Bos. But Galambos never gave Bos credit for the idea, and it was not until 2008 that Bos learned that Galambos had used it. Bos has written a book, THE ROAD TO FREEDOM (which should be available by early 2015), that incorporates his ideas for building a free world, and naturally insurance plays the role he envisioned.

Galambos’ failure to give credit to Bos has not been explained. Not to have done so was a violation of the very things he taught. An answer might lie in his recordings and papers from that era, should they ever become available for study. As it is, however, the trustees of Galambos’ estate have withdrawn SIC ITUR AD ASTRA from sale. They have also refused to fulfill the rest of the book contract by publishing the transcript of what Galambos called his most important course, V-201, The Nature and Protection of Primary [Intellectual] Property and delivering it to those who paid for it. However, the most important material is gradually being revealed at capitalismtheliberalrevolution.com, created by Frederic G. Marks, Galambos’ onetime attorney and confidante. I highly recommend it.

So, did the insurance-as-government idea originate with Peter Bos, then flow to Galambos, to Pearson, and then to the Tannehills, with the latter getting the credit? Among other things, Galambos acknowledged that ideas could be independently discovered, and in course V-201 he proposed a number of tests for independency. It was one of those tests – whether the person claiming independent discovery had a track record in the subject area – that caused me to look into the Tannehills. In fairness, they didn’t explicitly claim independency, but neither did they cite an antecedent, so the inference was that their book offered new ideas, and that’s how it was accepted by the esteemed Dr. Hoppe. It’s likely that we’ll never know, but absent evidence to the contrary I’ll credit Peter Bos who, by disclosing the idea in 1963, appears to have been first.

Addendum (August 1, 2016)

This is a retyping by Richard Boren of Peter (Piet) Bos’ 1962 paper, “Some Ideas on the Proprietary Management of Government.” The original was labeled “rough draft” by the author, and was retyped for the purpose of incorporating his handwritten edits, some of which are quite faint in the original.

The text reveals that Bos is not a native English speaker. Born in the Netherlands, as a young boy he suffered greatly during the Nazi occupation, seeing firsthand the evils of a totalitarian state. After the war an American family sponsored his immigration to the United States, leading to a degree in aeronautical engineering from MIT, and a successful business career.

In this draft his repeated use of the word “objective” may show the influence of his primary philosophical inspiration, the work of Ayn Rand. The influence of Galambos is clearly seen in his use of Galambos’ definition of property. Neither man had yet broken free of the idea that there must be a state (Rand never did) and both of them were at that time trying to find ways to limit the state’s coercive power.

In this document we see Bos’ early formulation of the idea that the insurance industry, already established and financially strong, could perform the fundamental function of government—property protection—even on a national scale. Bos disclosed this idea, which perhaps had evolved by then, to Galambos in 1963 during a Galambos alumni meeting. It later became part of Galambos’ recipe for a fully privatized society, but without credit to Bos, giving the impression that Galambos had violated his own teachings about primary property. However, Galambos was licensed to sell securities and insurance and even taught a deeply insightful course on the subjects. It is not known whether Galambos got the idea of applying insurance on a grand scale from Bos, developed it independently, or whether both men deserve the credit. Absent additional evidence, we cannot know.

In this paper Bos discusses the role of insurance companies in national defense while overseen by the state to prevent them from initiating coercion. Galambos took things one critical step further by eliminating the state. He redefined “government” as “any person or organization which offers services or products for the purpose of protecting property, to which the owners of property may voluntarily subscribe.” He identified insurance companies as the organizations best-positioned to do this, as competing “governments.”

Bos knew Galambos only slightly and never took a class from him, hearing his ideas in lectures given by their mutual colleague Alvin Lowi, Jr. Bos was never a Galambosian, preferring instead the ideas of Rand and her disciple Nathaniel Branden, and it wasn’t until 2008 that Bos learned the role that insurance played in Galambos’ teachings. Bos had found his own path to the belief that society should be state-free, and reveals his prescription for accomplishing that in his 2015 book, The Road to Freedom and the Demise of Nation States.


(Rough draft) 10 – 18 – 62 Piet B. Bos

SOME IDEAS ON PROPRIETARY MANAGEMENT OF GOVERNMENT

The concept of taxation as a revenue collecting method for financing of Government (State) has always contributed to the decay of many known civilizations due to the inherent evils of such a concept. Taxation in all cases amounts to non-objective coercive confiscation of private property and regardless of the methods of the taxation selected, always consistently penalizes the most productive individuals. Therefore, a concept of financing and operation of Government consisted with the market operation in a laissez-faire society is a very important consideration in the establishment of an enduring society.

Government in a moral society has as its only function the protection of private property of the individuals comprising this society. As such, the only monetary requirement for government consists of the financing of the apparatus for the protection of private property. The protection of property can be broken down into local protection and protection on a national level from infringement by other countries which is known as national defense. Examples of protection on the local level are the courts, police and fire departments, etc. The question amounts to how to finance these services in a non-coercive objective manner consistent with the market operation. It is obvious that a system is desirable in which each individual (or corporations) pays an amount proportional to the services received by him, but this immediately poses another question – how to evaluate the amount of services rendered to each individual.

Arbitrarily designating a service charge amounts to some individual (Bureaucrat) defining the amount of services rendered to individuals (or corporations) which directly makes this system of financing nonobjective. Only the individual (or corporation) in question can objectively evaluate his own private property (his life and the non-procreative derivatives thereof), and consequently the individual’s own estimate of the amount of property to be protected will be required to objectively compute the service charge for the protection of this property. However, to rely on an honor system in obtaining this information would result in sacrificing the responsible individuals to the irresponsible ones. Furthermore, there would be no reliable indicator as to the total amount of protection required and, therefore, what the total expenses and protection (Government budget) ought to be. Again arbitrary bureaucratic (nonproprietary) decisions would dictate the total amount to be collected without the benefit of a built-in yardstick such as is present in the market operation due to the profit incentive. Fortunately, in a free enterprise society there are in existence interested organizations other than the property owners themselves with regard to property and its protection. These organizations are the insurance companies.

To protect property from disaster, etc., individuals (or corporations) resort to insurance programs which basically are voluntary risk sharing programs. The corporations who make insurance their business determine the cost of such policies on the basis of risk using statistical methods. These risks are computed on a continuous basis to ensure that the business remains profitable and competitive. To ensure his property, an individual (or corporation) must objectively evaluate the value of his life and property on a continuous basis to ensure himself against possible losses. Since risk and insurance depends directly on the amount of protection provided for the property to be insured, there is an optimum market solution of the amount of protection provided and the required total cost for providing this protection plus the cost of the insurance policies themselves. Therefore, the obvious solution is to have insurance companies finance the protection of property provided, the cost of which would be part of the insurance policy cost. The insurance companies in order to hold down the cost of operation would continually optimize the amount of protection provided with the lowest possible insurance rate. If, for example, in the case of fire protection (the financing for which could be collected from real estate insurance policies, etc.) the amount of protection is inadequate, the claims for fire damage would increase resulting in great expense to the insurance companies. This would force the management to increase the fire protection in the particular area such as to minimize total cost. If the fire protection is excessive, fire insurance would be very high resulting in loss of business directly due to the higher prices and indirectly by competition. This would force the management to reduce expenses which is only possible by reducing the amount of protection provided. This balance would be continually reviewed such that the insurance company can provide the best possible service at the lowest possible cost resulting in an optimum solution between the amount of protection and the cost thereof. Protection of property thus is provided on the proprietary management which ensures maximum efficiency resulting in minimum cost for these services. On a local level the insurance companies would provide this protection under contract with companies in the business of providing police, fire, etc. protection. The latter companies again have proprietary interests against ensuring maximum efficiency and lowest possible cost due to competition.

Some concept of separation of power may be necessary even at the local level to ensure that insurance companies will not be able to utilize the intended retaliation coercive power for protection of property for immoral purposes (for example veto power over the selection of the protection service maintained by the individuals seeking the protection in that particular area).

To provide for protection of property on a national level this idea would be equally adequate. To make this possible, protection from war disasters such as nuclear attack, must be included as part of the insurance coverage in return for national defense financing provided by the insurance companies. Necessary proprietary management decisions are required of the insurance companies with regard to the amount of financing for the national defense such that in the case of external danger, the defense will be adequate to offset the claims to property damage (property including life). Again, we find an optimum balance between national defense expenditures and cost of insurance policies. Since we are again relying on proprietary management decisions which are reviewed continually to ensure this proper balance, the total amount required for national defense will be much lower than the amount presently scheduled. In addition, the cost for national defense will continually decrease due to two basic reasons: (a) by virtue of the laissez-faire capitalistic society out-producing all of the collectivist societies by a very large margin the threat of these nations is continually lessened; (b) the unit cost of insurance will continually decrease by virtue of the fact that property is created at a very fast rate in a laissez-faire capitalistic society. This increased amount of property will require insurance itself, resulting in a lower unit cost of insurance for a given total cost of national defense.

The national defense, even though financed by the insurance companies, is the responsibility of the federal Government, which in turn is subject to constitutional law in a moral society with the consequent separation of power inherent in such a Government thus eliminating initiating coercion by the insurance companies.

The defense contracting will be performed on the basis of maximum protection for minimum cost. This would reestablish the defense industry subject to the free market profit and loss system, eliminating such abhorrent concepts of cost-plus-fixed-fee (in other words, the larger the cost the larger the fee). This will reduce the cost of national defense by very large amounts and will also eliminate political favoritism (government subsidies, awards of contracts, etc.) to any one company. The defense companies themselves will be required to work under maximum efficiency due to the competitive market. This will require continuous review of management and personnel efficiency as well as production costs. This in turn will direct the defense industry to peaceful, profitable business endeavors in the astronautics field which will result in a great reduction of system cost. New ideas will evolve in much greater succession in the effort to cut down on the system cost, establishing a very creative atmosphere for profitable space exploration.

In summary, the advantages of this proprietary management operation of government with regard to revenue collection are: (1) the amount of protection and, therefore the cost thereof, determined by proprietary decisions subject to the laws of the market such as to establish an optimum balance between protection provided and cost of protection; (2) the method of financing accomplished on a voluntary basis stimulated by self interest for protection of property; (3) the amount of services received objectively evaluated by the individual himself subject to no coercion; (4) proprietary management decision in the execution of the protection of property; (5) continual review of the balance between the amount of protection and the cost of protection.

Readers of this article may be interested in this other historical essay dealing with related themes.

[Editor’s Note: The following two editorials appeared in the Colorado Springs GAZETTE-TELEGRAPH, page 11, on September 6, 1957. They were penned by Robert Lefevre. Although Gustave de Molinari’s article in 1849, “The Production of Security,” is probably the earliest description of competing defense agencies providing protective services, these sister editorials may be the earliest expression of the idea that free market insurance companies could be the major providers of defense services in a stateless society.]

Two Kinds of Protection

Protection is one of man’s basic requirements. From earliest days man has been interested in preparing against assault, whether the attack he anticipated might come from weather, beasts or other men. Man’s ability to protect himself against any and all of his enemies is responsible for his survival.

At best, this is an unfriendly world, and one must prepare in peace and calm for the storm and strife which surely will come.

In very ancient times men turned for their protection to the strong. They looked about for a bandit chieftain, mighty and resourceful, on whom they could depend for safety. They knew when they did so, that the bandit was a villain. But they hoped, by paying him in taxes or in tribute, to make him their villain. It was wise, men reasoned, to have a powerful and unscrupulous leader on their side. Such a leader could be counted on, they felt, to offset the fury of some other bandit leader against whom they would be powerless.

The search for protection among the ranks of the bandit chiefs provided men with government. And so long as a particular bandit remained loyal to his own people, men felt secure. They reasoned that it was better to pay a known and limited amount of plunder to their own bandit chieftain than to be compelled in suddenness to surrender everything they had in the dark of night to some other bandit not in their own pay.

The trouble has always been that a bandit is still a bandit, however he is paid. And bandits, like their fellows, are ambitious. Hence, with dreadful regularity, bandit leaders turn upon their own people time after time. They become dissatisfied with the tribute rendered to them voluntarily for protection. They begin by raising the amounts of that tribute according to their own selfish desires of supremacy and vainglory. They end by preying upon their own supporters in a manner not unlike the conduct of the very bandits they have been hired to combat.

When such a practice rises to its zenith, the people who pay become dissatisfied. They deem it disastrous to keep a particular bandit in power. They look back upon the good old days when their particular bandit was tractable and satisfied with smaller sums. And in the end they change their patronage.

Which is to say that by elections or revolutions they overwhelm the bandit chief of the moment to replace him by another bandit chief who gives promise of more moderate ways. But moderation is not a strong point with bandits. And so the endless story is repeated, over and over again. People rise up and do away with one particular bandit, and fly to the arms of another for protection.

Such changes in the long run provide little in the way of actual change. Only the names are different. The practice of banditry is still the general rule. And it should be noted that this reliance upon banditry is a reliance upon physical force and violence, however friendly such force and violence can be made to appear at a given moment.

In relatively recent years, a new mode of protection has made its appearance, in the market place. Foregoing force and violence, the insurance idea was born. It was and is the contention of insurance experts, that men can secure protection by translating the protection desired into terms of money. Insurance men know that people cannot be protected against the inevitable. Fire, flood, storm, drought, accident and even death are always with us. The insurance idea is that the possible amount of damage can be calculated in advance in terms of money. The person desiring insurance can pay to the insuror a sum of money which in toto will be but a fraction of the loss he might experience if one of these dread enemies should strike. Then, altho he is still subject to disaster, he can indemnify himself against the frightful financial loss such disaster might represent.

This is a free market idea. The growth of insurance companies since the first marine coverage to the present time, is ample evidence that the idea of protection is marketable on a voluntary basis. Unlike the bandit chieftains, the insuror does not make his coverage mandatory. He indemnifies only those who patronize him. Those who wish to be covered, pay in advance. Those who do not wish to be covered, pay nothing.

But there is a notable difference in the manner in which each of these protection agencies functions. Surpluses collected by bandit chiefs are spent in a vast and lordly fashion on all sorts of silly and irresponsible projects. Surpluses collected by insurors are invested in free enterprise, thus enhancing the market place, increasing financial responsibility and otherwise strengthening freedom and voluntarism. The bandit chiefs still rely on force. The insurors rely upon arithmetic and logic and use no force. Yet, both sell protection. To us the voluntarism of insurance is vastly superior to any kind of banditry.

Superior Protection

In the preceding editorial we have discussed two types of protection: that provided by bandits who make their protection mandatory once they have been hired and that provided by insurance companies which use voluntary, free market practices and protect only those who wish to be protected. And we have commented that to us the voluntarism of the insurance idea is superior to the involuntarism of banditry.

We might also show that with the passing of the last half century, the bandit idea, while sustained in most minds, has resulted in a mammoth debt of such magnitude that serious students are wondering if the sum can ever be repaid, whereas the insurance idea, while not universally adopted has resulted in such surplus that insurance companies are now among the largest repositories of funds throughout the world. Bandits, relying on physical force, have constantly betrayed their own payees. Insurors, relying on nothing but honesty and the voluntary way, have met their obligations cheerfully and promptly. This provides. a curious contrast.

It is clear that insurance is a successful and worthy enterprise. Grave questions have still to be answered as to the success and the worth of universal plunder even when such plundering is sponsored by our political friends.

So, in very recent times, the bandits have recognized the value of the insurance idea. And, having recognized it, they have turned to it to practice it. But in so turning they have retained their basic character. Thus nowadays, certain of our group of world bandits have sought to employ the insurance idea as their own. But they cannot rid themselves of the curse of compulsion. Thus, when our own group of political thugs undertook the largest and most expansive program of insurance in world history ­ the Social Security scheme ­ they brought to it their own ideas of banditry and made Social Security a matter of compulsion. Most were not asked if they wanted such government insurance. Instead, at the point of the tax gun, they were compelled to take it. And the money collected by our bandits was used just as any other money they collected. It was poured into any number of the numerous rat holes of political expediency maintained by the bureaucracy of banditry, so that our bandit insurance is naturally dependent upon its income from banditry and not at all upon its investments, which are nil.

Thus we see that a merger of an insurance idea with banditry is of little merit. But such a merger gives rise to the thought that it might be possible for the insurance idea, maintained without banditry, to be expanded into the areas now presumably protected by bandits. In other words, might we not ask if it is not possible that some of the vaunted protection we are still paying for from bandits could not be purchased in a voluntary manner from insurors?

If protection against fire, flood, accident and death can be purchased by those who wish such protection; why cannot those who wish it, purchase protection from the thief, the liar and the cheat? Perhaps, if we put our minds to it, we might even devise a type of protection which could be purchased from an insuror against banditry itself. Here is a thought to conjure with.

Perhaps it would not be so difficult an accomplishment as it now seems. If the protection furnished us by our bandit friends were to be placed on a voluntary basis, with each person paying for exactly the type and amount of such protection he deemed useful and wise, then the insurance idea would have, in large measure, supplanted the bandit idea. And what would be wrong with that?

It seems to us that civilization itself is voluntary association. Barbarism is involuntary association. Civilization begins with the first voluntary action. If it ends, it will end with the last voluntary action. And if we wish civilization to expand as well as continue had we not best be advised to study ways and means of supplanting compulsion with voluntarism?

Perhaps there are areas of protection open to us thru voluntary means which we as yet have not explored. Surely, it would pay us to commence the exploration. In the end, if necessary, wInsurance Companies as Competing Governments: Whose Idea Was It?e can always go back to the bandits. Why not try a superior way first? You know, it might work.

-End ( Insurance Companies as Competing Governments: Whose Idea Was It? )

Sophisticated Slavery


By Marco den Ouden

[Editor’s Note: This article won the grand prize in The Voluntaryist essay contest on how best to explain that taxation is theft.]

 

 

One of the by-products of the American Civil War was the abolition of slavery. Well, sort of!

The Civil War resulted in the elimination of formal slavery. However, it did not get rid of essential slavery. What does this mean? Let’s go back to pre-Civil War America to find out.

The Southern U.S. states were not sophisticated slave states. Slaves were held as chattel. The plantation owner literally “owned” his slaves. They were his property. He kept them and cared for them just as he kept and cared for cattle and other domestic livestock. He housed them, fed them and clothed them, and, of course, he made them work for him. If they did not suit him, he sold them.

But suppose slavery was not abolished in the 19th Century, but rather it evolved into a more sophisticated system. How might it have changed? First a slave owner might have thought, “Hey, what if I can get the benefit of slave labor without the exorbitant cost of feeding, clothing and sheltering them?” Some slave owner may have taken the first path to sophistication by paying his slaves a nominal wage (less than it cost to keep them on the plantation) and told them, “I’m going to start paying you for your work but you must go and find your own food and shelter. You are free to go about your own business except that you must come to the plantation to work every day. After all, I still own you.”

Other slave owners notice he’s saving a bundle on costs and also adopt the practice. Soon the entire society has adopted this new mode of slavery.

The slaves have so much free time on their hands that some start moonlighting. While it’s still nickel and dimes, the slave owners look the other way. But after a while they notice something quite unexpected. The slaves are not the stupid, backward people they thought they were. Some used their spare time to get educated and now earn as much, if not more, off the plantation as on.

A very sophisticated slave owner puts two and two together. “My slaves can generate more wealth on their own time than working for me,” he reasons. “Why don’t I give them complete freedom to choose their own line of work and develop wealth in their own way. Instead of having them work on the plantation, which would under-utilize their skills, I’ll let them do what they are best suited for in the marketplace. I’ll hire some poor white trash and slaves who can’t find other work for the fields. And as for my slaves, they will give me 50% of all they earn. After all, I still own them.”

If the slave owner is really sophisticated, he will notice that skills and aptitudes vary greatly among his slaves. The unskilled ones will not be able to survive on the small remuneration he pays for farm work. The original concept was to save on the costs of feeding, clothing, and sheltering his slaves by paying them and letting them fend for themselves. He decides that he will not demand any tribute from slaves who can do little besides farm work. He decides to graduate the tribute demanded according to how much the slave earns. The more they earn, the greater the percentage they pay to the slave owner. He carefully crafts the rates of tribute so the slaves still have an incentive to better themselves and earn more. He calls this sliding scale a “progressive” tribute system.

Soon other slave owners follow suit and the slave society reaches its ultimate level of sophistication. The slaves are formally free to do what they want to do. Formal slavery has been abolished. But essentially, they are still slaves. They must pay a tribute based on their earnings to their masters. The essence of slavery is working for the benefit of others rather than yourself, not by choice (as in supporting your family or giving to charity) but by force. To paraphrase Frederick Douglas, who escaped from slavery in 1838, a slave is someone who “toils so that another may reap the fruit.”

The American Civil War resulted in the end of formal slavery. But it did not end essential slavery. In fact, over the years, essential slavery has expanded to include not just former slaves, but everyone. And everyone is a partial slave owner as well. We have, to paraphrase Abraham Lincoln, a system of slavery “of the people, by the people and for the people.” The instrument of its implementation is the income tax!

Until we abolish coercive taxation, the forced taking of the fruits of the labor of those who have earned it for the benefit of those who have not, we will not have abolished the essence of slavery. Until we see the rise of another great emancipator who can educate the world to the evil of slavery down to its essential core, we will not be a truly free people!

[This article originally appeared at About.com on April 13, 1998. It can also be found at Towards a Tax Free Canada.]

Soul Rape


by Carl Watner

The modern nation-state is predicated upon exercising control over a certain geographical territory, and depends on revenues which it generates by means of threats and/or compulsion. The English colonists, when they emigrated to New England in the early 17th Century, replicated much of the political and religious environment they had left behind. Every newborn was a British citizen, a loyal subject of the King and local colonial government; everyone was considered to be by birth a member of the local Congregational church; most white males were subject to militia duty and had to pay taxes for the support of the government and church in the parish in which they lived.

Dissenters and nonconformists, like the Baptists and Quakers who chose not to support the colonial religious establishment, founded their own churches, designated their own ministers, and paid them directly (if they were paid at all). Their refusal to sanction the Congregational establishment led to fines, confiscations of property, and often imprisonment. Many were so stubborn that “they refused to let anyone pay their taxes for them. They preferred to prove their loyalty to their principles by going to jail.” One elderly Baptist widow, Esther White, spent thirteen months in jail “because she would not pay the eight-penny tax levied on her.” [1] These resisters were not tax dodgers or cheats. They could not honestly support or attend the services of a religion they did not believe in. “Going to prison [wa]s a hard way to avoid paying taxes,” and they often complained that “the worst part of going to jail for refusing to pay their religious taxes was the ungodly company they had to associate with there.” [2]

Their opponents in the Congregational establishment shared “a universal assumption that the stability of the social order and the safety of the state demanded the religious solidarity of all people in one church.” [3] “The safety and welfare of [the] community rested on the morality and virtue of its citizens: Christianity was the best system of morality and religion ever revealed to man; therefore, the [community] should, for its own good and the good of its people, use its taxing power to see that the Christian religion was supported and promulgated.” [4]

The Congregationalists of New England believed that separation of church and state and religious voluntaryism would be unworkable. Men were too depraved to voluntarily support the proper number of churches and ministers. “In their view a good society justified taxes for support of religion just as it did for support of law, courts, highways, and public schools.” [5] They believed that “churches were necessary to give consolation to the grieving, moral order to the common people, and the fear of God to potential lawbreakers. … They did not trust the common man to support religion voluntarily … because ‘history taught’ that human nature is always guided more by self-interest, passion, and lust for power than by benevolence, charity and generosity. ‘The first want of man,’ John Adams said, ‘is his dinner, the second, his girl’.” The “most important check on human depravity was” the required preachings of “morality, piety, and fear of God taught in the churches” every Sunday. [6]

The analogy between the monopolistic religious establishment and the monopolistic political establishment was a well-recognized argument used against the dissenters. “Where would society be if everyone who disliked a law refused to obey it?” [7] The question of taxation to support religion was compared to taxation to support roads, courts, and police. All were “essential to the general welfare.” [8] Religion was so important “to the safety and well-being of society that no state could exist without it.” [9] As Chief Justice Theophilus Parsons of the Massachusetts Supreme Court wrote in 1810, “the distinction between liberty of conscience and worship and the right of appropriating money is material; the former is inalienable, the latter is surrendered as the price of protection” [10] Freedom of conscience was quite distinct from the power to raise money for a public purpose. The argument in favor of exempting “a dissenter from his parish taxes ‘seems to mistake a man’s money for his conscience.’ A contribution to the support of the regular churches, Parsons reasoned, was a contribution to the welfare of the state, and a man had no more right to be exempt from supporting a church he could not attend than to be free from school taxes because he had no children.” [11] Religious taxes, like other taxes required for the support of government, were part of the necessary cost of maintaining a government that provided protection to life, liberty, and property. [12]

Defenders of religious freedom, such as Roger Williams and Thomas Jefferson, thought differently. Henry Robinson, a contemporary of Roger Williams, compared the freedom to choose one’s religion to the freedom to engage in work of one’s own choosing. If the government could not designate what sort of work you should choose, why should it have the right to designate what religion you chose to follow? [13] Williams repeatedly used the terms “soul rape,” “soul killing,” and “soul oppression” to illustrate his belief “that being forced to affirm” or being forced to pay for something that “you do not believe can harm the soul” by weakening and deforming it. [14] This “occurs when people are forced … to give assent to orthodoxies they don’t support.” [15] In her book, LIBERTY 0F CONSCIENCE, Martha Nussbaum discusses Williams’ views on conscience and notes that he defined conscience as a “holy Light,” a “most precious and invaluable Jewel.” It is the essence of a person. Williams thought that “damage to conscience is an intrinsic wrong, a horrible desecration of what is most precious about a human life.” Williams describes “Soul killing” as “the chiefest murder,” and “soule or spirituall Rape” [sic] as being more abominable in the eyes of God than forcing and ravishing “the Bodies of all the Women in the World,” or of blowing up Parliament or cutting the throats of kings or emperors. [16] Jefferson used the words “spiritual tyranny” to describe the violation of a person’s conscience. [17] When he drafted the Virginia Statute for Religious Freedom in 1777, he wrote that “…to compel a man to furnish contributions of money for the propagation of opinions which he disbelieves and abhors, is sinful and tyrannical; that even forcing him to support this or that teacher of his own religious persuasion is depriving him of …liberty … .” [18]

Although Williams, and Jefferson, and members of the Baptists and other dissenting sects saw “religious taxation” as “a crime against God” and a violation of one’s religious scruples, none of them ever questioned the propriety of taxation as it applied to the secular realm. [19] They did not see that if it was wrong to force a man to pay for a minister whose service he did not attend, then (by the same reasoning) it would be wrong to force a man to pay for a teacher that did not teach his children. None of them ever attacked church rates as a violation of property rights or as a confiscation of private property. To have done so would have called into question the propriety of all taxation. None of them saw taxation as a violation of the commandment prohibiting theft. What they objected to was the violation of conscience, not realizing that one’s property and conscience were intimately connected. Taxation, in their mind, was okay as long as it was used for a purpose which they approved. It was proper to them to force someone to pay for schools or roads. They saw the provision of roads, and schools, and public order as being essential to human welfare, but they did not realize that these necessary goods and services could be supplied, voluntarily, by entities other than the government. They did not see the connection between the natural right to choose one’s religion and the natural right to make uncoerced choices in all other spheres of human activity. [20]

Today, voluntaryists are forced to support a political establishment, much like the dissenters of several centuries ago were forced to support a religious establishment. Even if one does not accept the claim that society could exist without the state, one ought to see that taxation, whether for religious or political purposes, is a violation of the conscience and property rights of those who oppose the initiatory use of force in human affairs. It is soul rape to be forced to sign a government tax form when one disbelieves in political government. It is soul rape to be forced to use government identification and a government passport for travel. It is soul rape to be forced to contribute to a political institution that one opposes in conscience. To paraphrase Jefferson, it is sinful and tyrannical to be forced to pay for and participate in something that one does not believe in. It is slavery to have all or part of your life controlled by others against your will. It is just as wrong to have your property stolen from you, for whatever the alleged purpose, as it is to be forced to attend a church, whose teachings you do not believe in; or to support a preacher with whom you disagree.

“The right to seek the truth in one’s own way is one of the most important and necessary responsibilities of life.” [21] As Williams would have said, to destroy this right is to destroy the soul because one is being forced to do something that one would not have willingly chosen to do. The way a man chooses to spend his money is a reflection of his personality and his conscience. To coerce a man into paying money for something he does not want or does not agree with is to demand that he surrender his property and his conscience. The common thief says, “Your money or your life.” The government says, “Surrender your money and your conscience, or we will put you in jail.” The voluntaryist is one of the few that sees these demands as equally unjust. Whether emanating from the thief or from the government, such a demand is robbery plain and simple. To describe taxation as soul rape, soul oppression, and soul killing is to seek to delegitimize the State, and to take a step toward the withdrawal of the cooperation and tacit consent on which it ultimately depends.

Footnotes
[1] William G. McLoughlin, SOUL LIBERTY: THE BAPTISTS’ STRUGGLE IN NEW ENGLAND, 1630-1833, Hanover: Brown University Press, 1991, pp. 170 and 8-9.
[2] ibid., p. 176 and William G. McLoughlin, NEW ENGLAND DISSENT 1630-1833, Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971, 2 vols., p. 756.
[3] Winfred E. Garrison, “Characteristics of American Organized Religion,” 25 THE ANNALS OF THE AMERICAN ACADEMY (1948), pp. 14-24 at p. 16.
[4] McCloughlin, SOUL LIBERTY, op. cit., pp. 175 and 202.
[5] ibid., p. 231.
[6] ibid., pp. 231 and 294.
[7] ibid., p. 170.
[8] McLoughlin, NEW ENGLAND DISSENT, p. 610.
[9] ibid., p. 594.
[10] ibid., p. 611 (italics in the original), as summarized by Nathan Dane in his abridgement of Barnes vs. Falmouth.
[11] John D. Cushing, “Notes on Disestablishment in Massachusetts, 1780-1833,” THE WILLIAM AND MARY QUARTERLY, Third Series, Vol. 26, No. 2 (April 1969), pp. 169-190 at p. 184.
[12] McLoughlin, NEW ENGLAND DISSENT, p. 611.
[13] Carl Watner, “‘For Conscience’s Sake’: Voluntaryism and Religious Freedom, in Carl Watner, editor, I MUST SPEAK OUT, San Francisco: Fox & Wilkes, 1999, pp. 404-414 at p. 408. This article originally appeared in THE VOLUNTARYIST No. 55, April 1992. Both versions are available online at https://voluntaryist.com/voluntaryist.pdf and https://voluntaryist.com/backissues/055.pdf.
[14] Martha C. Nussbaum, LIBERTY OF CONSCIENCE, New York: Basic Books, 2008, p. 54.
[15] Martha Nussbaum, “Veiled Threats,” THE NEW YORK TIMES “Opinionator,” July 11, 2010 at http://opinionator.blogs.nytimes.com/2010/07/11/veiled-threats/?page wanted=print at paragraph 3. Accessed June 12, 2013.
[16] Nussbaum LIBERTY OF CONSCIENCE, pp. 54-55. Also see Perry Miller, ROGER WILLIAMS: HIS CONTRIBUTION TO THE AMERICAN TRADITION, Indianapolis: The Bobbs-Merrill Company, Inc., 1953, pp. 127 and 264 (footnote 10).
[17] Thomas S. Kidd, GOD OF LIBERTY: A RELIGIOUS HISTORY OF THE AMERICAN REVOLUTION, New York: Basic Books, 2010, p. 54.
[18] See Wikipedia entry, “Virginia Statute for Religious Freedom,” paragraphs 5 and 6 of the actual text.
[19] McLoughlin, NEW ENGLAND DISSENT, p. 611.
[20] For more on this general theme, see Watner, op. cit.
[21] ibid., p. 409

“You’re Not My Master; I’m Not Your Slave”: Voluntaryism and the Story of Absolutist Objectors


By Carl Watner

The Voluntaryist Statement of Purpose concludes by advocating the withdrawal of the cooperation and tacit consent on which State power ultimately depends. This conclusion, in turn, rests on the voluntaryist insight: the understanding that all government is necessarily grounded upon general popular acceptance. In short, the majority of the people themselves, for whatever reasons, acquiesce to the demands of their government. All governments depend upon the cooperation and compliance of those over whom they rule. Governments require the sanction of their victims.

What if instead of complying with the law government agents are trying to enforce, a person asks, “What is the punishment for refusing to comply, for refusing to do what you say?” [1] What if the citizen says, “No!”? How does a free man react to those who might imprison him for failing to follow government rules? What does he say? How does he act toward his would be enslavers?

In his essay on how he became a voluntaryist, Peter Ragnar observed that he became a voluntaryist the day that he fully realized that no one could force him to do anything he chose not to do. To illustrate his point, he recited the confrontation between Alexander the Great and an old Indian sage, as Alexander’s army was about to cross the Ganges River. “Alexander questioned the sage about what to expect after he crossed the river.” When he was told that his army would be defeated, Alexander threatened to decapitate the sage for his insolence. The sage was unmoved, replying Alexander could watch his head fall. Then he, the sage, would be dead.” [2] This spirit of voluntaryist resistance has been repeated many times. William Grampp in Volume I of his book on the history of economics tells the story of an ancient Stoic “who was captured and told to renounce his beliefs. He refused and was tortured. Still unable to make him recant, his captors told him he would be put to death. He answered that they could do whatever they wanted with his body, but whatever they did, they could not injure his philosophy, which was in his mind. Their authority, in its physical and moral aspect, did not extend [that far].” [3]

What these anecdotes describe is the idea that while “physical freedom can be curtailed by force,” one’s voluntary acquiescence can never be coerced. One might be killed, but one can never be forced against one’s will. [4] This lesson is repeated over and over again as one reviews the histories of conscientious objectors to conscription and war. Peter Brock, in his book LIBERTY OF CONSCIENCE, cites many such instances. Jonathan Whipple (1794-1875) was an 18 year old carpenter and member of the Rogerene religious sect from Mystic, Connecticut. During the War of 1812, he refused to perform any military duties or pay any fines. As he related in his diary, “Of course they could imprison me, or do what they would. But they could not make me do what I thought wrong, and wicked.”

Tilghman Vestal was a Quaker conscientious objector during the Civil War. Some time after November 1863, he was court-martialed by the Confederate army “and sentenced to be punished until he would bear arms.” He was repeatedly beaten, abused, knocked down, and then stabbed numerous times with a bayonet for his refusal to obey orders to fight. Tilghman remained calm throughout his ordeal, and told his tormentors “that he was a Christian and could not fight.” Once when arguing whether his position was sustained by the Scriptures, an army chaplain told Vestal that he “wouldn’t give a cent for a religion that [wa]s opposed to his country.” Vestal replied that “I wouldn’t give a cent for a country that is opposed to my religion.” Tilghman was sent to brigade headquarters , and “every effort was made to induce him to go and perform the duties of a solider, but he was firm and as inflexible as the everlasting hills. He was told that if he persisted in his course he would be subjected to severe punishment, and would finally be shot for disobedience to orders. He replied that they had the power to kill him, but neither the Federal nor the Confederate army possessed the power to force him to abandon his principles or prove false to his religion.” [5]

Another Civil War objector was William Hackett, a North Carolina farmer who was conscripted into the Confederate army in June 1863. “He was then 36 years old. He refused to bear arms and refused to purchase exemption, although he could have afforded to do so.” The officer to whom he reported told him that if he did not comply with orders he would be shot. “I told him I would not take gun nor march in the drill, so he said, ‘Which will you choose, to be shot in the evening or in the morning?’ I told him I should choose neither, … . He said he had full power, without permission, to kill me if I did not comply. I told him that I did not deny that he had, so far as the power of man extended, but that there was a power above man’s, and he could not remove a hair of my head without my Heavenly Father’s notice.” The next day, June 24, 1863, Hackett was ordered to fall in line with his company to drill. He refused. As he relates, “They tried to make me, and I sat down on the ground. They reminded me of the orders to shoot me, but I told them my God said to fear them not that kill the body, but are not able to kill the soul; … .” A firing squad was then formed and ordered to “Load; Present Arms; Aim.” The guns were pointed at Hackett, who then raised his arms and prayed, “Father, forgive them; they know not what they do.” Not a shot was fired. The men of the firing squad lowered their rifles “without orders, and some of the men were heard to say that they ‘could not shoot such a man.’ The order was then given, ‘Ground arms’.” [6]

One of the best-known stories of conscientious objectors during World War I involves two Hutterite brothers, Joseph and Michael Hofer, of South Dakota. They were court-martialed for refusing to put on military uniforms and obey orders. Sent to a prison on Alcatraz Island in California, they “were stripped to their underwear and thrown into the dungeon where there were no sanitary facilities and sea water oozed across the bare floor on which they had to sleep. Given only a little water each day, they were manacled standing with their hands high above their heads so that their feet barely touched the floor. Beside them on the floor were soldier uniforms and they were promised relief if they would put them on and agree to obey. They persisted; and the authorities could not continue their brutality. When the Hutterites emerged from the hole their arms were hideously swollen and they were scurvy-ridden and insect-torn. Then they were transferred to Fort Leavenworth, Kansas, where they again refused to wear the army uniform and to work; they were confined in solitary. In two days, Joseph Hofer was taken to [the] hospital and died of pneumonia; Michael followed Joseph a few days later. Joseph’s body was returned to the Hutterite community dressed in the military uniform which [he] had resisted to the point of death.” [7]

During World War II, there were a number of conscientious objectors who took what they described as an absolutist position against war and conscription. The consistent absolutists refused to cooperate in any way, shape, or form with the American government or its representatives. Corbett Bishop (1906-1961) was one of the most famous non-cooperators. His story is related in the book CONSCRIPTION OF CONSCIENCE by Sibley and Jacob in their chapter “Certain Absolutists.“ Bishop registered as a religious objector under the Selective Service Act and “was inducted into the Patapsco, Maryland Friends Civilian Public Service camp on March 19, 1942.” When he realized that he would not be allowed a furlough to wind down his business affairs, and when he saw that he would be forced to work without pay, he began to fast in protest. This was on June 26, 1942. “Day after day the fast dragged on, Bishop continuing to work on the camp kitchen crew for three weeks, despite increasing physical weakness. At length he was admitted to the infirmary [and] listed as ‘Sick in Quarters.’ Five weeks of fasting had now elapsed.” [8] On August 3rd, Selective Service ordered him to report for work on the camp project, but due to his condition his crew leader listed him as unfit for work. He was persuaded to end his hunger strike on August 7th, after forty-four days of continuous fasting. The camp director took him to a Baltimore hospital where he recovered his strength.

At the end of August 1942, he was transferred to the CPS camp at West Campton, New Hampshire. There he “began the practice of attacking at mealtimes the ‘slavery’ of Civilian Public Service.” He objected to the futile work done in the camps, and he “quoted from religious leaders like E. Stanley Jones: ‘Let anyone be saturated with the thought of the Sermon on the Mount and he will not only not try to argue a man into slavery, but he will not rest until every man is free, including himself’.” [9] By June 1943, he had reached the conclusion that the American Friends Service Committee was conspiring with the US government to enslave him and others. At this point, the Friends Service Committee wanted nothing more to do with Bishop, and turned him back over to Selective Service, which assigned him to a government camp at Mancos, Colorado on July 7, 1943. Later he was transferred to another government camp at Germfask, Michigan, where “he took furlough days which he had accumulated.” He resolved not to return to camp voluntarily.

When he was arrested on September 9, 1944, “he announced that his spirit was free and that if the arresting officers desired his body, they would have to take it without any [as]sistance on his part. Transferred to the Milan, Michigan, federal prison to await trial, he refused to eat, stand up, or dress himself. The slightest degree of ‘servility’ or seeming acquiescence in his captivity would, he maintained, compromise his case.” He was being force fed by the end of October, by having a tube pushed up through his nose. On December 6 he was brought before federal Judge Fred M. Raymond in Grand Rapids, MI. Bishop admitted that he had refused to return to camp, “but pleaded that the whole system of alternative service was unconstitutional” and violated his moral rights as a free man. [10]

He was told to appear in court on January 17, 1945, but he ignored this order. A new court date was set for January 25th. Again he refused. He was finally arrested by three FBI agents, when they appeared at his rooming house in Philadelphia, PA on February 20, 1945. He refused to cooperate with them. Encountering his passive resistance, they dragged him from the house and drove him to the Federal Court House, where “they had to carry his limp form into the building, deposit it in the elevator, and carry it into the room of the United States Commissioner.” There was no response when Bishop’s name was called. Finally he responded “I am here — in body only. … I am not going to cooperate in any way, shape or form. I was carried in here. If you hold me, you’ll have to carry me out. War is wrong. I don’t want any part of it.” [11]

Bishop was taken to Moyamensing prison where he continued his passive resistance and his refusal to feed himself. Again, prison officials resorted to forced feeding. On February 26, 1945, he was carried back into the Philadelphia court room of Federal Judge George A Welsh. “When the judge asked whether he opposed his removal to Michigan for trial, he opened his eyes and replied: ‘What you do with me is your own responsibility’. On March 15 he was returned to Grand Rapids, still maintaining his passive resistance and still being forcibly fed. He was sentenced to four years in prison and fined one thousand dollars. Returned to prison as a sentenced offender, he continued his strike and complete non-cooperation.” He was still being tube fed and was becoming weaker. Finally federal officials granted him a parole with the condition that he work on the Morris Mitchell co-operative farm in Macedonia, GA. “Actually, however, Bishop had signed no papers, made no promises, and regarded himself as absolutely free. Upon release he brought to an end his passive resistance, which had lasted for the almost incredible period of 144 days. During that time he had done nothing to assist prison officials, even to the extent of walking or rising from his cot,” eating, or using the prison toilet facilities. [12]

In September 1945, FBI agents found him in Berea, OH where they arrested him, once again, for violating his parole. He was not supposed to leave Georgia without government permission. When asked whether he was ready to come along with them “he gave what was by now the expected reply – that he would not cooperate in any way with the government’s restraint of his body. Hearing this, the agents picked up his suddenly limp body” and drove him to the Milan, Michigan prison. There the old story repeated itself. He resumed his fasting and non-cooperation; he was force fed and again lost weight and was weakened. Finally, the Department of Justice decided that there was no point to his continued incarceration. The publicity his case was generating was negative and the war was over. He was again paroled on March 12, 1946, and again, there were no conditions, and Bishop signed no papers. [13]

“Bishop had fasted 426 days since entering prison. [He] followed, to its logical conclusion, the proposition that man should not, in any way, cooperate with the State in the waging of war, and that persons who by reason of religious training and belief are opposed thereto should not be imprisoned.” [14] The most important idea in his philosophy was the distinction between the soul and the body. “Corbett Bishop as a person was found entirely in the soul. The government could gain complete control over the body that was known as Corbett Bishop, but couldn’t control his soul, which was the real Corbett. As soon as the government began to coerce him, he responded with non-cooperation, leaving responsibility for the ‘body’ in the hands of the government.” [15] He wouldn’t do anything: eat, walk, or go to the bathroom. Bishop realized that governments can “terrorize individuals into submitting to tyranny by grabbing the body as hostage, and thus destroying the spirit. His body was taken by the American despots to conquer his spirit. They might have his body as hostage, but as long as they have it, he repudiate[d] the body, and w[ould] have nothing to do with it. Thus his spirit remain[ed] free.” [16]

Other conscientious objectors have recognized this, too. Henri Perrin was a French Roman Catholic priest imprisoned by the Germans during World War II. In his autobiography he noted that the Nazis “could keep me locked up; they could take me to a concentration camp tomorrow, they could torture me and make me cry out with pain, but they could never touch the sanctuary where my soul watched, where I alone was master. They might deceive me, abuse me, weaken me; they might get words out of me which they could take as an admission; they could kill me. But they could never force my will, for it could never belong to them; it was between myself and God, and no one else could ever touch it.” [17]

So what does all this mean for voluntaryists, who object not only to State wars but to the very institution of the State itself? It inclines them toward thinking that total, absolute non-cooperation with one’s oppressors is the most potent method ever devised to counter the State. The State is not my master; I am not its slave. It does not own my body or my soul, and while I sometimes cannot prevent it from kidnapping my body, I can always counter its attempts to control my soul. As Peter Ragnar put it: “physical freedom can be curtailed by force, but coercion can never buy willing acquiescence. … You can chop people’s fingers off so they can’t write. Then you will have to cut out their tongues so they can’t speak. But ultimately you will have to cauterize their brains so they cannot think.” Or as William Glasser wrote in his book, CHOICE THEORY, “In practice, if we are willing to suffer the alternative – almost always severe punishment or death – no one can make us do anything we don’t want to do.” [18]

“Only those who know for sure what [is] essential and what [is] ephemeral in themselves and in life” can resist in this fashion. [19] Other objectors have noted that “My will power is stronger than the bayonet, and my ideas will not be shot out of my head.” [20] Another recognized that “The power of fearlessness is astonishing. They could threaten me with anything at all and not get me, because I wasn’t afraid. This was immensely liberating to me. I could be the person I was without fearing them. They had no power over me.” [21] Or as the horse might say, if he could speak: you can take me to water, but you can’t make me drink.

Footnotes
[1] This approach, of asking those who claim authority, “what is the punishment for violating this rule, so that I may decide whether to follow it or not,” was suggested by Dave Scotese, voluntaryist webmaster.
[2] Peter Ragnar, “So, What Is It About ‘No’ That You Don’t Understand … ?” THE VOLUNTARYIST, Whole No. 125, 2nd Quarter 2005, pp. 7.
[3] William Grampp, ECONOMIC LIBERALISM, (Vol. 1: “The Beginnings”), New York: Random House, 1965, pp. 11 and 26, cited in Carl Watner, “The Voluntaryist Spirit,” THE VOLUNTARYIST, Whole No. 124, 1st Quarter 2005, p. 7.
[4] Peter Ragnar, op. cit.
[5] Peter Brock, LIBERTY OF CONSCIENCE: A DOCUMENTARY HISTORY OF THE EXPERIENCES OF CONSCIENTIOUS OBJECTORS IN AMERICA THROUGH THE CIVIL WAR, New York: Oxford University Press, 2002. For Whipple, mentioned in the previous paragraph, see pp. 78, 91; for Tilghman (this paragraph) see pp. 160-163.
[6] Geoffrey Bould, CONSCIENCE BE MY GUIDE: AN ANTHOLOGY OF PRISON WRITINGS, London: Zed Books, Ltd., 1991, pp. 59-60.
[7] Yuichi Moroi, ETHICS OF CONVICTION AND CIVIC RESPONSIBILITY: CONSCIENTIOUS WAR RESISTERS IN AMERICA DURING THE WORLD WARS, Lanham: University Press of America, 2208, p. 121.
[8] Mulford Q. Sibley and Philip E. Jacob, CONSCRIPTION OF CONSCIENCE: THE AMERICAN STATE AND THE CONSCIENTIOUS OBJECTOR, 1940-1947, Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1952, p. 402.
[9] ibid., pp. 402-403.
[10] ibid., p. 405.
[11] ibid., p. 406.
[12] ibid., pp. 407-408.
[13] ibid., p. 409.
[14] ibid.
[15] Letter from Brad Lyttle to Carl Watner, June 20, 1986.
[16] Julius Eichel, ed., THE ABSOLUTIST, OFFICIAL ORGAN OF THE ABSOLUTIST WAR OBJECTORS ASSOCIATION, Volume III, No. 4, May 22, 1945, p. 2.
[17] Bould, op. cit., pp. 127-128.
[18] William Glasser, CHOICE THEORY: A NEW PSYCHOLOGY OF PERSONAL FREEDOM, New York: Harper Collins Publisher, 1998, p. 332.
[19] Bruno Bettelheim, THE INFORMED HEART, New York: The Free Press, 1960, p. 281.
[20] Moroi, op. cit., p. 120.
[21] Bould, op. cit., p. 234.

The Problem with Trading


By Dave Scotese

The problem with trading is theft. If you find an object that is common, which can be easily replaced with something else if you lose the one you found, like a rock, for example, or a stick, it isn’t worth much. However, if you put some work into it, perhaps sharpening the end of the stick to a point, or breaking the rock to create a sharp cutting edge, then it becomes a bit more valuable. As you put more work into making your found object into something useful, you will develop a feeling of ownership. If it is destroyed or taken from you, you will feel sad at the loss even though you can easily find another such object and work on it to make it as useful as the previous one.

This object, then, is something that I will call your “property” because you put your work into it to make it useful to you. If it is also useful to me, perhaps as something to dangle from a string around my neck to make myself attractive, or from my earlobe, or perhaps as a tool to cut parts of plants that I like to eat, then I might offer you something I consider as my own “property” in trade. You may refuse to give me the one you have, but offer to make another one for me, to trade for the thing I have. If and when we both feel that we are getting more out of our proposed trade than we are giving up, we will make the trade.

Multiply this by six or seven billion and you have the economy of today’s Earth. However, there are some important deviations from this pattern.

One such important deviation is the introduction of coercion. If we have agreed to meet at a certain place and trade our property with each other (say I’ll give you a sharp stick, and you’ll give me a sharp rock), it might happen that someone else wants your rock. They may approach us where we meet and threaten to injure one or both of us if we don’t hand over the rock. At this point, it doesn’t matter whether you have my stick, or I have my stick, the fact is that this third party is committing theft. If you disagree with this use of the word theft, substitute in some other word to characterize what the third party is doing. I will use the word theft.

There are a number of alterations to this scenario which do not affect the nature of the thief’s act. First, let us agree that what you’re bringing is not a rock but some money. When a thief steals, it is still theft no matter what he steals, as long as there is a natural presumption that it is owned by someone else.

Next, let us agree that the thief can make all manner of promises about how he will use the proceeds of the theft without changing the nature of his act. Keeping one’s promises does not affect the nature of one’s previous criminal act. While it can be a way to mitigate its negative effects, a crime has nevertheless been committed and the criminal is guilty of it. When the promises are made as a part of the crime, they serve to make the crime more insidious.

Let us now agree that the thief can represent a group of people who have decided that your money will help them accomplish some kind of goal, whether or not it’s a goal with which you agree. Whether or not this is theft still depends on your ability to control what happens. If the representative explains that your unwillingness to contribute will cause them to take part of your pay from your employer, or to lock you in a cage, and you pay the money in order to avoid these things, it is still theft.

Finally, let’s assume that the group represented has been legitimately elected by a sufficiently large number of people. Through this mechanism of election, what has been theft up to this point is transformed for some people from theft into something more honorable. For such people, when enough voters agree that some part of what you earn shouldn’t be yours any more, they justify taking it by electing people who will put it in writing and call it law. For those people, a majority of voters can override our right to barter rocks for sticks or to exchange money for goods and services of others.

Whether you call this new election-backed behavior “taxation” or “theft”, the results are the same, and it is the results of a behavior that give it its meaning. Let’s examine the results and determine whether or not a significant difference is introduced by the election process.

You will no longer have direct control over who gets the money. It certainly won’t come to me in trade for my sharp stick. Most of the other people and companies that might provide you with goods and services for that money won’t see any of it. The few that do will not favor you with the goods and services they offer in return for it. These things all remain true regardless of the election process.

When a thief takes your money, you may appeal to the authorities to make an attempt to recover your loss. The chances of success for this strategy are usually pretty low because the authorities have no vested interest in or contractual obligation to seek the return of your property. However, if the thief has set up some kind of mechanism through which you can register your preference as to how your stolen money should be spent, you will have a small amount of control, though the choices may have little to do with the purchases you would have made had you retained control of your earnings. The same situation exists with taxation except that the election process allows your preferences to be registered if you participate, though the choices still have little to do with the purchases you would have made had you retained control of your earnings.

Additionally, taxation is worse than thievery because the authorities themselves are in on the take. They will use the private thief as an excuse to provide everyone with more (mostly ineffective) protection. They will use any resistance to being robbed through taxation as an excuse to provide everyone with “more security” through enforcement of tax laws and “closing loopholes”, as if being robbed through taxation is a benefit. So again, we see no significant difference even for those who vote, and none at all for those who do not, except that for both kinds of people, the election process co-opts the authorities and thus makes taxation worse than thievery.

Perhaps the best expression of the results of our discussion is that taxation and theft are different mostly because of their semantics, but an examination of their results makes them largely equivalent. However, taxation is even worse on several counts. The amount taken through taxation is much greater. The authorities, rather than working to rectify it, encourage it. Those who benefit the most from taxation make the crime more insidious by burying it in promises to spend the proceeds helping to make things better. So if taxation is not to be called theft, let us agree that it is something worse – maybe something like slavery!

[This article was prepared for the essay contest “How Do You Explain To People that Taxation is Theft?”. Dave Scotese is webmaster for voluntaryist.com and a freelance computer contractor.]

“My Yea Is Yea, My Nay Is Nay”: Voluntaryism, Integrity and the Question of the Oath


By Carl Watner

In his recent column, “The Solitary Leaker,” about Edward Snowden, David Brooks pointed out that Snowden betrayed all “honesty and integrity, … . He made explicit and implicit oaths to respect the secrecy of the information with which he was entrusted. He betrayed his oaths.” [1] Others have pointed out that perhaps Snowden solicited his top-secret job with the express purpose of exposing NSA secrets. Whether this was so, or whether Snowden took the job, and then discovered the perfidious extent of government surveillance, we will assume he broke whatever oaths he had sworn.

The taking of oaths is an immemorial tradition in the western world, generally connected to the relationship between the individual citizen and his government. Two people might take marriage vows, but one partner cannot imprison the other partner if the marriage promise is broken. A man does not swear an oath to Ford Motor Company when he accepts employment (though he may sign a confidentiality agreement), but when he deals with the State, he must generally swear to the truth of the facts under discussion. Most oaths are subject to the penalty of perjury, by which the government reserves the right to prosecute a person who willfully lies. Thus, it is easy to conclude that oaths are a way of forcing the truth from the recalcitrant citizen; a way of exercising government control over the citizen. Though oaths were intended to bring about truthful testimony, they were also designed to root out dissidents. Under the English Act of 1609, justices of the peace were authorized to administer a combined oath of allegiance and supremacy to any English man or woman whom they suspected of being disloyal to the king. Refusal to take the oath subjected the recusant to the punishment of praemunire, which meant being put out of the king’s protection, forfeiture of one’s property to the crown, and imprisonment for life or at royal pleasure. [2]

Both Baptists and Quakers suffered at the hands of the crown. In August 1664, George Fox, founder of the Society of Friends, was imprisoned for refusing to take the oath of allegiance and supremacy. When questioned by the judge of the Lancaster Assizes, he explained, “my yea or nay was more binding to me than an oath was to many others.” Fox stood upon Christ’s admonition “Swear not at all” (5 Matthews 33-37), and referred to the Epistle of James (Chapter 5, Verse 12) which taught all believers to abjure oaths and “let [their] yea be yea; and [their] nay, nay.” A few years before in 1662, Francis Bampfield, a Baptist minister, was ejected from his church and imprisoned for nearly 9 years. He was later imprisoned again for his persistent refusal to swear the oath of allegiance and he eventually died in Newgate prison in 1683. In 1675, William Penn and twelve other Quakers published A TREATISE ON OATHS CONTAINING SEVERAL WEIGHTY REASONS WHY PEOPLE CALLED QUAKERS REFUSE TO SWEAR. They pointed out that an oath will not deter a liar from lying, and the truthful person needs no inducement or threat to tell the truth. “God has taught us to speak the truth, the whole truth, and nothing but the truth, as plainly and readily without an oath as with an oath. … We regard the taking of an oath as contrary to the teaching of Christ, and as setting up a double standard of truthfulness, whereas truthfulness and sincerity should be practiced in all the dealings of life.” [3]

The whole concept of treason is directly related to the oath of allegiance and obedience to the laws of state. In her study of TREASON IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY, Margaret Boveri pointed out that the military loyalty oath had deep implications for members of the German army during World War I. Even before the flight of the Kaiser at the end of the war, some members of the General Staff were questioning what their oaths really meant. Were they bound by oath till the day the Kaiser died, or were they released from their promises of loyalty when he abdicated the throne? By the time the Weimar Republic morphed into the Third Reich, “the habit of unquestioning loyalty to the state was so deeply ingrained [in the psyche of the German citizens] that nothing seemed able to shake it. … Which particular government happened to be in power was of secondary importance.” [4]

However, after Hitler came to power in 1934, he had all members of the German military take an oath which stated: “I swear by God this holy oath, that I shall give my unconditional obedience to the Fuhrer of the German people and Reich, Adolf Hitler, and that I shall be prepared to sacrifice my life as a brave soldier in keeping this oath.” [5] Civilian employees of the German state were also required to swear allegiance. In 1993, “Luitgard Wundheiler remembered how her father, a judge in Marburg, Germany weighed the matter [of taking the oath].”

In 1936, her father had just received the letter sent to all German civil servants asking him to join the Nazi Party by signing a loyalty oath. He discussed it with his wife and then called the fourteen-year-old Wundheiler into his study. He gave her the letter to read and asked her if she thought he should sign. To her, his choice was clear: he should not sign it because to do so would be a lie and he never lied. Fifty-seven years later, Wundheiler still remembered the judicial clarity with which her father presented exactly what was as stake:
Before you say yes or no so clearly and so spontaneously, I also want you to know what the possible consequences are. I don’t know what the consequences will be definitely, but there will be some consequences. Under the best of circumstances, I will lose my job. Under the worst of circumstances, you will never see me again in your whole life because they will do away with me. There are a number of possibilities in between. Maybe they will put me in a concentration camp and sometime later release me, but there will be some consequences, and I want you to know that.
As it happened, her father, who was stubbornly honest and passionately committed to justice, refused to join the Nazi Party. He was summarily dismissed from the judiciary but managed to land a job as a court messenger. For the remaining years of the Nazi rule, he and his family existed barely above the poverty level. [6]

Hitler was very astute in having the oath predicated upon his person rather than upon the German nation or constitution. As World War II progressed, some German army officers became bitterly anti-Nazi, but they would not violate their obligation to obey Hitler’s orders, even if they thought them criminal or contrary to the international laws of war. Boveri relates the case of one German general in Italy who received orders which he considered wrong. “He made dispositions which were contrary, and then, with his hand still resting on the telephone, pulled his pistol from its holster and put a bullet through his brain.” [7] “The most curious example of oath interpretation by a professional soldier is the case of Paul Borchardt, a General Staff officer of considerable distinction, … . In 1938 he was dismissed from the General Staff and forced to leave the Army and he eventually left Germany because he was half Jewish. When charged by American Intelligence with spying, in 1942, he professed to be an anti-Nazi. However, he remained a German patriot who did his duty when Germany was at war, and eventually received a prison sentence of twenty years when he refused to violate his oath and give the names of his prior military contacts in Germany.” [8] Near the end of World War II, those inside the German resistance movement decided to attempt to assassinate Hitler, rather than arrest him and put him on trial, because hundreds of thousands of Germans had sworn fealty to him. [9]

So what do these brief historical comments portend for voluntaryists? What lessons are to be learned?

First, stay as far away from government as you can, so you are not involved in situations where you need to take an oath or swear allegiance. Second, refuse to swear, affirm, or answer questions posed by government agents. The burden in any criminal case is on the prosecution to prove that you are guilty. You are not required to prove your innocence.

Third, in my article “Am I an American Citizen and What Might It Mean?” I pointed out that people are born stateless and have citizenship imposed upon them by simply being born within the geographic area controlled by a particular government. Voluntaryists want nothing to do with any government, whether it be the one that controls the land where they are born, or otherwise. In that article, I asked whether a voluntaryist could sign an application for a U.S. passport that reads, I “declare under penalty of perjury that I am a citizen of the United States.” Not only is the voluntaryist not a citizen, but the voluntaryist objects, much like the Baptists and Quakers of old, to signing any government document, much less one that carries a penalty of perjury.

One subscriber took me to task because he argued that the declaration on the passport application was not morally binding because it was made under duress. Is this a valid argument or reason for signing a government document with which you do not agree? I think not. You cannot make a mental reservation when you take an oath or make an affirmation under penalty of perjury. One’s integrity is compromised if one makes an outward sign of submission, and then maintains an inner resolution of defiance. If integrity is a matter of being whole, of being the same on the inside as on the outside, then one cannot claim duress as a reason for being dishonest. One simply says, “No, I will not do this,” and then takes the consequences, whether it be going to jail, or fleeing and hiding from government agents, or being executed for being a voluntaryist. [10] As I explained in the conclusion to “Voluntaryism and Extreme Necessity,” a man only dies once so he must be careful and respectful of how he lives. How a man lives always trumps how long he lives. Or, as Gandhi wrote, “If one takes care of the means, the end will take care of itself.”

Footnotes

[1] NEW YORK TIMES, June 11, 2013, p. A 21.

[2] Constance Braithwaithe, CONSCIENTIOUS OBJECTION TO COMPULSIONS UNDER THE LAW, York, England: William Sessions Limited, 1995, pp. 19-20.

[3] from various Quaker tracts as quoted in ibid., pp. 14-17.

[4] Margaret Boveri, TREASON IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY, New York: G. P. Putnam’s Sons, 1963 (first published 1961), p. 32.

[5] ibid., p. 299. Also see entry for “Hitler Oath” in wikipedia.

[6] Eva Fogelman, COURGE AND CONSCIENCE, New York: Doubleday Books, 1994, pp. 23-24. Also see Milton Mayer, THEY THOUGHT THEY WERE FREE (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1955), pp. 176-181, for information about a German who was required to take the oath of fidelity and who opposed it in conscience. This excerpt is reprinted as “The Day the World Was Lost,“ in THE VOLUNTARYIST, Whole Number 31, April 1988.

[7] Boveri, op. cit., p. 301.

[8] ibid., p. 34. Also see “Paul Borchardt, the Abwehr and the W.J. Harding King Letters,” at http://www.fjexpeditions.com/frameset/borchardt.htm.

[9] ibid., p. 80.

[10] See David Romtvedt, “Loyalties,” THE VOLUNTARYIST, Whole Number 62, June 1993.

comments powered by Disqus

Voluntaryism and Extreme Necessity


by Carl Watner
From Issue 160 – 1st Quarter, 2014

In their book, LAW AND JUSTICE IN COMMUNITY, Garrett Barden and Tim Murphy write, “The nature of morality is a constant theme of this book. ‘What am I to do?’ is the moral or ethical question … because as humans we are constantly engaged in thought and action,” and must constantly deliberate and decide what course of action to take. [1] So, what would you do in the following situations?
you were out walking and saw a young child drowning in a pond;
you learned of people dying from starvation in Ethiopia;
you found a homeless family with a sick child occupying an unused building that you owned?
Although under the common law “there is no general duty to come to the rescue of another,” what are your legal and moral obligations in the above cases? [2] Would your responsibilities differ because of your proximity to the endangered? Would someone be able to throw you into jail for your failure to help those in need? Would you be able to remove squatters from your property? Would those in extreme need be justified in using your property in order to ensure their continued survival? Would your failure to help the drowning child make you responsible for that child’s death?

These questions and many others of a similar nature presented themselves as I did my reading during the Summer and Fall of 2012. For example, in the book WORLD HUNGER AND MORAL OBLIGATION, the editors discuss the responsibility of those in the developed countries toward the rest of the world’s population. [3] How should those who have more than enough food treat those who lack? Do those threatened by starvation have the right to invade and consume the property of those who have more food than they need? Would those whose property is invaded have a right to repel those who claim a right to their extra food? Is it legally and morally proper to take the food of another without that person’s consent in order to save one’s own life? Is the claim “it is my property” a sufficient reason for refusing food to the starving? In such a situation, where an owner chooses not to share his superfluities, is that owner legally or morally responsible for the death of people who die from starvation?

Similar conundrums were presented in an article subtitled “Rights of Subsistence and the Principle of Extreme Necessity” by Gerald Swanson. [4] Who should decide how much food, shelter, and clothing should be distributed to the poor and needy? Is anyone responsible for meeting their needs? Who should take care of those who cannot produce their own basic necessities? Would it be morally acceptable to let them starve, freeze, or die from lack of medical attention when others have more than they, themselves, require? Who should decide 1) how much is enough to distribute to the poor; 2) how much the rich should keep; and 3) the geographic limits of the distribution? Should it be limited to the poor in the next town, the next state, or the next country? Why should the poor on the other side of the earth suffer when there are superfluities here? In short, do individuals, by the mere fact of their being born, have a right to subsistence, and, if they do, who is obligated to provide it, and who is to be held responsible if there is not enough to go around?

Before answering these questions from a voluntaryist perspective, let’s look at how they were dealt with before the advent of the modern nation-state.

In Western Europe, at least until the 16th Century, the primary responsibility for the poor fell into the hands of people of the Christian faith, who followed Jesus’ teachings to feed the hungry, shelter the homeless, and care for the sick. The attitude of the Catholic Church was best exemplified by St. Basil (c. 330-379) who asserted that those who had more than they needed really didn’t own their extra wealth: “The bread that you store up belongs to the hungry; the cloak that lies in your chest belongs to the naked; and the gold that you have hidden in the ground belongs to the poor.” [5] This theme was elaborated during the later Middle Ages when the principle of extreme necessity became a common doctrine among medieval theologians and

canon lawyers. The principle stated that “a person in extreme necessity — that is, facing the prospect of certain, not necessarily instant, death — may rightfully take the property of other people to sustain his life. This principle is the most radical formulation of the medieval belief that God had bestowed the earth upon all mankind for its sustenance… .” [6] This conclusion led to two co-ordinate positions:

[T]he first held that people in extreme necessity might rightfully take what they needed to survive, and that their taking such goods had nothing of the nature of theft; and the second, … held that every person has the obligation to sustain the life of other people once his own needs have been met. [7]

Gratian’s DECRETUM, a famous medieval tome compiled about 1140 AD, also expounded the view that the fruits of the earth belonged to all mankind. “All things are common, that is, to be shared in time of necessity with those in want. … [W]e should retain for ourselves only necessities and distribute what is left to our neighbors in need.” [8] Joannes Teutonicus (also known as John of Wildehausen , c. 1180-1252) was one of the first medieval theologians to discuss the principle of extreme necessity. Citing the DECRETUM, he interpreted the word “‘common’ to mean ‘shared in time of need’”: “No one may call his own what is common, of which if man takes more than he needs, it is obtained by violence.” [9] “The decretist text did not deny the right to private property; rather it denied the right of anyone to appropriate as his own more than sufficed for his own needs.” According to Joannes, a “man was not bound to deprive himself of his own necessities in order to help another in need, though if he did so it would be a commendable act. He could even retain superfluities provided that others were not in want. But ‘in time of necessity’ any superfluous wealth of an individual was to be regarded as common property, to be shared with those in need.” [10]

The decretists saw no contradiction in maintaining the right to private property, on the one hand, and, on the other, the right of the poor to sustain their lives by taking from the wealthy. They recognized the right to private property, but the right of accumulation only extended as far as satisfying one’s basic needs. The man who accumulated goods beyond what he needed “to live in a decent and fitting fashion according to his status had no right to keep his wealth.” The DECRETUM was full of phrases like “Feed the poor. If you do not feed them, you kill them. A man who keeps more for himself than he needs is guilty of theft.” The canonists, living at a time when capitalism was unknown, “assumed that there was a fixed amount of food and other goods available.” As Brian Tierney explains in his book, MEDIEVAL POOR LAW, they believed that “a man who acquired more than was due to him was therefore necessarily depriving someone else of his fair share. He was literally guilty of theft.” That being the case, then it was clear that the poor had a right to be supported at the expense of the wealthy. A man “in extreme need who took the property of another was not guilty of any crime. He was not stealing what belonged to another but only taking what properly belonged to himself.” [11]

There was some question among the theologians and canon lawyers as to whether this obligation to assist the poor was legally enforceable in the church courts or whether it was simply a matter of fulfilling a moral obligation. Certainly the man who voluntarily helped the poor was more virtuous than the rich man who was forced to give up his wealth. But “from a lawyer’s point of view, there was a major flaw in the theory that a poor man had a right to the superfluous wealth of the rich. There did not exist any established form of legal action by which he could sue to enforce his right.” [12] Joannes Teutonicus solved this problem by directing the poor to denounce to the bishop the man who refused to give alms. The “Church could compel him to give, presumably by ecclesiastic censures,” by imposing penances, threatening imprisonment, and, in the last resort, by excommunication. [13]

Some later churchmen skirted this problem by describing what the poor took from the rich as a loan. The poor were duty bound to restitution as soon as their circumstances allowed. According to Martin de Azpilcueta (1491-1586), it was “more ethical to ask to borrow, than to borrow without acquiescence, and both alternatives” were superior to outright taking without permission. [14] Since the person who benefits from the taking must have the obligation to return what he has borrowed, this “proves that it is not the domain [the title] but the use that changes hands.” [15] Others opposed Martin by arguing that at the point of extreme necessity the goods became common, the title of the rich was extinguished, and that there was no further obligation on the part of the poor to restore whatever they had taken. [16]

In the century after Martin, the principle of extreme necessity became a topic for natural law writers, such as Hugo Grotius (1583-1645), Samuel von Pufendorf (1632-1694), and John Locke (1632-1704), and in the following century by Adam Smith (1723-1790). There was a wide variation in their thinking, but the consensus was that it would be morally wrong for anyone to starve while others had more food than they needed. If the world had been given to mankind in common, where was the proof that the poor had surrendered their rightful claims to what they needed to survive? According to Locke, “since a person has property for the sake of preserving himself and others, once his own preservation is secured, any further use for enjoyment is conditional on the preservation of others.” Thus, for Locke, charity is a right on the part of the needy and a duty on the part of the wealthy. … If a case of need arises… one man’s individual right is overridden by another’s claim, and the goods become his property. By failing to hand over the goods, the proprietor invades the share now belonging to the needy… .” [17] As Locke wrote in his FIRST TREATISE OF GOVERNMENT:

[N]o Man could ever have a just Power over the Life of another, by Right of property in Land or Possessions; since ‘twould always be a Sin in any Man of Estate, to let his Brother perish for want of affording him Relief out of another’s Plenty. As Justice gives every Man a Title to the product of his honest Industry, and the fair Acquisitions of his Ancestors descended to him; so Charity gives every Man a Title to so much out of another’s, as will keep him for extream [sic] want, where he has no other means to subsist otherwise; … . [18]

What did Adam Smith, the father of modern economics think of Locke’s position? What did Adam Smith recommend in times of drought and famine? Was it possible for him to reconcile the rights of farmers and merchants to the grain they owned with the possibility that the poor might starve because market conditions were reflected in high prices, which the poor could not afford? On the one hand, Smith believed that if the markets for food and labor were freed of government intervention, in the long run the prices of food and labor would balance out “in such a way that the poor would never go hungry.” [19] “By raising the productivity of agriculture, commercial society could provide adequately for the needs of the wage earner without having to resort to any form of redistributive meddling in the property rights of individuals. Growth in conditions of ‘natural liberty’ would explode the whole antinomy between needs and rights.” [20] On the other hand, Smith admitted that governments had the responsibility to secure the subsistence of all the inhabitants of the realm. He “could not quite find the way” to say that the poor must simply die of hunger. He followed his conscience, rather than his economic analyses, to assert that in times of famine it was justified to suspend “property rights in grain.” [21]

Today, we must still answer the same questions that Adam Smith faced.
Does extreme necessity justify taking another’s property without permission?
Does nature kill or do men kill by their refusal to help others in need?
Should some die while others live?
Who should decide?
Does the right to live trump the right to own property?
Are some people obligated to produce so that others may survive?
What are the basic necessities?
Are they the same for an African bushman as for a resident of the United States?
Who should decide what other people need?
Are those who can produce the most to be enslaved to those who cannot produce enough for their own sustenance?
Let me briefly answer these questions from a voluntaryist perspective:
No. Extreme necessity does not excuse the use of another person’s property without permission.
Nature causes the death of a starving man; not the man who refuses him food.
Yes, in emergency and extreme situations (where not all can survive) it is necessary that some, if not all, perish.
No one decides who lives or dies in such situations. Nature decides.
No. One cannot live without property; nor can there be property without someone to own it.
No. People are not obligated to produce more than they, themselves, need, in order to support other people.
Basic necessities would be food, shelter, and clothing.
Yes, basic necessities are the same for every person.
No one should decide what other people “need.”
No one should be enslaved or forced to produce so that others live.
Consider this from the point of view of a factory owner who has decided to close his manufacturing facility because it is not producing a profit. [22] If his current employees cannot find work elsewhere, they will eventually starve to death. Is the factory owner obliged to furnish them jobs? If he closes his factory, and they have no other means of survival, is he responsible for their deaths?

First of all, it ought to be clear that the factory owner is not killing his employees by closing the factory. He might choose to help them find new jobs or relocate, but at some point they have to fend for themselves. It is a fact of nature and a fact of reality that a person who does not produce enough for himself is causing his or her own death. Some might reply that the reason the employees cannot sustain themselves is because the necessary land and resources have been appropriated by others. If land and resources were available to the employees, they would be able to survive. However, this only takes our analysis one step backwards. Who is the rightful owner of the resources in question, and what, or how does appropriation of the land and resources of the earth occur, and are those currently alive responsible for remedying what appears to be injustices in its current ownership?

It is certainly strong medicine to say that some should die while others live but should the factory owner be forced to keep his factory running? Is the factory owner a slave of his employees? If justice requires that each person have a minimum sustenance, “[p]roduction then becomes a requirement of justice.” [23] Then the failure to produce would be wrong, but if that were the case then why is the failure of the poor to produce even enough for their own survival not wrong, too? If it is a requirement of justice to produce, then the poor should be as much obliged to produce as the rich. This reasoning illustrates the contradiction inherent in the idea that the rich are obliged to sustain the poor. In reality, there are no rich people and no poor people, there are only people – some who produce more than others. As Thomas Sowell once wrote, “private property rights do not simply exist for the sake of people who own property.” [24] The poor, even though they own only a small amount of personal property, still benefit from the existence of private property. If you were poor, where would you rather live: in a country where property rights are respected or one where property rights are not recognized?

What does modern history tell us about countries where property rights are generally respected? We know that modern free market societies have never experienced famine. We know that Americans have been and are some of the most generous people on earth. [25] We know that the poor in America are often better off than the rich in some countries around the world. We know that the plight of the poor is usually much worse in countries whose economies are collectivist and socialist. We know that in societies where property rights are respected, there are fewer conflicts and greater wealth. We know that the Golden Rule, which tells us to treat others as we would have others treat us, provides us guidance. The Golden Rule urges us to respect other people’s property as we would have them respect our property. It also directs us to assist others who need assistance, as we would have others help us when we need assistance. And these guidelines are applicable to all mankind, rich or poor, healthy or sick, well-off or in circumstances of extreme necessity.

To continue our analysis, consider the distinction between acts of commission and acts of omission. No one normally decides who lives and dies. If Robinson Crusoe is alone on an island and cannot produce enough food to feed himself, nature and reality cause him to die of starvation. Why does the presence of other people change the responsibility for what has happened? Suppose they were on one side of the island and Crusoe on the other, and neither have knowledge of the other. Being ignorant of Crusoe’s situation, how could they be responsible for his death? And even if they knew he was starving, why would they be obligated to act? Their failure to act was not the cause of his death. It is Crusoe’s inability to produce enough for himself that results in his death. As Lysander Spooner pointed out in his ESSAY ON NATURAL LAW, individuals may owe many moral duties to their fellow human beings: “such as to feed the hungry, clothe the naked, shelter the homeless, care for the sick, protect the defenseless, assist the weak, and enlighten the ignorant. But these are simply moral duties, of which each man must be his own judge, in each particular case, as to whether, and how far, he can, or will, perform them.” [26] It may be immoral, vicious, even inhumane, to watch another person starve when you have more than enough, but it is not criminal to do so. Others may choose to ostracize you (for what they may call selfish behavior), but they do not have the right to put you in jail or force you to share your superfluities with others.

Do we have a duty to discover if people are dying from starvation in Africa? To what extent, if any, are we our brother’s keeper, whether he lives next door or on the other side of the earth? Are we responsible for the starvation of people in Africa who cannot produce enough to sustain themselves? I believe the answers to all of these questions are in the negative. We can choose to voluntarily commit resources to help our fellow human beings survive, but our failure to do so is not the same as killing them. Do people have positive rights to survive? “No.” As Tibor Machan observes, “Unfairness is built into the very idea of positive basic rights.” [27] It is impossible to secure positive rights for some (such as the right to food, health care or education) without trampling on the rights of others. Someone must produce first, and it is a matter of justice to recognize that the producers are the rightful owners of what they produce. “If we may force others to educate our children, to feed us, to provide us with health care, why not with their one eye when we are blind, their one kidney when both ours are damaged, their entire life if we need it badly enough? And if we are entitled to their support, when are they entitled to ours, and who has priority in all this?” [28] People’s needs are endless, particularly when they do not have to pay for their fulfillment. Are the needs of the producers any less valid than the needs of those who don’t produce?

Furthermore, who should decide these things? All human beings are equal when it comes to making decisions about their own bodies and property. He who says my property should be distributed to those in need, should first distribute his own wealth. He who says I should go to the aid of a drowning child, simply ought to go himself, rather than speaking up and urging me to go. That is why such people as Mahatma Gandhi and Mother Teresa are such shining moral examples to us. They first do themselves, what they ask others to do, and they certainly stand in stark contrast to politicians and elected officials who are not noted for leading ascetic life-styles.

The classical liberal conception of fundamental human rights is that such rights do not conflict. Such rights are “essentially negative injunctions which instruct us not to interfere with other people’s choices.” [29] It is clear that the voluntaryist definition of liberty is entirely negative. A man’s right to his life and property tell “us not so much what he may properly do but rather what others may not properly do to him. It is fundamentally a right not to be interfered with.” [30] The primary issue is an ethical one, a matter of justice: Where does A get the right to direct the use of B’s life and property? [31] Voluntaryism calls for the absence of coercion between man and man, and no more. It does not guarantee life, or success, or a full belly. It does not mean the absence of bad luck or the presence of good luck. It does not mean that a person will make the best use of his property. It simply means that other men must leave him alone. As F. A. Hayek put it, “to be free may mean freedom to starve, to make costly mistakes, or to run mortal risks.” [32]

The ancient Stoics believed that it was more important how one lived than whether one lived or died. Paraphrasing William Wallace, from the movie BRAVEHEART, every man dies only once. A person of integrity is more concerned with the means than with the end. He or she will give up his or her own life rather than take the life or property of another. To the person of self-esteem it may be a personal failure to have to beg for food, shelter, or clothing. However it would be a greater personal failure to steal. If one were in a condition of extreme necessity would it be better to become a thief and stay alive or to remain true to one’s principles and die if all refused your pleas for help? I cannot speak for others or make their decisions, but as for me, I would rather die an honest man than die a thief. How we live always trumps how long we live.

Footnotes:

[1] Garrett Barden and Tim Murphy, LAW AND JUSTICE IN COMMUNITY, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010, pp. 5 and 16.
[2] “Duty to Rescue,” www.wikipedia.org. Accessed February 10, 2013. See Section 1, “Common Law.”
[3] William Aiken and Hugh La Follette (editors), WORLD HUNGER AND MORAL OBLIGATION, Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall Inc., 1977. See their “Introduction,” pp. 1-10.
[4] Scott G. Swanson, “The Medieval Foundation of John Locke’s Theory of Natural Rights: Rights of Subsistence and the Principle of Extreme Necessity,” XVIII HISTORY OF POLITICAL THOUGHT (1997), pp. 399-459.
[5] “Charity” in H. L. Mencken (editor), A NEW DICTIONARY OF QUOTATIONS ON HISTORIAL PRINCIPLES FROM ANCIENT AND MODERN SOURCES, New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1942, p. 156. Also see a similar translation in Brian Tierney, MEDIEVAL POOR LAW, Berkeley: University of California Press, 1959, p. 34 and footnote 21, p. 146.
[6] Swanson, op. cit., p. 401.
[7] ibid., p. 405.
[8] Tierney, op. cit, footnote 17, p. 146.
[9] ibid., p. 34.
[10] ibid. pp. 34-35.
[11] For the numerous quotations in this paragraph see ibid., pp. 37-38.
[12] ibid., p. 38.
[13] ibid.
[14] Alejandro A. Chafuen, FAITH AND LIBERTY, Lanham: Lexington Books, 2003, p. 44.
[15] ibid., p. 45.
[16] Swanson, op. cit., p. 408.
[17] James Tully, A DISCOURSE ON PROPERTY, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1980,p. 132.
[18] John Locke, TWO TREATISES OF GOVERNMENT, edited by Peter Laslett, New York: The New American Library, First Printing as a Mentor Book, December 1965, pp. 205-206. See THE FIRST TREATISE, Chapter 4, “Of Adam’s Title to Sovereignty by Donation,” Sec. 42.
[19] Istvan Hont and Michael Ignatieff, “Needs and Justice in THE WEALTH OF NATIONS: An Introductory Essay,” in Istvan Hont and Michael Ignatieff (editors), WEALTH AND VIRTUE, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983, pp. 1-44 at p. 14.
[20] ibid., p. 25.
[21] Swanson, op. cit., p. 459.
[22] Howard Richards, “Productive Justice,“ in Aiken and La Follette, op. cit., pp. 165-179 at p. 171.
[23] ibid., p. 171.
[24] Thomas Sowell, “Forward to the Past?” on www.creators.com, circa December 18 or 19, 2012.
[25] See Carl Watner, “The Most Generous Nation on Earth: Voluntaryism and American Philanthropy,” THE VOLUNTARYIST, Whole Number 61, April 1993, pp. 1, 3-7.
[26] Lysander Spooner, NATURAL LAW; OR THE SCIENCE OF JUSTICE, Boston: A. Williams & Co., 1882, Part I, Section II, p. 6, reprinted in Charles Shively (editor), THE COLLECTED WORKS OF LYSANER SPOONER, Weston: M & S Press, 1971, Volume I.
[27] Tibor Machan, GENEROSITY: VIRTUE IN CIVIL SOCIETY, Washington DC: Cato Institute, 1998, p. 37.
[28] ibid.
[29] John Hasnas, “From Cannibalism to Caesareans: Two Conceptions of Fundamental Rights,” 89 NORTHWESTERN UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW (1995), pp. 900-941 in Part IV, Section B “Features of the Classical Conception.” Also apparently published in 45 DUKE LAW JOURNAL (1995), pp. 84-125.
[30] James Sadowsky, S. J., “Private Property and Collective Ownership,” in Tibor Machan (ed.), THE LIBERTARIAN ALTERNATIVE, Chicago: Nelson-Hall Company, 1974, pp. 119-133 at p. 121.
[31] paraphrasing ibid., p. 124.
[32] F. A. Hayek, THE CONSTITUTION OF LIBERTY, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1960, p. 18.

Do You Really “Owe” Those Taxes?


By Anonymous

I recently had a short conversation with a friend about the meaning of the stealing commandment, “Thou shall not steal.” His attitude was “If you owe the taxes, then the government can’t be stealing from you when they collect it.” However, he did recognize that if you don’t owe it, then it is stealing when the government comes after you with all its might. So, do you really owe the tax money or not? Are you stealing from the government when you refuse to pay? Or is the I.R.S. stealing from you because you never agreed to pay what they claim you owe? It has got to be one or the other. Which is it?

On the one hand, government personnel pass legislation that demands compulsory contributions from the citizenry. No one is really asked to consent to this legislation, and even if one voted to select some of the government personnel that support these taxes, one could hardly be said to have agreed to its imposition. And what if one voted, but chose an opposition candidate who was defeated; or didn’t vote at all? Clearly, the government does not care whether you have voted or not. They still consider you liable for your taxes.

Most people want to be upright and meet their voluntarily-assumed obligations. They willingly pay their rightful debts in order to maintain their own self-esteem and to maintain their reputation in the minds of their friends, neighbors, and countrymen. So if taxes were really voluntarily contracted debts as the Internal Revenue Service maintains, then why does the government need to rely on force and its threat to collect the money? The very fact that the government must resort to this supports my argument that taxes are not voluntarily-assumed obligations.

Is there really any evidence that you owe your taxes? Did you even enter into a contract that you would pay ‘x’ amount in return for government services? Is your income tax return such a contract? No, it is a document coerced from you under penalty of perjury and under penalty for not filing. Furthermore, the government does not depend on having you file a tax return in order to claim that you owe them money. Ever hear of people being imprisoned and fined for NOT filing returns? The government cannot have it both ways: you owe if you do file and you owe if you don’t file. In fact, this is proof that the government is simply demanding money from you, no matter what you do. Therefore, I think it is safe to conclude that neither filing nor not filing constitutes any kind of proof that you owe taxes. There is no evidence of any consent or agreement on your part. The government considers you under its jurisdiction and consequently claims you owe it the tax.

Most advocates of taxation justify their view that “taxation is not theft” by referring to some form of “tacit” consent that each person incurs by simply being alive. This amounts to the claim that if you were born in the United States, then your presence means that you have agreed to be taxed! But where does it say that on your birth certificate (another service controlled by the government)? And even if it did, could an infant agree to such a condition at time of birth? No: infants do not have the capacity to contract debts. Besides, what would happen to those parents if they refused to consent on behalf of their children? Would they and their infant be forced to leave the country?

Does one’s use of government-provided services, such as the roads and the schools, mean you agree to be taxed to support the government? No. The government coercively monopolizes many of the goods and services some people would willingly pay for. By preventing competition, the government effectively denies them any choice in who they should buy these services from. At most, the government should present a bill for specific services rendered, not a bill for supporting all its activities. Furthermore, governments collect for such services from people regardless of whether they use, or even want, the service in question. For example, parents with no children, or, parents with children who do not attend government schools, must still pay school taxes. Pacifists are forced to pay taxes to support the police and the army. What possible justification can there be for compelling a man to accept a product he never ordered, doesn’t use, and would prefer not to have? And then jailing him when he refuses to pay the bill?

But this moves the argument one further step backward. Does the State have the right to determine the conditions under which we live? It is true that there are costs expended in protecting one’s property, and most people recognize that they must furnish their own protection or pay someone else to provide it. However, they should not be restricted from doing so themselves or seeking competitive bids for the provision of the services they desire. Government taxation prevents this from occurring.

Some argue that government is a necessity, just like food, shelter and clothing, Therefore, we are obligated to pay for it, despite not having requested its services. But this is a false analogy for two reasons. First, government is not a necessity, though some of the services it provides may be a requisite for civilized living. The question then becomes: what is the most moral and most practical method for delivering these services to those who want them? Second, even if government were a necessity, there is no reason for it to compel the purchase of its services. No one forces us to buy food, shelter, and clothing for ourselves. If a concerned third party acted like the government, they would outlaw all other providers and force us to buy from them. If we refused to do so, they would bundle us off to jail and steal our property, to boot. But that is not the way the “free” world works. If I fail to buy food, shelter, or clothing, I may die of hunger, exposure, or cold, but no one puts me in jail or confiscates my property for failure to do so.

It should be clear that government taxation is a coercive activity that introduces force and violence into an otherwise peaceful society. Those who say they haven’t agreed to pay their taxes understand that certain goods and services (food, shelter, clothing, protection) are essential to human survival and must be paid for, but realize they need not be provided by the government on a compulsory basis. What they oppose is the coercion involved in collecting taxes. They oppose the means, and take the position that the ends never justify the means. If some people think that certain government services are necessary, then they should try to collect the money to fund them in a voluntary fashion. If the people collecting this money do not think enough has been collected, then let them dig into their own pockets to make up the deficiency or do without. They do not have the right to spend other people’s money on things they think are necessary.

The whole premise of government taxation is essentially the idea that you and your property belong to the State. You are a slave of the State. Whatever the government allows you to keep or accumulate is simply attributable to its generosity. It is not yours by right. The voluntaryist view is that the State is a criminal institution; and that the State accumulates its resources and wealth only by stealing from each member of the community. Consequently, failing to file a tax return, or “cheating” on one’s tax return is simply a case of outwitting the criminals and keeping your own property. How could anyone object to you hiding your jewels so that a common thief couldn’t find them? Is that any different than you holding on to your wealth so that the government can’t seize it?

The answer in both cases is the same. Neither the common thief nor the government have any right to your wealth. They have no right to object to your actions that prevent them from seizing all or part of it. What the government calls tax evasion, either not paying your taxes or paying less than it claims, is simply a person’s way of saying, “No!” or “Enough is enough!” Such actions are one way of protecting your property from government thieves and reducing the amounts the government steals from you. The non-filer and tax evader are usually looked upon as cheats but is that really the case? No! The cheaters are those who deceive others into believing that they “owe” taxes to the government. These are the people who are trying to cheat the rest of us out of our rightfully earned property! Tax refuseniks are simply trying to outwit a criminal government by keeping what belongs to them. It is their money. It was honestly earned. They are fully justified in keeping it out of the clutches of both the thief and the tax man!

Addendum

The gist of my article is to counter the belief that you are obligated to pay taxes levied by the government. Most people agree that if you “owe” somebody money, then you should meet your obligation and pay the debt. But to “owe” already assumes that you have voluntarily contracted the debt, and thus obligate yourself to its repayment.

But this is false in the case of taxes (which is precisely why the government goes to such great length to argue that paying taxes is voluntary).  Taxes are a coercive demand imposed upon you by the government, just as the robber demands your wallet.

If you once admit taxes are “forced exactions,” then it follows that taxation is no different than the forced exactions of a thief.  You certainly don’t “owe” the thief the contents of your wallet. “Well,” you reply, “the government provides us with infrastructure and services.”  “So what?” I reply, “so does the kidnapper who forcibly abducts you and then feeds and shelters you.” Do you “owe” the kidnapper for his services in keeping you alive while he demands a ransom? Of course not!

Isn’t the government acting just like the kidnapper? – which brings us to the whole point of my argument: “How can you define taxation in a way which makes it different from robbery?”

 

“The question is not whether or not theft is wrong but what is considered to be theft; in the same way, murder is universally forbidden but there are great differences between peoples as to what killing is considered to be murder.”
– Garrett Barden and Tim Murphy, LAW AND JUSTICE IN COMMUNITY (2010), p. 54.

 

The Gospel According to Government


By Larken Rose

We read now from the Gospel according to Government, first book of Politicians, Chapter 1, Verse 1.

In the beginning, there was chaos and mayhem, and people were as wild beasts. And there was great wailing, and gnashing of teeth throughout the land. Then it came to pass that politicians came down out of heaven, shining in glory, and spoke unto the people, saying, “Were are the Lord thy government, and we have decided to bless you with our presence, so that we may save you from your sins. Obey our commands, pay tribute unto us, and salvation shall be yours. For you are but stupid, violent animals, and only through our benevolent domination of you shall you be transformed into a civilized, happy and prosperous people.”

And the people wondered at the words of the politicians, and were sorely afraid. But the politicians said unto them, “Fear not. If you blindly obey the god called government, and mindlessly follow our every whim, then you shall be blessed. But those who would disobey our commands–the heathens and criminals who think for themselves–being evil in our sight, shall be cast into prison, and banished from the collectivist paradise we shall create for you. Cast aside your individual judgment, your free will, your conscience and your moral codes, and follow us, the high priests of government, without thought or question. ”

“The foolish man builds his house upon consensus, cooperation, and voluntary interaction, but the wise man builds his house upon political promises, state coercion, and the lust for power over others. Free will, self-determination, and peaceful coexistence are the devil’s work, and lead only to fire and brimstone, suffering and torment. But blind obedience, unthinking loyalty, and unwavering subservience are the path to salvation.”

“You have heard that it hath been said, love your neighbor, and do unto others as you would have done unto you. But we, the politicians, say unto you, pray for the incarceration or extermination of those who are not like you. But pray also for your neighbors to be taxed and regulated, petition for your friends to be controlled and enslaved, devote your heart and soul to the rituals of the cult of politics, so that we, the high priests of government, may dominate all of mankind, for its own good. Only then shall you have everlasting peace.”

“We are the lord thy government, and here are our commandments. Thou shalt have no other gods before government. Thou shalt follow no moral codes and no value systems above the arbitrary whims of your masters. Thou shalt not take the name of government in vain, or speak against us, the high priests of state. For those who do so are sinners, criminals and terrorists in our eyes, and shall be wiped from the face of the earth.”

“Remember election day, to keep it holy. Judge not the politicians, lest ye be put on the no-fly list. Honor thy congressman and thy senator, that their reign may be long upon the land which government thy god has taken from thee.”

“Thou shalt murder, by voting for those who engage in perpetual war-mongering. Thou shalt kill, when government commands it. And the killing shall be called, “national defense,” “serving one’s country,” and “spreading democracy.” No greater love hath a man than this, that a man will go halfway around the world to murder complete strangers, because we told him to.”

“Thou shalt steal, by voting for your neighbors to be taxed, and thou shalt hate and persecute any who resist. Thou shalt covet thy neighbor’s income, and his house, and everything that is thy neighbor’s, and beg the lord thy government to take these things from thy neighbor, to give them unto thee. Verily we say unto you, it is greedy and selfish to keep what you have earned, but noble and virtuous to take what your neighbor has earned.”

“Thou shalt bear false witness, by calling thieves and robbers “public servants,” by calling usurpers and tyrants “representatives,” and by calling those who advocate liberty for all, “criminals and terrorists.”

Blessed are the blindly obedient, for the politicians shall reward them.

Blessed are they who hunger and thirst after power, for they shall be satisfied.

Blessed are the voters, for they shall legitimize tyranny and oppression.

Blessed are the bankers, for they shall embezzle the earth.

Blessed are the jackbooted thugs, for they shall get away with murder.

Blessed are the corrupt in heart, for they shall receive power.

Blessed are the war-mongers, for they shall imagine themselves to be gods.

Blessed are they who have persecuted the innocent, for the politicians’ sakes, for they shall be promoted.

And cursed are the heathens and extremists, who speak out against our tyranny, who encourage you to question authority, and who instruct you to disobey immoral commands.

We, the politicians, say unto you, worship those who insult and exploit you, bow to those who extort and oppress you, and vote for those who spitefully use you and persecute you.

Here ends our reading from the first book of politicians, from the gospel according to government.

[Reprinted by permission of the author. Originally presented June 2012, at Porcupine Freedom Festival (PorcFest), Lancaster, New Hampshire.]

The Wisdom of Bob LeFevre


 

by Carl Watner

[Author’s Note: The following article was written in September 2012 as an Introduction to the e-book version of Robert LeFevre’s THE NATURE OF MAN AND HIS GOVERNMENT.]

 

At the outset, I must admit some personal bias. My intellectual acquaintance with Bob LeFevre goes back at least as far as January 1972, when I first ordered a copy of his book, THIS BREAD IS MINE. I first met Bob at the Long Beach, California, Future of Freedom Conference in October 1983. Thereafter, until his death, Bob was a key part of my life. He helped publish the first book of voluntayist essays to which I contributed. Titled NEITHER BULLETS NOR BALLOTS, it came out in December 1983. In October 1984, Bob approached me about writing his biography, which was eventually published in 1988 under the title ROBERT LEFEVRE -TRUTH IS NOT A HALFWAY PLACE. In March 1985, Bob and I both attended a week-long session of Freedom School given by Kevin Cullinane. Bob was present at my wedding in Campobello, South Carolina, on May 3, 1986. He died a few days later while driving home to California with his wife, Loy.

I knew Bob well during the last three years of his seventy-five-year life span. What kind of person was he? What were his intellectual roots? What was the nature of Bob LeFevre? What wisdom did he share with us in this book you are about to read?

Bob was always the gentlemen. Karl Hess remembered him for his “majestic civility,” always respectful of those who differed with him. As he put it in the “Foreword” to my LeFevre biography, “[I] was always mindful of Bob’s great patience, the truly caring nature of his advice, and finally, the clear rightness of his principles.” For one who only knew Bob in his later years, it was surprising for me to learn that he had such a checkered professional life. It ran the gamut from being a supporter of the “I Am” movement in the last half of the 1930s, a radio announcer, an army captain during World War II, a self-employed entrepreneur, a would-be politician, a newspaper editorial writer, and finally founder and primary instructor at Freedom School.

This book, THE NATURE OF MAN AND HIS GOVERNMENT, was a product of these last two phases of his life. The idea for the book originated with Jim Gipson of Caxton Press, who suggested to Bob that he prepare a step-by-step explanation of the doctrine of liberty as taught at Freedom School. All but Chapter 6, “National Defense,” were first written as editorials and appeared in the Colorado Springs, Colorado, GAZETTE-TELEGRAPH between January 5, and January 15, 1958. They were then collected and published as a small book in 1959, with an original Introduction contributed by Bob’s friend, Rose Wilder Lane.

The most significant influence on Bob during his formative years was his mother, Ethel. Better known as Bonnie, she came from Quaker stock, and had always taught him to question the rightness or wrongness of his conduct. She instilled in him the idea that “truth” – whatever it was and wherever it led him – was the most important thing in life. She also taught him not to be afraid of being different, to tell the truth, to work like hell, and to smile. She showed him how to search out the truth, and then to act on it according to the best dictates of his conscience.

Bob was active in Republican politics during the early 1950s, but he finally proved to himself that “politics was not the answer.” In November 1954, he began work as an editorial writer for Harry Hoiles, publisher of the GAZETTE-TELEGRAPH in Colorado Springs. It was here that he began to formulate a complete freedom philosophy. Harry’s father, R.C. Hoiles, was founder of the Freedom Newspapers, which were once described “as the greatest money-making device ever put together in support of human liberty and human dignity.”

Both Hoiles, father and son, wanted someone who could write consistently on the subject of human freedom. Until he resigned on January 15, 1965, Bob worked with both of them, hammering out the libertarian philosophy of the Freedom Newspapers. Nearly all of his editorial output centered around various aspects of human liberty and the free market. Bob had previously read Rose Wilder Lane’s DISCOVERY OF FREEDOM, and had met Leonard Read and Baldy Harper of the free-market-oriented Foundation for Economic Education. Baldy Harper, who had taught economics at Cornell University, was the first person Bob ever knew who questioned the basic assumption that human beings require a political government. However, it was the Hoiles’ insistence on building an integrated philosophy of freedom that made Bob realize “limited government” was an oxymoron and that it was redundant to speak of “unlimited government.”

Both Harry and R.C. had a significant impact on Bob’s thinking. They exposed him to the idea of abandoning reliance on limited government, and replacing it with competing defense agencies and other private service-providers to carry out the many functions of government. As they saw it, individuals needed food, shelter, clothing, protection, etc., but providing these necessities did not require a monopolistic government. In the late 1940s or early 1950s, Frank Chodorov pointed out to R.C., “[T]here was no such thing as voluntary taxation.” R. C., who had been a proponent of voluntary funding of government, then concluded that he was “against all taxes.” What he came to favor was free-enterprise associations or voluntary defense companies that would sell protection of life and property, much like an insurance company. As Bob asked, is there a way to “devise a tool for our protection which will be paid for only by those who want it, and in whatever amounts the payers deem best?”

Bob’s editorial writing, as well as his teaching at Freedom School, propelled him towards the conclusion that there was nothing that government could do that the private sector could not do more efficiently. Free enterprise, which rested on the consent of the customer, was certainly more moral than government-provided services. As he wrote in an April 7, 1961 editorial: “We are convinced that when it comes to things people want, the market place can do the job less expensively and better than government can do it. And this includes the job of protecting life and property, providing roads, schools, hospitals, cemeteries, airfields, and scores of other things which governments presently provide.” Some called Bob an anarchist for rejecting government, but he disagreed. He preferred the labels “voluntaryist” or “autarchist” to differentiate himself from those anarchists who rejected private property.

It was in this milieu and under the influence of the Hoiles that Bob wrote these editorials on the nature of man and his government. Essentially Bob saw government as a tool created by men to help protect themselves from invasion and aggression by others. However, this tool which had been intended “as a safeguard for human freedom and dignity” was ill-designed from the start because it depended on the use of violence. Shouldn’t peaceful individuals be left alone to protect themselves as they saw fit? Wasn’t government acting in an aggressive manner when it forced people to patronize its services? As Bob observed, government “is an instrument of force and coercion.” Even if it were to be voluntarily funded, as R.C. had once advocated, its violent and compulsory nature still remained. Those who preferred to have another protection agency serve them were prevented from doing so, and those who preferred no protection, or to provide their own, were not allowed to withdraw their patronage.

The essence of Bob’s philosophy was taken from Rose Wilder Lane’s dictum: “freedom is self-control.” Harking back to the attraction of the “I Am” movement, Bob understood that human energy can only be controlled by the individual. This means that each of us has the decision-making power over his own life. We decide whether we vote or not, whether we respect other people’s property or steal, whether we lie or tell the truth, whether we forgive or seek forceful restitution, whether we deal with our fellow man violently or peacefully.

Bob shared a common viewpoint with the Stoics of ancient Athens and Rome. Like them, he viewed human freedom as the absolute dominion of the individual over his own will. This meant that man, by his very nature, was free, and that there was only one long- term way of improving society. If individual men would conduct themselves morally, then society, a mere gathering of men, would be virtuous. In short, Bob saw that if one took care of the means, the end would take care of itself. Bob’s idea behind teaching the fundamentals of liberty was not to change anybody. He had neither the authority nor the ability to do so. His aim was to inspire each person to achieve freedom in the right way; the rest was up to the individual.

Bob was a truth-seeker, a man of wisdom. Part of his greatness was his ability to stand alone intellectually, another was his consistency. He insisted on thinking ideas through to their conclusions. If there was a choice between being popular and holding to the truth, he always chose the truth. He knew that truth is not a half-way place. Cyrano de Bergeac’s maxim, “Be admirable in all things,” could have been Bob’s own personal motto. Bob thought that we shouldn’t spend much time on destroying evil ideas, but rather devote ourselves to nourishing good ideas and putting them into practice. His task was to understand, to comprehend, and to make allowances for the failures of others. Only to himself did he insist on total self-control and complete self-discipline. Bob was a man who admirably achieved those goals in his own life, and it is that spirit of reasonableness, honesty, and truth-seeking that shall always epitomize Bob for me.

As you read this book, keep Bob’s perspective in mind. As he put it, “wisdom is possible only when the individual has learned to control himself.” Whether you have long been exposed to libertarian thinking or are newly introduced to voluntaryism, this will help you understand Bob’s quest for consistency and his conclusion that political government is inherently an invasive institution.

Short Bibliography
Carl Watner, “A Freedom Philosopher: Robert LeFevre, 1911-1986,” THE VOLUNTARYIST, No. 20, July 1986, pp. 1-2.

Carl Watner, ROBERT LEFEVRE: TRUTH IS NOT A HALF-WAY PLACE, Gramling: The Voluntaryists, 1988.

Carl Watner, “To Thine Own Self Be True: The Story of Raymond Cyrus Hoiles and His Freedom Newspapers,” in Carl Watner (editor), I MUST SPEAK OUT, San Francisco: Fox & Wilkes, 1999, pp. 147-158. (First appeared in THE VOLUNTARYIST, No. 18, May 1986.)

From Vagueness to Voluntaryism: How I Got From There to Here


By Alex R. Knight III

The first time I remember even seeing the word “libertarian,” was in 1994, when I was twenty-five. Years prior to that, like most kids, I had no real philosophical or political leanings. Government was just something that happened to be there, like the landscape, or the weather. As I grew into my teens, however, I began to develop a kind of vague sense that something was wrong – perhaps even horribly so – with the way society was structured. I think the catalysts for this awakening process were things that many young people experience on the path to adulthood: I had my first few brushes with the police – mainly for underage drinking. The paychecks I earned at the several jobs I had over those years had numerous taxes taken out of them. Laws restricting ownership of guns seemed increasingly wrong. The police and the military had them, yet the government wanted to curtail others from doing so. I began, again, like many young people, to distrust and resent authority in all forms.

My new awareness, however, had no cohesive threads running through it. My rapidly developing beliefs didn’t fit into any form of traditional political paradigm. I wasn’t “right-wing.” I didn’t think the police should have many of the powers that they had. I didn’t think drugs should be illegal (after all, I was doing them). I didn’t think the government should have soldiers marching all over the world. But I wasn’t “left-wing” either: As stated, I liked guns, and thought people should be able to own them without asking permission from anyone. I thought people, regardless of how much money they had, should be able to keep that money without having the government confiscate it through taxation. I thought that public schools were run more like prisons and indoctrination centers than learning institutions, and that they should be privatized, and all associated property taxation ended. Indeed, if people were actually supposed to own their houses, how could they be taxed? I didn’t identify with either Republicans or Democrats. I settled for considering myself politically independent. I had no idea what I would do when I became old enough to vote. When I did get there, I did nothing. Based on my beliefs, there seemed no method of voting consistent with my principles.

But in 1994, I chanced upon an article written by one Sean Glennon in a free newspaper published in New Hampshire called Seacoast Times. Glennon was a far leftist, but the piece was about drug legalization, so it held my interest. In it, Glennon made mention of the fact that the LIbertarian candidate for governor, Steve Winter, was in favor of ending the drug war. This intrigued me. So much, in fact, that I looked up the Libertarian Party of New Hampshire’s toll-free number in the phone book (the Internet was still in its infancy), and left a message requesting an information package. A few days later, a large envelope showed up in the mail. By the time I was done reading all the material therein, I had come to what was for me, at the time, a revelation. All those years, I had actually been a Libertarian without knowing it.

Or, that’s what I thought.

I contacted the LPNH again, and let them know I wanted to get involved in some way. I was kind of excited. I now had some people I could vote for at election time, and a vehicle to advance the philosophy I had always, for the most part, embraced: The Libertarian Party. I went on to become Communications Director, won more media coverage for the LPNH than had accrued in all the prior years of their existence, and was awarded Activist of the Year in 1998.

But there were still some unresolved problems.

Probably the most daunting one was how to reconcile libertarian philosophy with the existence of government. Because, of course, if one follows the non-aggression principle to its ultimate (and only logical) conclusion, no government – not even a miniscule one – can function without the implementation of coercive force. This seemed paradoxical to the notion of a political party attempting to get candidates elected in order to then legislate into existence greater freedom. I wrestled with this concept for some time. I talked with a lot of other liberty-minded people. I questioned, then questioned again, my core beliefs. There were a lot of great books on the subject I now realize I should have been reading, but that didn’t come until later. Things all came to a head for me in 2000 when, at the LPNH’s annual convention, I publicly confronted the late, great Harry Browne on an issue which similarly challenged his candidacy for U.S. President, and the Libertarian Party’s fundamental integrity. As a result of that somewhat discomfiting tableau, I resigned from any and all participation in politics, including voting altogether. I realized that I had become a true libertarian in the purest sense. I had become an anarchist. Or if you prefer, as many do, a Voluntaryist – a believer in non-aggression and peaceful willing relationships amongst human beings instead of the imposed violence governments bring to bear against individuals. I now believe I am on the correct path in doing my part to bring about a truly free and prosperous society. I warmly invite one and all to join me.

Voluntaryism and The Art of Being Free


By Carl Watner

Before beginning this book review, I must reveal my own bias. My personal friendship and intellectual acquaintance with Wendy McElroy goes back three decades, and was rooted in the creation of The Voluntaryist, whose first issue was published in October 1982. George Smith, Wendy McElroy, and I were co-founders of the newsletter, and it is the guise under which nearly all of my own writing and advocacy have appeared for the last thirty years.

What should one expect from a book of essays written by Wendy McElroy? Although she only uses the word ‘voluntaryism’ once in the entire book (p. 221 as I recall), the chapters in this book revolve around her “deep conviction that there is something sacrosanct about the individual.” (vii) The idea that everyone must “live with self-respect according to [his or] her own values” (ix) forms the underlying theme for all its contents. That, in fact, is what voluntaryism is all about: respecting the self-ownership that each person brings into the world with his or her birth.

In Section I, “The Theoretical Footing of Freedom,” Wendy offers four essays dealing with natural law, natural rights, the differences between state and society, and an explanation of why social engineering is inherently coercive and ultimately unable to plan for all the vicissitudes of life. A legislative or bureaucratic plan either has a reasonable and persuasive basis, or it does not. The fact that at least some people have to be coerced into following the government plan is proof enough to show that government arguments are not sufficiently reasonable to convince them. True, such recalcitrant people, may themselves be ignorant, greedy, or simply stubborn, but is that any reason to “force” them to obey the law, so long as they themselves are not coercing others? Paraphrasing Wendy (35), the main practical benefit of a decision-making system based on individual choice, as opposed to one based on central government dictates, is that individuals may quickly adjust to localized, changing circumstances. Government bureaucrats, far from the field of action, not only do not know what is going on, but when they find out, the chain of command is unable to change course very quickly. Neither individual owners nor government personnel know the future, and for that very reason it is far safer to let individual owners fend for themselves rather than to be directed by a central planning bureau. If the government plan goes wrong, the whole country suffers. Under individual planning, it is unlikely that all owners will all make the same unwise decision(s) at the same time. Disasters are far less tumultuous when planning is not centralized and monopolized by the government.

Section II of The Art of Being is a group of chapters on “the issues,” and includes discussions of the Industrial Revolution, unions, public education, the drug war, passports, the constitutionality of the federal post office, contempt of court, and war. As you may imagine she conveys her individualist outlook on all these subjects and shows why voluntary interaction always trumps forced behavior. Many of these topics have been discussed in the pages of The Voluntaryist, but one of the most interesting has not. What should be the responsibility of parents to support their under-age children? In “The Return of Debtors’ Prison” Wendy discusses what the American legal system has settled on: “civil imprisonment for nonpayment of child support.” Tens, if not hundreds, of thousands of deadbeat parents are incarcerated each year on charges of civil contempt because they have not made court-ordered payments. The fact that they do not have income or assets to make these payments is often irrelevant.

Section III is titled “Principles Work Through People,” in which she introduces “some of the historical friends from whom [she has] drawn insight” and inspiration. (129) Her first subject, Etienne de La Boetie (1530-1563) was often mentioned in the early days of The Voluntaryist. It was he who first identified the voluntaryist insight: that every tyranny is grounded upon general popular acceptance. In short, the bulk of the people themselves, for whatever reason, must acquiesce in their own subjection. All oppression demands the cooperation and compliance of its victims. Oppression cannot operate without the sanction of its victims, and if their consent is withdrawn, State power must disintegrate. As Wendy concludes her essay, she points out that La Boetie in effect told people “Refuse both violence [trying to fight the tyrant militarily and] submission. Simply say ‘No’.”

Other essays in this section deal with the French enlightenment thinker, Voltaire (1694-1778), the transcendentalist, Henry David Thoreau (1817-1862), the abolitionist, William Lloyd Garrison (1805-1879), and Raymond Cyrus Hoiles (1878-1970) founder of Freedom Newspapers chain and defender of the Japanese-Americans during their internment in World War II. Here one finds the never-before-told story of how Hoiles stood up for the constitutional rights of the Japanese living in Orange County, California. It is in these three later articles, that we begin to find the thread that helps bind this book together. Many know the story of Thoreau’s one night stay in Concord jail. Wendy labels Thoreau’s protest as “an act of conscience.” (155) “The individual and his conscience is the final judge of right and wrong.” (157) Although Wendy mentions Thoreau’s opposition to slavery, she does not mention his friendship with Charles Lane and Bronson Alcott, both of whom set a precedent for Thoreau and who were arrested for non-payment of their poll taxes in 1843. All three were abolitionists and undoubtedly would have agreed with the sentiments of William Lloyd Garrison which Wendy quotes:

I believe in the spirit of peace, and in sole and absolute reliance on truth and the application of it to the hearts and consciences of the people. I do not believe that the weapons of liberty ever have been, or ever can be, the weapons of despotism. I know that those of despotism are the sword, the revolver, the cannon, the bomb-shell; and, therefore, the weapons to which tyrants cling, and upon which they depend, are not the weapons for me, as a friend of liberty. (177)

The final section of The Art of Being Free ties the book together by showing how to “get from there to here.” Wendy suggests that we focus upon things in our own backyard: “concentrate on grassroots movements in which … individuals make an incredible difference.” (200) This can be in such areas as homeschooling, the father’s rights movement, protecting one’s privacy through encryption, barter groups, and the use of alternative currencies. In discussing Hannah Arendt’s Eichmann in Jerusalem, Wendy points out that for many Germans under the Nazi regime, “the law assumed the role that conscience plays in other people. It told them what is right or wrong, and they obeyed,” not realizing that in in reality they were causing harm and death to innocent people (211). The American military police and soldiers who rounded up the peaceful Japanese in America during World War II were doing the same thing: accepting what the government told them to; not questioning what was right or wrong – in other words, just following orders. As she points out, in contrast, a century earlier, Thoreau held that “every human being has a fundamental obligation to discover for himself what is just and then to act according to his conscience, even if it contradicts the majority or the law. It is precisely his moral conscience that makes a man fully human … .” (212) Reminiscent of La Boetie, Wendy writes: “The words most feared by those in authority are ‘I won’t‘,” and “No.” (218) Suppose those Germans and Americans had simply refused to do what they were ordered to do. They probably would have been jailed, but then suppose those who were told to jail them said, “No,” too. What a chain of consequences that would entail!

Perhaps Wendy planned it this way, but the two best chapters of her book are those at the end. The next to last chapter is the very intriguing story of “Boycott: A Nonviolent Revolt.” In a chapter that should be reprinted in The Voluntaryist, Wendy lays out the history of the boycott, from its initial attempt to ostracize Captain Boycott, overseer for an absentee landlord in Ireland in 1880, to its expansion via secondary boycotts, blacklists, peer pressure groups, and in a wide variety of economic boycotts ranging from withdrawal of bank deposits to non-consumption and/or non-importation of certain products. In short, Wendy concludes that the boycott is a “nonviolent, non-political” strategy with the potential for bringing about true social change without involving the government.

In her “Conclusion,” Wendy sums up The Art of Being Free by focusing again on the important message that Henry David Thoreau sends us in his essay “On the Duty of Civil Disobedience.” Thoreau asked himself a question that has appeared in The Voluntaryist numerous times: where do you draw the line and refuse to cooperate with the State? Here is how Wendy answers that question:

There is no duty to confront the state except when it seeks to make you an active accomplice in the oppression of others. Those who stand up against the injustice of others are to be applauded. But they should not do so at the expense of their primary duty: to live deeply and honestly. This duty involves pushing back or walking away (when possible) from the areas of life in which the state commands jurisdiction. (245-246)

Some may disagree with Wendy and say this is impossible, and in some cases, it may be because State agents refuse to leave you alone. Bob LeFevre was fond of saying, “the free man will find a way to be free.” Implicit in Bob’s observation was the fact that there is a difference between physical liberty and spiritual freedom. Even a person whom the State has imprisoned may remain free in spirit if he or she refuses to submit. The difference between a prisoner and a slave is this: the former refuses to submit and is placed in an iron cage; the slave is allowed his liberty because his or her spirit is in illusory chains of his or her own making. This difference is exemplified in the story of the Stoic who was captured and tortured in order to make him renounce his beliefs. He told his captors that they could do whatever they wished with his body, but that they could not injure his philosophy. “That was in his mind and their authority, in its physical … aspect, did not extend to that.” (see Issue 17 of The Voluntaryist, page 4) “Know the truth and the truth shall make you free,” or as The People’s New Testament puts it, “The way to know the truth is to obey the truth.” (John 8:32) Live life in accordance with your conscience, and the world is bound to be a better place. That’s the message of The Art of Being Free.

[The Art of Being Free was published 2012 by Laissez Faire Books, 800 St. Paul Street, Baltimore, MD. See www.LaissezFaireBooks.com. All numbers in parentheses within this review refer to page numbers in the paperback edition.]

What Is the Point of My Libertarian Anarchism?


By Robert Higgs

 

In college in the 1960s I was not a political person. Although I took a keen interest in politics, especially in the war that was raging in Vietnam, I concentrated on my studies, earning a living, and chasing women. After I began work as a professor, in 1968, I gravitated quickly from my collegiate New Leftism toward classical liberalism. As I learned more about Austrian economics, political economy, public choice, and history, I became increasingly libertarian (minarchist variety). My views continued to evolve, however, and by the time the 21st century arrived, if not sooner, I had finally reached my destination as a libertarian anarchist.

Although I make no apology whatever for this ideological identity, I do not share the seeming expectation of some of my fellow libertarian anarchists that a revolution is now, or soon will be, occurring in the direction of my preferred political ideals. Indeed, my expectation is, if anything, the reverse: it seems to me much more likely that the USA will continue to drift and lurch toward totalitarianism, though this system will surely have a unique red, white, and blue coloration to suit the American people’s history, culture, and tastes. I do not expect a dictator with a funny little mustache and a horde of brown-shirted thugs to take power after smashing heads in the streets. I expect instead an elected dictator who looks like George W. Bush or Barack Obama and a horde of police dressed in riot-suppression gear to turn the trick, though most people will not need to have their heads smashed and will go along gladly.

If I comprehend the world in this way, what, some people wonder, am I doing by embracing libertarian anarchism? Well, I am obviously not taking this position in order to come out on the winning side. If that were my goal, I would already have found a way to make myself useful in the military-industrial-congressional complex. No, I have put myself where I am now somewhat as Martin Luther did when he announced: “Here I stand. I can do no other.”

In my case, this declaration means most of all that I am simply doing what seems to me the decent thing; that taking any other ideological position would entangle me in evils of which I want no part. Although I sincerely believe that a stateless world would be better than the present world in countless ways, such as better health, greater wealth, and enhanced material well-being, I am not a libertarian anarchist primarily on consequentialist grounds, but instead primarily because I believe it is wrong for anyone–including those designated the rulers and their functionaries–to engage in fraud, extortion, robbery, torture, and murder. I do not believe that I have a defensible right to engage in such acts; nor do I believe that I, or anyone else, may delegate to government officials a just right to do what it is wrong for me–or you or anyone–to do as a private person.

Still, one might ask, if I do not expect that my vision of a just world can ever be realized, why do I persist in evaluating the events of the nasty “real world” by the standards realizable only in my ideal world? The answer is that everyone must have an ideal; without one, there is no standard against which one may assess the imperfect actions and events of the actual world. Without a standard, one may only shrug his shoulders, like a character in an existentialist novel, in nonchalant indifference to the political wickedness raging on all sides. Just as a devout Christian seeks to live a Christ-like life, knowing full well that no one can live up to the standard set by Jesus, so I aim to live and to make my judgments of the events I hear about in the light of the nonaggression axiom. The initiation of violence or the threat of violence against innocent others is wrong, regardless of the noble ends that one might cite to justify such violence or threat. It is wrong for me, wrong for you, and wrong for the president of the USA and his flunkies.

Like the Christian who inevitably falls into sin, I may fall short of my ideal. I may act or speak inconsistently with it. Many public issues are complicated, and in regard to them I may fail to discern the best way to act in accordance with my ideological ideal. If you let me know about my inconsistency, I can attempt to set aside my pride, admit my error, and correct it. As new issues arise, the task of sorting out the best way to deal with the most pressing problems will present itself repeatedly. Perhaps, like St. Paul in his letters to the new churches of the ancient world, we can strive to instruct one another in the most defensible understanding and practice of libertarian anarchism. Merely shouting that the existing order is rotten, is on the verge of collapse and, once it has collapsed, will be replaced by libertarian anarchism, however, seems to me so hopelessly naive that I am inclined to urge my ideological comrades who do such shouting to get a firmer grip on themselves. One needs to combine his moral uprightness with a solidly founded understanding of the social, political, and economic world and how it works. Otherwise, our statements and actions become hopelessly quixotic.

I do not expect to live to see a world that even approximates my ideal. In fact, I greatly fear that I shall instead live long enough to see the most obscene species of police state in the saddle in the USA–after all, there is now only a short distance to go to reach this horrible destination, and many Americans seem eager to get to it as soon as possible. Nevertheless, I am comfortable with my ideological convictions. To have embraced anything else would have been a great mistake for me. I took almost a lifetime to reach my current position; I did not come to it lightly or without extended study and thought. Of course, I may still be wrong in every regard; I am a human being, and as such I am certainly subject to running off the moral and intellectual rails. I do not propose to be paralyzed by this universal human susceptibility to error, however. Feeling the need to take a stand of some kind as a participant in the events of my time and place, I have put myself firmly where I now stand. By the light I have been given to see the right, I can do no other.

[This originally appeared on www.badquaker.com/archives/1315.]

The Noose Continues to Tighten But No Government Lasts Forever


By Carl Watner

Voluntaryists have a unique outlook on government. They view the State as an invasive institution. It imposes a coercive monopoly over defense services and collects its revenues via compulsory taxation. Theodore Lowi, a professor of political science at Cornell University in the early 1980s, authored a book, INCOMPLETE CONQUEST (1981), in which he observed:

Every action and every agency of contemporary government must contribute to the fulfillment of its fundamental purpose, which is to maintain conquest. Conquest manifests itself in various forms of control, but in all those forms it is the common factor tying together in one system the behavior of courts and cops, sanitation workers and senators, bureaucrats and technocrats, generals and attorney generals, pressure groups and presidents. [p. 13]

Two of the most basic “forms of control” exercised by any government are that of demanding enrollment in its armed forces, and in collecting taxes based on one’s income and/or accumulated wealth. Perhaps conscription is the State’s most direct control over your life, but its ability to tax ultimately destroys the principle of private ownership. Everything you think you “own” is really held subject to its pleasure. It is as though you are a slave and your master allows you to retain certain perks.

In my article, “The Chickens Come Home to Roost – The Master Plan for ‘Tightening the Noose'” (Issue 48, February 1991), I referred to the late Fred Rowe, who wrote an article for his House of Onyx publication entitled “The IRS Electronic Monster.” Rowe set forth his predictions about the future state of economic freedoms in these United States. He described what he called an IRS “master plan” under which the United States government would push toward the creation of a cashless society. Electronic money would take the place of banknotes, and all financial transactions would be recorded via computers, which in turn would be connected to those of the IRS. The tax bureaucracy would then take this information and render every citizen and resident of the United States a tax return. Withholding on all income from your labor, and on all major financial transactions, such as the sale of real estate and investments, would enable the government to collect taxes on a mostly “pay-as-you-go” basis. Such computer transparency would also make it very difficult for tax resisters to escape the government’s clutching hand.

Whether or not such a conspiratorial master plan was ever hatched by government bureaucrats, the unceasing efforts of government to take control of its citizens’ property have continued unabated. Some of the steps in this never-ending battle for conquest and control have been:

…requirements that most people born in the United States have government-issued birth certificates;

…passage of the 16th Amendment to the U.S. Constitution authorizing Congress to tax income;

…requirements that a government social security number be used in conjunction with all large financial transactions and in filing tax returns;

…reporting all domestic cash transactions of $ 3,000 or more to the U.S. Treasury

…attempting to require that payments to individuals of $ 600 or more be reported via 1099 Forms to the Internal Revenue Service;

…requirements to report to the U.S. Treasury and/or U.S. Customs movements of more than $ 10,000 cash and certain other negotiable instruments to and from the U.S.

…requirement that applicants provide a social security number on passport applications, and upon refusal being fined $ 500 by the Internal Revenue Service;

…requirements to report the existence of foreign-held bank accounts and foreign-held assets;

…requirement that anyone renouncing their U.S. citizenship for reasons of avoiding U.S. taxes be liable for U.S. taxes for the 10 years following their renunciation;

…requirement that all employers within the United States verify the eligibility of prospective hires, who, of course, must have a government social security number; [see “Countdown to Extinction,” THE VOLUNTARYIST No. 68, June 1994, page 3 for further information]

Now the government is working out some new regulations that affect both our property and our bodies. The Obama care health care legislation mandates that most people in the United States purchase health insurance or pay a penalty. Its constitutionality has been argued before the Supreme Court. Increasingly, doctors are no longer able to abide by the Hippocratic Oath because third-party payers (mostly the government through Medicare and Medicaid, but also insurance companies) make health decisions for their patients. It is no longer between the doctor and patient to determine what is the best treatment. The decision is up to the party paying for that treatment. Furthermore, physicians have been ordered “to adopt electronic health records or face economic sanctions from Medicare.” The Federal Commission for the Coordination of Comparative Effectiveness Research will determine the “most-cost effective way of allocating a fixed amount of resources among” the U.S. population. [See “Notable & Quotable,” THE WALL STREET JOURNAL, March 17-18, 2012, p. A13]

The government is also tightening the regulations surrounding the ownership of foreign bank accounts and the reporting of assets held abroad. For all practical purposes there has never been any financial or banking privacy in the United States. Currently the governments of the United States, France, Germany, Italy, Spain, and the United Kingdom have joined together in cooperation to intensify their efforts to combat international tax evasion. On March 10, 2010, the United States enacted the Foreign Account Tax Compliance Act (FATCA). This legislation introduced reporting requirements for foreign financial institutions (FFIs). Many banks headquartered abroad are required to identify U.S. account holders, report certain information to the IRS about their accounts, and assess a 30% withholding tax on certain payments of U.S. source income to recalcitrant account holders or non-participating FFIs that are unwilling to provide the necessary information. In short, great pressure is being brought to bear on banks that are not subject to U.S. jurisdiction to subjugate them to IRS regulations. Some foreign banks, particularly those in Switzerland, have decided to terminate their account relationships with U.S. citizens so as to avoid these entanglements with U.S. law.

All this is reminiscent of what Nazi Germany did to its citizens in the years before World War II. Consider these National Socialist laws:

The decisive sign that the Nazis had turned their sights on the assets of Germans abroad was the law against economic sabotage enacted in December 1936. In part this was aimed at enticing Germans to repatriate their foreign nest-eggs: those prepared to admit they had assets abroad could keep a third of them after they handed over the remaining two-thirds to the Reichsbank, … ‘Any German national who knowingly and having as a motive acts against the law in transferring assets abroad or keeps them abroad and thereby damages the German economy is punished with death’.”[Nicholas Faith, SAFETY IN NUMBERS: THE MYSTERIOUS WORLD OF SWISS BANKING, New York: The Viking Press, 1982, pp. 83-84]

[P]ursuant to the Decree on the Registration of the Property of the Jews of April 26, 1938, all Jews were required to value all their assets (foreign and domestic) and register them if their value was in excess of RM 5,000. [“Expropriation (Aryanization) of Jewish Property,” General, www.edwardvictor.com/

Holocaust/expropriation)

As reported in THE WALL STREET JOURNAL on April 6, 2012 [p. A9], “hiding money in [tax] havens isn’t as easy as it used to be.” The U.S. Congress has “passed laws imposing draconian penalties on people hiding foreign financial assets.” How do the following U.S. government regulations compare to those of Nazi Germany?

A person who holds a foreign financial account may have a reporting obligation even though the account produces no taxable income. … The FBAR (Report of Foreign Bank and Financial Accounts) is not filed with the filer’s federal income tax return. [From IRS.gov: Report of Foreign Bank and Financial Accounts (FBAR) page on the internet]

The principal purpose for collecting the information [required by Department of the Treasury Form TD F 90-22.1 – “Report of Foreign Bank and Financial Accounts”] is to assure maintenance of reports where such reports or records have a high degree of usefulness in criminal, tax, or regulatory investigations or proceedings. … Disclosure of this information is mandatory. Civil and criminal penalties, including in certain circumstances a fine of not more than $ 500,000 and imprisonment of not more than five years, are provided for failure to file a report, supply information, and for filing a false or fraudulent report. Disclosure of the Social Security number is mandatory. [From TD F 90-22.1, 2nd paragraph of the “Privacy Act and Paperwork Reduction Act Note.”]

The Internal Revenue Service also has other reporting requirements to be found in Part III (Foreign Accounts and Trusts) of Schedule B, Form 1040, as well as on Form 8938, Statement of Specified Foreign Financial Assets. A Bloomberg.com news report of August 3, 2011 demonstrates that the IRS means business. Robert E. Greely, who “pleaded guilty to filing a false U.S. tax return that concealed more than $ 13 million in two Swiss” bank accounts, “agreed to pay a civil penalty of $ 6.8 million for failing to file a Report of Foreign Bank and Financial Account form.” [“Former UBS Client Greely Admits to Hiding More than $ 13 Million From IRS by David Voreacos; citing U.S. v. Greely, 11-cr-374, U.S. District Court, Northern District of California (San Francisco)]

Why exactly are such assets of concern to the federal government, and why is the “failure to report” foreign assets a crime if it is not illegal to own them? The answer is to be found in the invasive nature of government. Governments demand obedience to their rules and regulations, whatever they may be. Governments also have an insatiable appetite for tax revenues. And furthermore, many governments have a record of confiscating the known assets of their citizens. Although the United States government has never required surrender of assets held abroad, it did confiscate all gold coins and gold bullion in 1933, and outlawed the ownership of gold by American citizens regardless of where it was located. But why would a citizen break the laws of the United States? An American might have several reasons. A person might be a conscientious objector against taxation. A citizen might think that foreign assets would be safe from seizure by the American government because they are outside its domestic jurisdiction. The citizen might also think that having assets abroad would provide a nest egg in case of the need to live abroad. Having foreign assets might provide a means to escape from government agents. During the Nazi era, how many German dissidents or German Jews would have been grateful to have had money outside of Germany, and how much easier would it have then been to leave Germany and escape the Gestapo?

There have been numerous books and articles comparing Nazi Germany and the United States of America. Leonard Peikoff”s 1982 book, THE OMINOUS PARALLELS, was subtitled “the end of freedom in America.” Naomi Wolf’s more recent publication, THE END OF AMERICA (2007) highlighted “the ten key steps that would-be despots take” when they assume control of a country. These include many that have already occurred in the Untied States:

…invoking the threat of internal and/or external dangers;

…establishing secret prisons where torture takes place;

…building paramilitary forces;

…creating a surveillance apparatus aimed at ordinary citizens;

…infiltrating citizen groups and organizations in an effort to disrupt their activities;

…arbitrarily arresting and detaining citizens and aliens;

…targeting key individuals who criticize the government and destroying their reputations;

…censoring and restricting the press;

…disparaging criticism of the government as “espionage” and dissent as “treason;”

…subverting the rule of law by ignoring constitutional provisions and due process.

No one can foretell how far these trends will affect the future, but they seem to reflect Carroll Quigley’s 1966 prediction: Man’s “freedom and choice will be controlled within very narrow alternatives by the fact that he will be numbered from birth and followed, as a number, through his educational training, his required military or other public service, his tax contributions, his health and medical requirements, and his final retirement and death benefits.” [p. 866] That is the tragic part of the prediction in his book’s title, TRAGEDY AND HOPE.

The hopeful part is reflected in what we can observe from history. No government lasts forever. The Nazi 1000 Year Reich was gone in less than two decades. The Union of Soviet Socialist Republics lasted less than 100 years. In western Europe, after the Roman empire disappeared, Quigley observes that by 900 A.D. there was clearly a period “when there was no empire, no state, and no public authority … . The state disappeared, yet society continued. … It was discovered that man can live without a state; … . It was discovered that economic life, religious life, law, and private property can all exist and function effectively without a state.” [p. 83] Every generation faces natural and political challenges. Despite the tightening of the political noose, our own times are not unique. Some problems are more daunting than others, but life goes on. As Robert LeFevre used to say, the free man will find a way to be free.

 

Am I An American Citizen and What Might It Mean?


By Carl Watner

 

This article was prompted by thoughts of a trip abroad and my perusal of the “Application For A U.S. Passport” (Department of State Form DS-11). On page one, the applicant is asked to “declare under penalty of perjury” that “I am a citizen … of the United States …”

Can I, as a voluntaryist, make that declaration? Can you?

First of all, what does it mean to be a citizen? What are the pros and cons of citizenship? Are they of any consequence?

The word ‘citizen’ is of Anglo-Norman and Old French origin and in the context of this article means “a member of the State.” From the perspective of the United States government, every person born within the United States has these basic duties:
..To serve in the military, if drafted;
..To pay taxes on his or her worldwide income;
..To serve as a juror and appear as a witness when subpoenaed by a court;
..To obey all the laws promulgated by local, state, and federal governments.

In return, the United States government’s primary duty towards its citizens is that of providing ‘protection’ from domestic criminals and foreign enemies. Federal, state, and local governments also provide courts, roads, postal delivery, social services, and numerous other entitlements to those living within its jurisdiction. (It generally does a poor job of providing ‘services’ and assumes no responsibility for its failures.)

The main problem with government, as voluntaryists see it, is that the State is a criminal organization. It claims sovereignty over a certain geographic area. Within this zone it wants everyone to become at least partially responsible for its crimes by making them citizens. It enforces a compulsory monopoly of defense (police, law and courts, and the armed forces), such that individual property owners may not decline its services, or employ another agency to provide the defense services they would prefer. To fund these monopolies, it collects compulsory levies known as taxation and operates a fiat money system (central bank with legal tender laws). In short, the State is an invasive institution because its existence rests on the initiation of coercion. According to the government, a person may not decline to fulfill his or her obligations to the State. You will be fined, arrested, and/or jailed, and probably held in “contempt” if government agents discover that you are not satisfactorily doing what you are supposed to do in fulfilling its mandates.

One of the ‘services’ provided by the American government is that of issuing passports and providing consular protection to those traveling outside the United States. Voluntaryists also object to the whole concept of government passports. To wit –
..They are government documents.
..They are generally required to leave the country.
..They are generally required for re-entry to the United States.
..They allow the government to track where you have been.
..They are unnecessary.

For much of American history (with the exceptions of the War Between the States, and the First and Second World Wars), no passport requirements existed. It was not until 1978 that it was made “illegal [for a U.S. citizen] to enter or depart the United States without” a passport. [Wikipedia, “United States passport”]

This is not to deny that there might be travel documents issued by private organizations in a free society. Some travelers may consider passports an essential part of life, but providing them need not be a government function. As I discussed in my article, “The Exit Option,” passports at one time were issued by notaries, and even peddlers. Furthermore, there has never been a requirement to have a passport when traveling within the United States, for example, from the East coast to the West coast. And that being the case, why should there be such a requirement when leaving El Paso, Texas for Ciudad Juarez, Mexico or from Niagara Falls, New York to Niagara Falls, Ontario? (By extension, voluntaryist logic questions why there should be any political boundaries at all.)

The whole purpose of government passports is to help the government to exercise control over its citizens, whether within or without the United States (and to generate revenue for itself in doing so).

This leads to the next question: who might be citizens of the United States?

Since many people reading this article are native-born Americans, I will only discuss the concept of birthright citizenship. This refers to people who were born within the geographical confines of the United States, and harks back to the old English common law which held that “birth and [political] allegiance go together.” [Wikipedia, “Birthright citizenship in the United States” (sub-section: “English common law”)] Citizenship law can be very complicated, so for simplicity sake, I will confine the discussion of birthright citizenship to those born within the United States of parents, who themselves, were born in the United States.

Generally, according to government interpretation, a person born within the territory of the United States is a citizen of the United States, regardless of that person’s desire. You become a citizen at birth, not when you reach adulthood, at age 18 or 21. You do not consent to become a citizen. You do not have any choice in the matter. You are simply designated a citizen! And if you wish to divest yourself of that status, you must leave the country, and formally renounce your citizenship before an American consular official outside of the United States. (And if you do this for the reason of not wanting to pay taxes to the United States government, you are still obligated to pay those taxes for another ten years from the date of your renunciation.) Jeff Knaebel, who immolated himself in India in 2011, discovered that he could not divest himself of his American nationality without assuming Indian citizenship, a fact that disconcerted him greatly. All political governments and international law discourage statelessness, which is what one becomes when one renounces one’s birthright citizenship and refuses to assume citizenship of another country. But the fact is that all people are born stateless. They certainly have not consented to become a member of any government merely by being born. If a government can unilaterally impose citizenship, then it has already assumed arbitrary jurisdiction over bodies. Perhaps that is why the Jewish zealots said that taxation (a consequence of citizenship) was no better than an introduction to slavery. If the government can assert its control over you due to the fact that you were born in an area it claims to control, then it is simply a matter of grace – on its part – as to what it allows you to do, to earn, and to keep from your efforts.

In truth and good conscience, and as a voluntaryist, I cannot affirm that I am a citizen of the United States. Why so? I don’t want to give my sanction to the United States government. I do not wish to support it financially. I do not wish to participate in political elections. I object to the forced collection of taxes because taxes are a euphemism for stealing. I do not want to be responsible for any of the actions of the United States government. Is there not a link between the crimes of the United States government and the citizens who compose it, those who pay their taxes, those who vote in elections, and serve in its armed forces? This is not to say, however, that I do not want to be a vibrant participant in the voluntary sector of the community within which I live. Communities have always existed before governments, and there are many peaceful ways of providing for the demands of society in the absence of the State (private business activity, co-operative societies, religious supported institutions, and philanthropic efforts, to name just a few).

So what does it mean to be an American citizen? Is an American citizen a slave of his government? A slave is a person who is “the property of another,” a person who is “bound to absolute obedience.” The status of a slave is not a matter of choice. A slave has the major decisions of his or her life made by his or her owner. Must a citizen fight in wars declared by the American government? Must a citizen risk his or her life to defend it? Must a citizen kill those whom the government labels “enemies”? Must a citizen support the American government by paying its tax bill(s)? Is there any limit to the amount it may demand? Must a citizen be forced against his or her will to serve as a juror or as a witness in criminal or civil legal proceedings? And finally, must a citizen obey the government’s laws, many of which are inane, insane, or simply against his or her conscience? The government’s answers to these questions are obviously, “Yes,” though a person may choose to say “No,” and refuse to follow its orders. Ultimately, if enough of us speak out and say “No,” the government will lose its legitimacy.

The American government can call me anything it wants, but that does not make it so. It can label me an American citizen, but it forgets that I have a say in the matter. In my own mind and in my own person I refuse to be subservient and accept its jurisdiction over me. That is why I am not an American citizen.

 

Articles of Further Interest

“If This Be Treason, Make the Most of It!” The Voluntaryist, Issue 30, February 1988.
“The Exit Option,” The Voluntaryist, Issue 37, April 1989.
“Conflicts of Allegiance,” The Voluntaryist, Issue 37, April 1989.
“Man Without a Country,” The Voluntaryist, Issue 49, April 1991.
“Citizenship Papers,” by Clark Hanjian, The Voluntaryist, Issue 49, April 1991.
“Patriotism or Voluntaryism? – ‘Anywhere So Long As There Be Freedom’,” The Voluntaryist, Issue 66. February 1994.
“Why I Refuse to Be Numbered,” The Voluntaryist, Issue 116, 1st Quarter 2003.
“The Territorial Imperative: Rationale for Conquest,” The Voluntaryist, Issue 133, 2nd Quarter 2007.
“Slavery and National ID” in NATIONAL IDENTIFICATION SYSTEMS (2004).

 

Freedom to Choose Your Own Money


By Carl Watner

 

1) Should the Federal Reserve System be abolished?

2) If so, what monetary system should take its place?

My answers to these questions are:
(1) No, the Federal Reserve System should not be abolished. If some people want to continue to use Federal Reserve notes as money they should be able to do so. However, they should not be able to impose their choice on others.

and

(2) The only monetary system to take the place of Federal Reserve notes, if they were to fall into disuse, should be a voluntary one; a monetary system in which people freely choose what they use for money.

These may seem surprising and even contradictory responses, so please read on to understand my reasons for answering this way.

Money is a commodity people use to facilitate their exchanges with other people. Economists refer to money as a commonly used medium of exchange. For long periods of history, money has usually been characterized by having a large value relative to its bulk and weight; by being homogeneous (one part being just like every other part); by being easily divisible into smaller parts (with each smaller unit retaining its proportional value to the whole); by being durable (not easily destroyed); and by generally maintaining its exchange value relative to other desirable things.

In a free society, the production of money would be a matter left to private enterprise. Money producers would compete with one another to offer the best product at the lowest cost. Such a system would be devoid of State coercion and government interference. The law of natural displacement (the best money will be used by traders and will displace less suitable ones) would minimize useless innovations because people would only accept new forms of money if they saw value in the improvements offered. Monetary freedom means that whatever is chosen for money must be able to survive on its own merits. A money that people must be forced to use has already lost its credibility. If the money the government wants people to use and accept had any inherent advantages over other monies, then there would be no reason to pass laws that force them to use it.

Just as there is more than one kind of credit card and payment system, e.g., Visa, MasterCard, PayPal, etc., there could be more than one kind of money, each touting its advantages to the end user. No one can tell in advance what form these monies might take because no one can know for sure what choices individuals would make or what new technologies might be discovered. Laws forcing people to use the Federal Reserve System money have frozen monetary developments at a certain stage. There is no way to determine the advances that might have occurred due to the government’s discouragement of competition. Just imagine if Congress had protected the Post Office by passing laws that would have prevented people from communicating via the internet. We would never have experienced the marvels of e-mail. What we do know, however, is that ever since the Civil War between the States, the federal government has successfully prosecuted competing providers of money. As recently as 2011, the principal of NORFED, the National Organization for the Repeal of the Federal Reserve, was convicted of violating the provisions of 18 United States Code, Sections 2, 371, 485, 486 and 1341, which prohibit the creation of “private coin or currency systems [designed] to compete with the official coinage and currency of the United States” government. At the conclusion of the trial, the United States Attorney for the Western District of North Carolina, Anne T. Tompkins, issued a press release (March 18, 2011), reiterating the government’s harsh attitude in suppressing potential competition: Attempts to undermine the legitimate currency of this country are simply a unique form of domestic terrorism. While these forms of anti-government activities do not involve violence, they are every bit as insidious and represent a clear and present danger to the economic stability of this country.

Despite the government’s claims to the contrary, it is not necessary that money be provided by government or that there be only one monetary system in place. Gold and silver were commonly used media of exchange for centuries. No person or institution has the right to prevent people from using their property and exchanging it in a peaceful manner. The history of private gold coinage in the United States shows what happened when the government was not there to force people to trade with a certain type of money. It was a natural right of the miner to pan or dig for gold. He could coin whatever precious metals he found so long as he did not counterfeit or imitate the coin of the United States government. Congress, at the time, did not believe it had the power to prohibit him from weighing and assaying his pieces of gold, marking upon them their weight and fineness, and exchanging them for whatever other people were willing to give for them. In Rutherfordton, North Carolina members of the Bechtler family coined over $ 2 million of gold between 1831 and 1840; in Denver, Colorado the Clark & Gruber mint produced over $ 500,000 of gold coins between 1859 and 1863, and in California immediately after the 1849 Gold Rush there were numerous private issues of coin and ingots. During this time, the common law right of the private coiner to issue gold coins was fully recognized by both the public which used them and the government that tolerated them.

When exchanges take place they are either voluntary or coerced. No voluntary exchange takes place unless both parties expect to better themselves. When people are forced to trade, it is obvious that their best interests (as they define them) are not being served. Coerced exchanges only benefit one party at the expense of the other. This, in fact, is just what happens when people are forced to use Federal Reserve notes in their daily transactions. But because they are so accustomed to this form of government intervention in their lives, very few people recognize the government’s threat of violence or the economic disutility arising from the use of force. Political controls and struggles over money and credit have continually disrupted our society from its very inception and have made economic calculation increasingly difficult. As Gustav Stolper pointed out in his 1942 book, THIS AGE OF FABLE, “A ‘free’ capitalism with government responsibility for money and credit has lost its innocence. From that point on it is no longer a matter of principle but one of expediency how far one wishes or permits governmental interference to go. Money control is the supreme and most comprehensive of all governmental controls short of expropriation.”

Now all this has been offered by way of showing why we should not have a governmental system of money. But why argue that the Federal Reserve System should not be abolished? Because if a voluntary monetary system is to be achieved it must be brought about in a peaceful, voluntary way. If most people are wedded to a money produced and operated by a quasi-government institution with powers to enforce coercive legal tender laws and a government monopoly over the production of money, then to “demolish, destroy, or put an end” to that system against their wishes would only result in the erection of another similar system in its place. A voluntary money system cannot be forced upon people. It must come about naturally, over time, as the result of millions of freely-made individual choices and exchanges.

The Federal Reserve System will only be replaced permanently if people come to understand the morality and practicality of a voluntary system. When a sufficient number of them recognize its merits, then instead of abolishing the Federal Reserve System, they will simply abandon it in favor of using better money. At that point, laws supporting the Federal Reserve would be rendered ineffective by people’s refusal to obey them. In such a situation, it would become nearly impossible for the government to prosecute, convict, and imprison all those who refuse to handle Federal Reserve notes.

Not only is it inconsistent to force men to be free, but people who have been forced to be free do not understand why they should accept personal responsibility for their own lives. Button-pushing (as in pushing the button to abolish the Federal Reserve System) would probably result in chaos because most people would still be looking to government to produce the money they use. To abolish is to resort to compulsion, and the free man does not force others to be free. The free man controls himself. He decides what he shall use for money. He recognizes the right of others to choose how they will live. This includes their freedom to choose what they will use for money.

[The above essay was submitted to the 2011 Thorpe Writing Competition c/o the Foundation for Economic Education.]

My Winding Road to Voluntaryism


By Ned Netterville

 

First, about my name. It’s a pseudonym. I use it to remain anonymous whenever I publicly mention my participation in Alcoholics Anonymous, as I do here. As you shall see, Alcoholics Anonymous, a completely voluntary institution, has played a pivotal role in my life. [Footnote 1] Beginning in my teens, I embarked on a fruitless, 30-year quest to sample every alcoholic beverage the world has to offer. Fortuitously, I was forced by the exigencies of the drinking life to surrender and join AA at the ripe age of forty-five after indulging in a considerable variety of booze, however only a small fraction of the world’s total offerings. It is apparent to me in retrospect that alcohol dependency is incompatible with the degree of individual liberty afforded and the personal responsibility required by voluntaryism.

My first introduction to voluntaryism occurred in the early 1990s. I had written an article for Jacob (Bumper) Hornberger’s FREEDOM DAILY, in which I asserted that the American colonies’ Continental Army was an all-volunteer force that defeated the British – the superpower of the day – without recourse to taxation or conscription. Carl Watner wrote a courteous letter to the editor pointing out that several of the colonies had in fact employed taxation and conscription to provide men and equipment to Washington’s revolutionary forces. Bumper forwarded Carl’s letter to me. After checking out his contention, I wrote him acknowledging my error and thanking him for his correction. Carl then graciously gave me a subscription to THE VOLUNTARYIST. I soon bought a copy of his book-length anthology of articles from earlier issues of THE VOLUNTARYIST entitled, I MUST SPEAK OUT. When I finished it, I chucked my pocket copy of the Constitution in the waste basket and became a voluntaryist. His book remains on my shelves as a valuable reference and an inspiration, which I need from time to time as I once needed to drink.

I was born in 1937, and grew up as one of five boys in a rather chauvinistic, somewhat insular, Irish-Catholic social network in the Cleveland, Ohio, area. My father was a street-smart, over-the-counter stock trader who took a year off high school after his father died to help with family finances. In the midst of the Great Depression (1933), he used his small savings, hocked my mom’s engagement and wedding rings, borrowed money from several of his retail-brokerage clients, and purchased a junior partnership in a startup broker-dealer firm, which he eventually owned outright.

Growing prosperous from his successful stock-market business, Dad provided a better-than-middle-class living for his five boys, who all went to work for his firm after college. My mom, the loving center of our young lives, supplied the glue that held the family together to this day, although she has passed away. Her principled adherence to her Catholic moral values undoubtedly saved me from even more trouble than I managed to get into as a rebellious adolescent.

As far back as I can remember, I hated school and any form of discipline. Apparently I suffered from what is now diagnosed as ODD – oppositional defiance disorder. I played hooky often. Two schools asked me to leave before I matriculated. Mom had to tutor me to get me through every math class. I’m sure the idea of homeschooling never occurred to mom, but she would have been a good teacher, and I might have become a good student much earlier in life if she had. It wasn’t until my sophomore year in college that I discovered a few subjects I liked and began attaining As and Bs instead of Cs and Ds. I switched my major from Forestry to English and took all of my electives in economics and finance. Unfortunately, the economics department at Miami University (Ohio) was and still is Keynesian, which isn’t really economics. Today I believe Austrian-school economics (AE) is the only brand that makes sense.

After graduating in 1960, I joined the Ohio National Guard in order to avoid being drafted into the Army for two years. I immediately spent six months on active “duty” attached to the U.S. Army. It never occurred to me that I could resist the draft, which today I consider to be the only moral way to approach military service. I spent my Army time doing everything in my power to avoid work (“duty?”). After basic training, I spent every weekday afternoon and evening in the PX drinking beer, and the weekend leaves in bars in Washington, D.C. It would be virtually impossible for a person to be less productive of value than I was those six months.

I spent the rest of the 1960s working for Dad as a proprietary stock trader, eventually becoming responsible for all trading and customer order executions. Sometime during the late 60s I came across and accepted the Foundation for Economic Education’s (FEE’s) offer of a free subscription to THE FREEMAN magazine. That wonderful journal introduced me to the principles of liberty through articles by Leonard Read, Ludwig von Mises, Hans Sennholz, James Payne and other great libertarian voices.

In January 1971, I “dropped out” of the securities business to “do my own thing,” a not-uncommon practice for that era of Vietnam-induced national angst. I traveled to Australia and New Zealand with a vague notion of immigrating, but found both countries too far down the road to socialism for my taste. I eventually purchased and operated a one-hundred year old cider mill and apple processing business and moved from suburban Cleveland to rural northeastern Ohio.

1971 was a watershed year for me in many ways. One of the company benefits I had when I worked for Dad’s firm was free, professional income-tax-return preparation by the firm’s CPA. In ’71 for the first time I had to prepare and file a return on my own. My only income that year was one paycheck for half of January, and a large capital gain from the sale of my shares in the brokerage firm. I also lost some money that year trading stocks for my personal account both in the US and Australia while I was there, so I took the cost of the trip as a business expense on my federal tax return. I soon got a call from the IRS informing me that I was to be audited regarding my business expenses, and to get my records together!

The audit, which was only supposed to address my business (trading) income and expenses, turned out to be a full “field audit” of every item on my return, and of all of my financial records including every check written and every deposit made with an explanation of what each one represented if it wasn’t self evident. When it was over I felt stripped of my dignity, privacy and freedom. The agent disallowed my trip expenses saying they weren’t sufficiently related to my trading, and informed me that I owed an additional two-hundred and fifty dollars in taxes. I could appeal, of course, but I quickly calculated that an appeal, to an IRS administrator first, and then to U.S. Tax Court, would cost me several-times more than the additional tax. (I felt I would need to hire a lawyer to argue my case.) My own reading of the IRS code told me my travel expenses were a legitimate deduction, I believed the agent, knowing it would be much cheaper to pay the $250 than appeal, arbitrarily disallowed my deduction in order to cover the IRS’ expenses for the hours he spent auditing my return. So I paid, but I am delighted to say that was the last federal, state or local income tax I ever paid.

Throughout the 70s I neglected to file returns. For several of those years I probably didn’t owe any tax because the apple crops in northeastern Ohio failed, and my cider-mill business lost money. In 1981–after ten years without a word from the IRS–an agent came by our house to see me. Fortunately, no one was at home, for I do not know how I would have reacted. The agent left his card with instructions that I call him. To say the incident scared the hell out of my wife understates the effect it had on her. It made me both scared and angry. When I called, the agent asked why I hadn’t filed any tax return since 1976. Why he didn’t ask about 1972, ’73, 74, and ’75, I’ll never know. Anyway, I told him I doubted I owed the IRS any money, but I would start to prepare those returns and get them to him within a couple of weeks. He allowed that would be acceptable.

I prepared five identical returns for 1976 through 1980, with no information other than my name and address. Across the face of each return in magic marker I wrote, “I CANNOT PROVIDE THE INFORMATION REQUESTED HEREIN UNLESS THE DEPARTMENT OF THE TREASURY ASSURES ME THAT IN SO DOING ALL OF MY RIGHTS AS A CITIZEN OF THE UNITED STATES SHALL REMAIN INVIOLATE.” With that simple quid pro quo I became what the IRS at the time called an “illegal tax protester,” even though according to the First Amendment there can be nothing illegal about protesting taxes.

I had committed no crime. As a matter of fact those were the most honest tax returns I ever filed, probably more honest than any of the hundreds of millions of returns that other Americans filed during those five years. As Will Rogers said, the income tax has made liars of more Americans than golf. Americans cheat on their taxes to the extent they think they can get away with it, or at least a comprehensive IRS study showed that to be the case.

I got sober in 1982, which likely saved me from going to prison on some tax-related charge. Before sobriety my attitude toward the IRS and its agents was belligerent, to say the least.

In sobriety I began studying the Gospels. The wisdom of Jesus revealed in the Gospels plus AA’s famous Twelve-Step program persuaded me of the utter futility of anger, resentment and retaliation. The Gospels also revealed that Jesus often hung out with tax collectors, calling some (Levi/Matthew) away from their tax-collecting duties, and redeeming at least one “chief” tax collector (Zacchaeus) from his sinful occupation. On the advice of Jesus (“love your enemies, pray for your persecutors”), I began praying for the IRS agents who were vigorously pursuing me. I diligently endeavored to love them and eventually forgive them. In due course I found to my surprise I had no enemies and no one persecuted me. That remains true to this day.

One of the things about the behavior of Jesus as reported in the Gospels that stood out to me was that he pointed to tax collectors as exemplars of sinfulness, yet he numbered many tax collectors among his disciples. This suggests to me that reformed tax collectors may play an important role in the tax abolition movement. Several IRS agents have already come out against the income tax and their former employer, to the cheers of those the IRS now refers to as “tax deniers,” since Congress, belatedly realizing the First Amendment assures that protesting taxes is legal, ordered the Service to do away with the “illegal tax protester” designation.

In the early 1980s when I first started studying Jesus’ teaching on taxes and tax collectors, I was struck by the fact that every so-called ‘Interpreter’s Bible” I consulted (and I think I consulted all of them) claimed Jesus endorsed the concept of taxation and/or the legitimacy of government rule when he said, “Give Caesar what is Caesar’s, but give God what is God’s.” This conflicted with my libertarian beliefs that taxation was theft in violation of God’s command, “Thou shall not steal.” It seemed to me that the State usurps God’s authority as Lawgiver, and the story of how Israel came to have a king bears this out. (See the first book of Samuel, Chapter eight.) It was inconceivable to me that Jesus would condone what his Father forbade or condemned.

One dissenting voice among the many statist interpretations of the Gospels was that of Leo Tolstoy. Tolstoy taught himself Greek, translated the Gospels from early manuscripts, and produced his own consolidated version of the Gospels because he didn’t trust the Russian-Orthodox Church’s translation. According to Tolstoy, Jesus told Peter that he and his disciples were not obligated to pay taxes. Tolstoy was indubitably an anarchist. After witnessing a public execution in Paris, he wrote to a friend, “The truth is that the State is a conspiracy designed not only to exploit, but above all to corrupt its citizens. … Henceforth, I shall never serve any government anywhere.” Amen, brother Leo.

After some serious Gospel study, I concluded that when Jesus said, “give Caesar what is Caesar’s but give God what is God’s,” he meant DO NOT give Caesar (representing the State of Rome and all other human governments) ANYTHING. Sacred Jewish Scripture, which Jesus consistently cited as his authority for what he said and did, states in at least five places, “The earth is the Lord’s and all that is in it, “ or words to that effect, which obviously leaves nothing for poor old Caesar. Eventually I wrote a book entitled JESUS OF NAZARETH, ILLEGAL TAX PROTESTER, which I published on the Internet in 2003. It is the first comprehensive analysis of everything Jesus said and did relative to taxes and tax collectors as reported in the Gospels. (http://www.jesus-on-taxes.com/Page_7.html)

Throughout the 1980s the IRS thrust and I parried. Eventually I was required to appear with my records at an IRS office before my favorite revenue agent and her supervisor. I brought a tape recorder and a witness, and when asked to produce my records I asked to see the warrant required by the Fourth Amendment. I was dismissed, but soon thereafter I received a “summons” to Federal District Court in Akron, Ohio. I ignored the summons, and soon thereafter two armed Federal Marshals picked me up in my office and brought me before the judge. I had been scrambling to learn something of court procedures from a patriot group whose members were mostly tax resisters. The judge gave pause when I raised a question of the court’s jurisdiction, but when he questioned me on the subject it became obvious to him that I didn’t know what I was talking about. So he ordered me to produce my financial record and provide testimony as required by the IRS.

Back at the IRS before the same two agents, I again demanded to see a warrant before I would provide testimony or give them my records. Our meeting abruptly ended. A few days later one of the Federal Marshals came again to my office to get me. The judge gave me a choice of jail or co-operating with the IRS. Refusing the latter, I was sent to jail for “civil contempt” until such time as I would provide the IRS with what it wanted (eternity???). Other than a few one-night stands for driving under the influence or public intoxication, that was my first jail experience. After 34 days and with a big Memorial Day weekend with my family in the offing, I told the judge I would cooperate and was released. A week later before the same IRS agents, a third time, I told them regretfully I had no financial records whatsoever. I informed them I didn’t keep records because I was afraid someday someone might subpoena them. After holding out for 34 days in jail, I think the agents expected my records would turn up a plethora of valuable assets. With taxes, interest, and penalties included, they thought I owed them about a quarter-million dollars. Their disappointment was palpable and worth every minute of my days in jail.

Unfortunately, I was forced by the threat of more jail time to answer all of their prying questions as they dug to uncover my hidden treasures. When the interrogation made it evident I had none, chagrin crossed their brows again. Although the meeting cost me nothing and yielded the IRS the same, being forced to answer their questions was the most mentally excruciating experience of my entire life.

Carl Watner’s writing made me realize voluntaryism fit me like a glove. The influences that made me become a voluntaryist were my undiagnosed oppositional defiance disorder, FEE, AA, AE (Austrian economics), my mother’s moral values, my non-payment of taxes and the pleasure of resisting them, and, last but not least, the principles Jesus preached and lived, especially nonviolence and love for all mankind, even to my would-be enemies. I am no longer defiant of human authority because I realize it is nothing but a hoax. Voluntaryism is good. Love your enemies. It befuddles them!

[Footnote 1] It is in keeping with AA tradition to remain anonymous when speaking publicly about AA. It’s a humility thing. Coincidentally, AA is a truly voluntary institution. It has no rules nor regulations, no dues nor fees nor taxes, only voluntary contributions. The expenses of local AA “groups” and AA’s significant worldwide services designed to provide help to alcoholics everywhere are the collective obligation of its members. AA’s “Twelve Traditions,” which are the closest thing to rules, compel nothing. There are no AA authorities. Our leaders actually are our trusted servants whose only power is persuasion. Each of the multitude of local AA groups throughout the world operates autonomously. Withal, AA has proven effective at achieving its primary purpose, which is to enable its members to remain sober and help other alcoholics achieve sobriety. No small task, which eluded the medical profession and mankind on any significant scale until AA came along in 1935. AA’s 76-years of experience may one day prove instructive to the formation of a stateless society.

 

Are Voluntaryists Hypocrites for Using the Roads?


 

by Carl Watner

I have never mentioned the voluntaryist email group in The Voluntaryist. It has been a means of connecting with people on the web who may not care to subscribe to the hard copy newsletter. If you have not signed up, you may go to www.voluntaryist.com and access the sign-up form on the homepage. There are occasional announcements, comments, etc. that otherwise might not fit into the newsletter or else be more timely by appearing via email. This, by way of introduction, leads to a question submitted by a subscriber to the email group:

How do you respond to the interminable rejoinder, from statists, that a voluntaryist is a hypocrite insofar as he/she cannot avoid using and benefiting from services paid for by government taxation? In other words, does using the post office or driving on the highways turn us into hypocrites?

Here is my reply.

First, one must determine the definition of hypocrisy. Wikipedia, The Shorter New Oxford English Dictionary, andWebster’s Unabridged Dictionary all introduce the elements of pretense, deception, and the false profession of belief as the key description of hypocrisy. In the words of Wikipedia, “an alcoholic’s advocating temperance” is not “an act of hypocrisy as long as the alcoholic makes no pretense of constant sobriety.” The intemperate person who supports temperance is guilty of inconsistency (his actions do not match his beliefs). However, the person who hides his cigar smoking habit from his friends, and tells them that he doesn’t smoke, and that they shouldn’t smoke, is a hypocrite. He is trying to pretend that he is a non-smoker when he really isn’t. The voluntaryist is certainly not a hypocrite insofar as he openly acknowledges his use of government services. Neither is a slave a hypocrite for wanting his freedom, even though he eats the food supplied by his master.

Secondly, a critic may rightfully claim that the voluntaryist’s use of the roads is inconsistent with his voluntaryist beliefs. The voluntaryist would certainly agree. The voluntaryist teaches that the most moral and practical system for satisfying human wants is that based on voluntary co-operation. A consistent voluntaryist will choose not to use State services, whenever and wherever possible. When there is a practical choice – say working for the government or working for a private employer – the consistent voluntaryist would and should always chose to maintain his integrity by working for the private employer. However, sometimes there is no reasonable alternative to using government funded services, such as the roads. Then, and only then, does the voluntaryist reluctantly use something provided by taxation.

As I pointed out in my article on “The Sin of the Intellectuals” in Issue 43 of The Voluntaryist (April 1990),

The behavior or misbehavior of the exponents of any particular philosophy indicates more about the psychology and personality of those advocates, than proving or disproving the philosophy itself. Ideas and theories must be judged on their own merits, otherwise we are in danger of committing the ad hominem fallacy, of judging the message by the messenger, rather than letting the message stand by itself. [end of emailed article]

After the appearance of my email, several other subscribers offered their opinions on this topic: Here are a few of them:

From Dr. Henry Jones (Miss.)

We all benefit from what those who came before us have created. We use language given to us freely by generations that worked to create it. .We benefit from roads and bridges that exist even though they were financed by stealing and killing. We use language, roads and inventions such as the wheel that we have not paid for ourselves. There is no way to avoid this and it does not represent hypocrisy. We are only responsible for the decisions we make freely and without coercion. I am opposed to murder yet I am forced to pay money (taxes) to support the murderer-in -chief in Washington D.C.

From Larken Rose (Pa.)

Here is my “short” answer to the “using the roads” thing: If you steal $100 bucks from me, and decide to give me a mediocre sandwich, am I a hypocrite if I complain about the theft AND eat the sandwich? No. Duh.

Slight elaboration: The roads should have been built via voluntary means. Nonetheless, as they are now, the roads still rightfully belong to the people who were robbed to pay for them. NOTHING belongs to “government.” It has a rightful claim on NOTHING, because everything it has, it stolen from others. Ultimately, no one gets anything from “government.” Whatever anyone receives from the state was either stolen from him, or stolen from someone else. I would say that if you’re accepting more than was stolen from you personally, you are indirectly cheating OTHER extortion victims (by accepting their stolen property). But it is impossible to “cheat” the “government,” because the state has never had a rightful claim to anything.

From Ned Netterville (Tn.)

Benefiting from government services??? I should send the State a bill for using their pot-holed roads and service-less post office. For all the money I pay in gasoline taxes, I get the worst imaginable roads compared to what a private road system would deliver at a fraction of the State’s graft-riven price, and USPS service stinks to high heaven compared to UPS. When I think of all the added wealth the people of America would have if government didn’t confiscate and waste their money, I’m appalled. Of what benefit is a government that incites “enemies” who want to kill me because of what its covert agents and armed forces do to people in other lands–killing and maiming innocents and using that egregious behavior to deprive me of the last vestiges of my human rights in the name of–ta, ta! ha, ha!–homeland security? Government is the ultimate, over-arching example of HYPOCRISY writ large.

Further comment from the Editor:

I think it is safe to conclude that in most cases use of the roads by voluntaryists is not hypocritical according to the definition of hypocrisy. Furthermore, anyone who attempts to use this criticism as a way to defeat voluntaryism is clearly guilty of the fallacy of ignoratio elenchi, known as raising an “irrelevant thesis.” The truth of voluntaryism depends upon a correct analysis of government as an invasive institute, of taxation as a coercive process, and of peaceful relations among individuals as being beneficial to all the involved parties. Whether or not voluntaryists are hypocrites has absolutely nothing to do with demonstrating whether or not these assertions are true.

If anyone has further comments, please email to editorREMOVE THIS@voluntaryist.com or snail to Box 275, Gramling SC 29348.

Open Letter to President of USA and Prime Minister of India


From: Jeff Knaebel, Moral Sovereign – January 2011
[Editor’s Note: Jeff Knaebel destroyed himself by self-immolation on January 25, 2011 near the ancient Buddhist site of Bairat, near Rajasthan, India. The following letter was found near his incinerated body. “Knowing that under certain conditions it is not worthwhile to live” (Aristotle, ETHICS, IV, 3) he deemed it “unconscionable and morally repugnant to live as a slave.” He maintained that taxation, government enforced citizenship, and travel and domicile restrictions, were all badges of enslavement.

Jeff’s posthumous manuscript titled Message From a Moral Sovereign: The Life and Death Story of an American’s Journey from Warpath to Gandhi Path was published in India in Fall 2011. A 320 page paperback, it is now available from The Voluntaryist for $ 20 (**) postage paid to US addressses or (**) elsehere, sent to

The Voluntaryist
P.O. Box 275
Gramling, South Carolina 29348

To pay for your order without Paypal, you may also submit a request and payment (Federal Reserve notes, stamps, gold, or silver, but please No checks or money orders) to the address above.

You can also send bitcoin to 1N9chGG4Dpp8Lw1eDye9wjiskAVqaiCi2Y, which you can click to email us your address.]

 

Subject: My Final Satyagraha for Nonviolence and Freedom

For a long time the Government of the USA (“USG”) has been the world’s leading merchant of death and destruction. Throughout my entire lifetime of 72 years the USG has been committing horrible crimes against humanity and all life. The sustained systematic psychopathic practices of the USG have launched humanity on a path to extinction. Mahatma Gandhi said upon the atomic bombing of Hiroshima that unless we adopted a nonviolent way of life, it spelled the suicide of the human species. Daily he is being proven correct.

As a citizen-slave of the USG I have been coerced to pay taxes which are then employed in bloody wars of aggression and coercive international economic practices which exploit weaker peoples whose lives, cultures, and ecologies are destroyed in the process. While dwelling in the land of my birth I was not permitted to withdraw from citizenship and the concomitant complicity in mass murder which USG citizenship entailed. Therefore I chose to come to India, and eventually decided to renounce my USG citizenship, and to destroy my United States passport and other government identity documents at the Gandhi Samadhi, Rajghat, New Delhi on 19 June 2009.

I acted in protest of government denial of my right to exist as a natural human living with respect for all life and answering to my own conscience. By requirement of identification and travel documents and permits both the USG and the Government of India (“GOI”) mark me as a piece of property to be regulated and controlled as the human equivalent of a dog on a leash. By my self-directed death I demonstrate my refusal to be the slave of either government.

To the Prime Minister of India (GOI), I refer the attached letter of 20 October 2010 from the General Counsel of The World Service Authority, which cites the violations by GOI of my human rights under the United Nations Declaration of Human Rights and International Law.

The GOI, acting through its police and the orders of its Supreme Court, has prohibited my freedom of movement and has denied me access to shelter pursuant to threat of FIR against any person who would host me. In thus pronouncing me to be an illegal human being, the GOI has denied my right to exist. A person cannot survive without freedom of movement and shelter.

My petition for Statelessness, denied by your Supreme Court, was based upon the clear fact that to change citizenship would only be to change the name of my slave master, for the GOI engages in many life-destroying and murderous actions against its own citizens, and also seeks “Strategic Partnership” with the war criminal USG.

By my death I send my answer to the rulers of the Corporate State who value property and profit more than human life and the life of Earth herself. In refusing to live as a slave I also extend to both of you my metta-karuna (compassion and loving-kindness), for if one examines deeply he will find that the corporate master is more tightly bound than the slave, for the slaves are powerless to come out of it, while the Powers That Be have free will that they fail to exercise because of addictive enslavement to power. For the corporate rulers, the power to manipulate and control other people has become an end in itself. They will no longer control me.

My wish for you is that you come to see the intrinsic evil of the governments which you head, and resign from your official positions, understanding that the people need no institutionally imposed ‘leaders.’

My campaign of Satyagraha has made it clear for all to see that under law and practice of both USG and GOI, a person striving for nonviolence at even the most rudimentary levels of non-support of killing is denied by law the right to exist. It is not by the laws of the Corporate State that humanity will find peace and justice, for such law is conceived in the womb of greed and implemented through the violence of power.

I give my life to the cause of nonviolence. I wish not to live under coercion to support the cruel inhumanity of either of your governments. I wish not to live under control of governments who possess neither the wisdom, nor the virtue, nor the right to exercise power over human life.

Only through fellow-feeling and loving-kindness can mankind survive on our small and crowded planet. We must share this Earth equally and with respect among all. I have acted out of love to try to send a warning to my fellowmen, and I send to each of you my sincere feelings of kindness and my prayers for your peace, happiness and harmony.

May peace and goodwill prevail among all men. May you both abide in well-being,

Signed – Jeff Knaebel

What Might Have Been – What Might Be


By Carl Watner

[Editor’s Note: The following article is the “Introduction” to my anthology, HOMESCHOOLING: A HOPE FOR AMERICA (2010). This 258 page softcover book is available from The Voluntaryists for $20.00 postpaid to US addresses, $25 elsewhere.]

The responsibility of parents for the education of their children is deeply rooted in the spirit and history of America. In his book, IS PUBLIC EDUCATION NECESSARY?, Samuel Blumenfeld points out that there was no mention of education, much less “public/government” education in either the Declaration of Independence or the federal Constitution. Even if one were to argue that education fell within the jurisdiction of the states, rather than the national government, one is hard pressed to explain why only two of the constitutions of the original thirteen colonies (Pennsylvania and North Carolina) mentioned the subject. This absence of concern for what is today deemed to be one of the most central of government functions (both on the federal and state levels) is not too hard to explain.

Education, both before and after the American Revolution, was certainly not the responsibility of governments. The educational backgrounds of the signers of the Declaration and Constitution attest to the richness and diversity of the voluntary educational environment of the time. Their schooling encompassed “every conceivable combination of parental, church, apprenticeship, school, tutorial, and self-education.” As Blumenfeld observes: “George Washington was educated by his father and half-brother, Benjamin Franklin was taught to read by his father and attended a private school for writing and arithmetic,” and “Thomas Jefferson studied Latin and Greek under a tutor.” [1] Charles Dabney, in his book UNIVERSAL EDUCATION IN THE SOUTH, reports that “a great advance in educational enterprises of a private and ecclesiastical character followed” the years after the American Revolution. “The wealthy established private schools. Academies and colleges were started wherever a few pupils could be gathered together and teachers found. A new ideal of education was in the making, … .” [2] In 1798, Joseph Lancaster opened his first free school in London, England, followed by its spread to New York City in 1805. [3] In short, the “men who founded the United States were educated under the freest conditions possible” and it would have been strange to most of them, indeed, to think that government should have been a provider of education. [4]

This is our ideal, the “what might have been” for American education, and our hope for what might be. Yet, as every 21st Century reader knows, educational freedom in America has been nearly destroyed, so much so that even the validity of homeschooling has been challenged in many states. This collection of eclectic articles from THE VOLUNTARYIST, which has been published since 1982, is designed to make you think about educational freedom and political statism. It takes the following points for its main theme:

… Government schools are paid for by compulsory taxes. (Why is it assumed that the majority of parents would not willingly pay for their children’s education? Why are they presumed guilty? At the very least, if taxes must be collected to pay for public schools, why not collect them only from those who refuse to educate their children and necessitate such schools?)

… Government schools depend on the coercion of compulsory attendance laws. (Why is it assumed that the majority of parents would not willingly educate their children? Why are they presumed guilty? At the very least, why not apply compulsory attendance laws only to those parents who refuse to educate their children? To teachers and state educators we ask: Do you think nobody would willingly entrust their children to you? Why do you have to collect your pupils by compulsion?) [5]

… Before the advent of government schools, parents were primarily responsible for the education of their children.

… The home has always been the main place where education occurred; and the parents were often the primary instructors of their children.

… Although restricted by every conceivable law and political regulation, it is the natural and common law right of the parents to direct the education of their children.

… Parents have a moral duty to educate their offspring. However, a child has no right to an education. (The common law held it as no offense for a parent not to educate his child.) [6]

… Government schools are designed to indoctrinate students in statolatry, in the worship of the State as the provider of all ‘good’ things. (A tax-supported educational system is the life-like representative of the totalitarian state.) [7]

… Someone or some institution must control the child. (Shall we have a free society with parental control of the child’s education or an authoritarian society with state-controlled education?) [8]

… If there is any hope for America as a beacon of liberty and freedom it is to be found in home education.

How does voluntaryism relate to education? Voluntaryism is the philosophic doctrine that all the affairs of mankind should be voluntary. No one has the right to force another peaceful person to act as he or she wishes. Voluntaryism comes about naturally if no one does anything to prevent it. Voluntaryism was a term that originated in the early 1800s in England to identify those who advocated voluntary, as opposed to State, support of religion. It was later extended to those who opposed the coercive collection of taxes. Ultimately, those who shared this position realized that government would probably receive little revenue if it did not threaten jail time or confiscation of property to collect its taxes. In short, voluntaryists question the legitimacy of coercive political government because it initiates violence against those who would decline its protection because they want none, or would provide their own protection, or hire some other organization to provide them with protection. Furthermore, by its monopolization of services, government violates the rights of those individuals or groups of individuals who might choose to offer competing services to those offered by the government. Many voluntaryists see a parallel between government churches and government schools. If it is not proper to support a State church by compulsory attendance laws and coercive taxes, why should it be proper to support State schools in a similar manner? Why is one’s spiritual health any less important than one’s educational development? [9]

In a free society, no one owes anybody else food, shelter, clothing, medical care, or spiritual or intellectual growth. Respect for individual rights means that some may have more than they need, some less, but each person is or should be secure in what is theirs. Only then, whether they have lots or little, may they be disposed to be charitable or miserly with what they have. Voluntaryism in education follows from each person’s self-ownership and rightful control of their property. Parents nurture their children. Teachers, tutors, and masters of apprentices offer their services. No coercive outside agency tells parents when, and where, and what and how to teach. This lack of any centralized agency directing education permits a tremendous variety of what to teach, as well as how to teach. Voluntaryism does not guarantee success, but it does allow for each family to experiment and find out what is best for them. Voluntaryism does not exhibit the one-size fits all approach of government schooling. There is nothing to prevent what works for one family to be imitated and copied, while a government monopoly almost assures us that mediocrity will rule. Parental-directed schooling, unlike government schooling, is not dominated by political considerations and compromises between competing interests and radically different constituencies.

All teaching and teachers are laden with values and beliefs. [10] Education can never be free of dogma. This is an inescapable fact of reality. Thus the question becomes: “Would one rather have a single educational monopolist deciding what is taught and how it is taught, or would one rather have each individual parent and family decide what they will teach or have taught to their children?” Family indoctrination may be just as thorough and enslaving as state indoctrination, but that situation would be far better than if “a universal education agency” were to have indoctrinated everybody in its dogma. As one advocate of diversity in indoctrination explained: if different families indoctrinate in different dogmas, “the dogmatic, indoctrinated product of one family’s indoctrination will grow up to profess a different dogma than that of another family’s indoctrinated offspring. Then, in social interactions among the various indoctrinated, differences of belief and lack of universality of dogma will become apparent to all, undermining in many the felt necessity of the dogmatic beliefs they were trained to hold.” The fact that no monopolist can instill its dogma on a captive audience insures that whatever dogmas are taught will clash in a manner that will make many question their beliefs and lead them to rectify their mistaken beliefs, if they come to that conclusion. But “people in a society where universal indoctrination has been practiced would be less likely to discover the inhibition on their freedom since everyone, everywhere will attest to the putatively obvious truth of everything that person believes.” [11] And in a society where government directs the people’s education it is a certainty that the people will be taught that voluntaryism in education is dangerous and that government education is best. Who could imagine the government criticizing itself?

Thus, it is readily apparent that the public school is a tool of the State, an idea going back at least as far as Plato. Those who direct the schools “control a character-producing institution” that is an instrument of the “ruling elite to maintain and enhance their power.” [12] Public education is simply one of the primary means of molding American children into tax-paying, law-abiding American adults, who rarely question the nature and legitimacy of their own government. As Jonathan Kozol notes: “The first and primary function of the U. S. public schools is not to educate good people, but good citizens. It is the function which we call in enemy nations state indoctrination.” [13] John Taylor Gatto expands on this theme calling government schools WEAPONS OF MASS INSTRUCTION:

[M]andatory public education in this country … was useful in creating not only a harmless electorate and a servile labor force but also a virtual herd of mindless consumers. In time a great number of industrial titans came to recognize the enormous profits to be had by cultivating and tending such a herd via public education, … . School trains children to be employees and consumers. … [W]ake up to what our schools really are: laboratories of experimentation on young minds, drill centers for the habits and attitudes that corporate [and political] society demand… . [I]ts real purpose is to turn them into servants. [14]

When homeschooling parents have been challenged in court for violating the state’s education law, rarely are the educational achievements of their children called into question. The accomplishments of the children (whether they have met the state requirements for their grade levels or not) are usually beside the point. The welfare of the child is not the concern of the State. The courts do not consider how well the child is educated, but only whether or not the child is receiving a government-approved education and if the appropriate rules and regulations were followed. [15] If the State were truly concerned with neglected and illiterate children, it would take corrective action to save those children its own educational system has failed to teach to read or write.

It is likely that some children receive a worse education under a government regime than they would in the absence of political laws. This is consistent with the nature of government intervention. Even from the point of view of its supporters, government action often makes conditions worse than before it interfered. If we examine the “Six Political Illusions” enunciated by James L. Payne we can begin to understand how this happens:

1. Since government has no funds of its own, “money spent on government programs must be taken from citizens who have good and useful purposes for their own funds. Therefore, all government spending programs injure these good and useful activities.”

2. Government is based on the exercise of physical force to accomplish its ends. “Its taxes and regulations rely on the threat of inflicting physical harm on those who do not cooperate.”

3. Government programs “have high overhead costs. Goods or services provided through a tax and spend system end up costing several times as much as they would if citizens obtained these goods or services directly” on the market.

4. “Money is only one factor in success. If the motivation and abilities of recipients are not suitable … government spending will be useless, or can do more harm than good.”

5. “Government has no superior wisdom. Government officials are ordinary people, as prone to bias, intolerance, greed, and error as anyone” else.

6. Government would have us think that it is a problem-solving institution, but it cannot duplicate the “the creative actions of individuals, families, neighborhoods, groups, and businesses. Problem-solving efforts by government almost invariably impair the energy and capacity of the voluntary sphere.” [16]

It is easy to see how every one of these illusions applies to government education, and why voluntaryists are more concerned with the means than the ends. Voluntaryists understand Mahatma Gandhi’s insight that “if one takes care of the means, the end will take care of itself.” If they rely on voluntaryism and don’t use coercion to educate their children, they not only set their children a moral, non-violent example (not relying on tax funds which are forcibly collected), but they generally do at least as good, if not a much better, practical job of preparing their children for life than the State. Voluntaryism has no formal guidelines that will dictate what kinds of education will take place in a free society. So long as the means are peaceful, respectful of self-ownership and property titles, the ends cannot be criticized from the voluntaryist perspective. This is not to imply that the only standard of judging human behavior is whether or not it is voluntary. Certainly some behavior may be irrational, vicious, immoral, religious, irreligious, (etc., etc.) but the first question the voluntaryist asks is: Is it truly voluntary? This is why the voluntaryist objects to government provision of dispute settlement, police services, schools, etc. Such services may be essential to human survival, but it is not essential that they be provided by government on a coercive basis. There is no logical, epistemological, or societal justification for forcing goods or services upon unwilling customers. The political attempts of 2009-2010 to impose universal national healthcare is just the latest government-mandated service being forced upon people (those who have to pay taxes to support other people’s medical care, and those who would prefer to make provisions for their own healthcare).

Education in a free society is the responsibility of every parent. Some parents will be irresponsible. Some will be responsible for the education of their own children. Others may choose to become responsible for the education of children that are not their own. That is the beauty of freedom. Each person must inevitably make their own choice, or choose to make none at all (though indeed, they have no choice; reality will make it for them if they fail to make a choice themselves). The kind of character we develop individually goes far in determining what kind of collective society we shall have. But after all is said and done, the only thing we, individually, can do is “to present society with one improved unit.” As Albert Jay Nock put it, “Ages of experience testify that the only way society can be improved is by the individualist method; … that is, the method of each one doing his best to improve one.” [17] This is the quiet or patient way of changing society because it concentrates upon bettering the character of men and women as individuals. As the individual units change, the improvement in society will take care of itself. In other words, if one takes care of the means, the end will take care of itself.

What better description of homeschooling could one pen?

THE VOLUNTARYIST insight into education offers a unique and seldom heard point of view about children, schooling, and the State. Many of these essays may make you fume but please let them help you think through the issues. But above all else, as Shakespeare wrote: “To thine own self be true: And it must follow, as the night the day, Thou canst not then be false to any man.”

End Notes

[1] Samuel L. Blumenfeld, IS PUBLIC EDUCATION NECESSARY?, Old Greenwich: The Devin-Adair Company, 1981, pp. 20-21.

[2] Charles Dabney, UNIVERSAL EDUCATION IN THE SOUTH, Volume I: From the Beginnings to 1900, Chapel Hill: The University of North Carolina Press, 1936, p. 3.

[3] Erica Carle, “Education Without Taxation,” THE FREEMAN, March 1962, pp. 48-55 at pp. 48 and 50.

[4] Blumenfeld, op. cit., p. 21.

[5] Murray Rothbard, EDUCATION, FREE AND COMPULSORY: THE INDIVIDUAL’S EDUCATION, Wichita: Center for Independent Education, 1972, p. 17 citing Isabel Paterson, THE GOD OF THE MACHINE. See Chapter XXI of the Caxton Printers edition, 1964, p. 274.

[6] Robert P. Baker, “Statute Law and Judicial Interpretation,” in William F. Rickenbacker (editor), THE TWELVE YEAR SENTENCE, LaSalle: Open Court, 1974, pp. 97-135 at p. 100.

[7] Rothbard, op. cit., p. 15.

[8] Ibid., p. 11.

[9] See Herbert Spencer, THE PROPER SPHERE OF GOVERNMENT (a series of twelve letters published in THE NONCONFORMIST, beginning June 1842, and reprinted as pamphlet in 1843). Especially see the conclusion to Letter VIII. Available on the worldwide web in the Library of Economics and Liberty at http://www.econlib.org/library/LFBooks/Spencer/spnMvS6.html.

[10] Gerrit H. Wormhoudt, “Supreme Court Decisions,” in William F. Rickenbacker (editor), THE TWELVE YEAR SENTENCE, LaSalle: Open Court, 1974, pp. 61-94 at p. 81.

[11] J. Roger Lee, “Limits on Universal Education,” in Tibor R. Machan (editor), EDUCATION IN A FREE SOCIETY, Stanford: Hoover Institution Press, 2000, pp. 1-25 at pp. 23-24.

[12] Joel H. Spring, “Sociological and Political Ruminations,” in William F. Rickenbacker (editor), THE TWELVE YEAR SENTENCE, LaSalle: Open Court, 1974, pp. 139-159 at pp. 140-142.

[13] Jonathan Kozol, THE NIGHT IS DARK AND I AM FAR FROM HOME, Boston: Houghton Mifflin Company, 1975, p.1.

[14] John Taylor Gatto, WEAPONS OF MASS INSTRUCTION: A School Teacher’s Journey Through the Dark World of Compulsory Schooling, Gabriola Island: New Society Publishers, 2009, pp. xix-xx, and p. xxii. Gatto admonishes: “School trains children to be employees and consumers; teach your own to be leaders and adventurers. School trains children to obey reflexively; teach your own to think critically and independently.” (p. xxii) After reciting many success stories of ‘unschooled’ but educated children, he concludes “that genius [among children] is common as dirt. We suppress genius because we haven’t yet figured out how to manage a population of educated men and women. The solution, I think, is simple and glorious. Let them manage themselves.” (p. xxiii)

[15] Baker, op. cit., pp. 130-131.

[16] James L. Payne, SIX POLITICAL ILLUSIONS, privately distributed manuscript dated November 19, 2009. See Chapter VII, p. 107.

[17] Albert Jay Nock, MEMOIRS OF A SUPERFLUOUS MAN, New York: Harper and Brothers, 1943, p. 307.

My Journey to Voluntaryism


By Joyce Brand

 

I always loved to read. I remember my mother telling her friends that I was no trouble because she could set me down with a book and I would amuse myself for hours. Maybe that was why I loved school, in spite of the regimentation, which I hated. My life was in my head, not in the stupid rules I had to follow.

My father was both a Southern Baptist minister and an officer in the US Navy, very conservative and very Republican. I adored him, so I found it very painful when I realized at the age of fifteen that I couldn’t believe what he preached, no matter how hard I tried. However, I was a good little girl, so I didn’t rock the boat, and I went off to a Southern Baptist university right after my seventeenth birthday.

Probably nobody was less prepared for college life than I was in 1966. It was then that I discovered Ayn Rand. It was a religion I could believe in, until I realized that worshipping Ayn Rand made no more sense than worshipping an invisible deity. Although my life took some strange turns in the next few years, I kept the basic philosophy of individualism that I learned from Ayn Rand, which included a profound contempt for politics.

After escaping from an unhappy marriage, I indulged my love of reading by going to a state university and taking a double major in English and History. I was particularly interested in how literature affected history and vice versa. I was shocked by how different the history I learned in college was from the history I had been taught in grade school. Yet even the texts in college were heavily influenced by the philosophy of the writers, which seemed to me disturbingly collectivist. In retrospect, I realize that, in spite of how much I was reading, I was never exposed to any ideas that challenged the legitimacy of the state.

I graduated Phi Beta Kappa and was accepted into the PhD program in History at the University of California at Berkeley, but I was unsure if I really wanted a life in academia, so I took a summer job in a law firm to see if law school might suit me more. I was disgusted by the legal profession and started to think about making my living in the real world of business.

I spent many years trying to find my place in the world through different careers and different relationships. Nothing seemed to suit me long term, but I learned a lot.

One of my most memorable lessons came from my job as an office equipment salesperson. I spent most of my time showing private businesses how my equipment could increase their productivity. I discovered that trying to sell to government agencies was a waste of time because bureaucrats didn’t want to increase productivity and possibly lose employees. Then one day I got a call that a District Court wanted to buy some electronic typewriters from me because the manufacturer of our newest line had a government contract. Easiest sale ever because there was no competition and they already knew they wanted the most expensive models we had. They had a budget for typewriters that they had to spend or lose, so they spent it on typewriters that actually decreased their productivity because the machines were designed for more complicated tasks than filling in forms. All I had to do was deliver the machines and teach the secretaries how to get around all the features that made filling out forms difficult. The commission was nice, but I couldn’t help thinking about all the tax dollars being wasted. That was when I realized that all tax dollars were wasted in exactly the same way, propping up the power of bureaucrats for no benefit to anyone else. It’s all about the perverse incentives.

Perverse incentives had a lot to do with the failure of my second marriage. My husband was a very kind person with little ambition but a history of taking responsibility for his life in difficult circumstances. He told me how his union job created the incentive for everyone to put forth minimal effort and how wrong he thought that was. Then he hurt his back and got into the worker’s comp system, which gives doctors and patients incentives to continue treatments after they are no longer needed. Maybe those perverse incentives just brought out weaknesses in his character that were always there, but I can’t help blaming that government program for the change in his personality. I saw the growth of an entitlement mentality and dependence happen before my eyes until I could no longer live with the man he had become.

Another job that taught me how government interferes with free enterprise business was the year I spent as a business broker. It started with my having to obtain real estate licenses in two states just to be allowed to do the job. I had always heard that real estate licenses required months of classes and most people still failed the exam on the first try, and the challenge exam was even harder. Fortunately, I didn’t believe it, so I spent about thirty hours on my own studying the guide and passed both challenge exams with no problem. The ridiculous thing was that passing those exams in no way ensured that I would be able to sell real estate (or negotiate business leases) honestly and responsibly. It just meant I knew a lot of stupid and useless rules.

The real lessons came from working with small business owners who were trying to sell their businesses. Listing the business for sale meant learning everything about the business, including how the owner did or did not manage to get around all the government regulations that interfered with his ability to please enough customers to make a living at the business. Even though intrusive regulations didn’t account for all the owners who were failing, the ones who were trying most scrupulously to follow all the rules seemed to be the ones who did worst. The owners who did best were those who found ways to please customers while keeping enough money for themselves to make it all worthwhile. That mainly meant figuring out which regulations to follow and which to ignore. Unlike big businesses that can use government against would be competitors, small businesses get no benefits from government. They don’t need any government to tell them to treat their customers and employees well in order to prosper.

As a corporate manager at Kelly Services, the oldest temporary help company, I learned even more about the difference between large and small business and how government affects business. My small department with twelve employees was a cost center rather than a profit center, so my job was all about achieving productivity goals at the lowest cost possible. Government regulations created the biggest costs and happy employees created the biggest productivity gains. Keeping employees happy is not about money but about respect and freedom and challenge. The problem with size is not that it is inherently bad but that it can dilute responsibility. Just a few political (rather than economic) business people at the top can create a corporate culture rife with political maneuvering and not enough focus on business goals. The more politics gain, the more business suffers. Kelly Services was once the leader of its industry, but not any more.

After a few more careers that got boring as soon as I accomplished my initial goals, I finally discovered a career that I loved and that never got boring — editing feature films — a different kind of storytelling than I had once imagined as a child. At about the same time, I got interested in the Libertarian Party. The man who recruited me insisted that the LP was not “politics as usual” but a real chance to restore freedom to America by reining in government power. I soon discovered how wrong he was when I attended the 2000 California state convention. It was just as disgusting as any other political game, in spite of the sincerity of most of the participants. I saw that it wasn’t the people involved that was the problem but the perverse incentives of politicians, just like the perverse incentives of bureaucrats, no matter how well-meaning.

However, I did get a lot out of my brief time in the LP, especially from a few speeches by libertarian anarchists, like Mary Ruwart. In particular, her books “Healing Our World” and “Short Answers to the Tough Questions” opened my mind to the idea that government wasn’t necessary at all. That started me on a reading program that emphasized writers like Frederick Bastiat, Lysander Spooner, Albert Jay Nock, Leonard E. Read, and Murray Rothbard. I found more than I would ever have time to read on websites like Lew Rockwell, Mises Institute, and Strike the Root.

It took me a few years of fairly intensive reading between films before I fully understood the beauty and simplicity of market anarchism/anarcho-capitalism. It seemed like I spent a lot of time defending the terms before I heard the word voluntaryism, which made it all so clear. What I had always believed on some level was that all interactions between people should be voluntary and peaceful. The vision of a society based on that idea was what I had always sought. I am now very happy to be one of the organizers of Libertopia, an annual festival that brings together people who share that vision of peace, prosperity, and a voluntary society.

 

Auberon Herbert


By Wendy McElroy
[First published in Freedom Daily, February and March 2011. See the Future of Freedom Foundation website www.fff.org.]

In his periodical Liberty (May 23, 1885), the quintessential American individualist-anarchist Benjamin Tucker wrote of his British counterpart Auberon Herbert, “I know of no more inspiring spectacle in England than that of this man of exceptionally high social position doing battle almost single-handed with the giant monster, government, and showing in it a mental rigor and vigor and a wealth of moral fervor rarely equaled in any cause.”

Auberon Edward William Molyneux Herbert (1838–1906) was born into the ruling class. As the son of the 3rd Earl of Carnarvon and brother to the 4th earl, Herbert attended both Eton College, which has traditionally been called “the chief nurse of England’s statesmen and St. John’s College, Oxford. He ran unsuccessfully for Parliament as a Conservative and later served as a Liberal in the House of Commons for Nottingham in the early 1870s. There, his sympathy for working people was evident through the support he rendered to fellow-politician Joseph Arch in the goal of forming the National Agricultural Labourers Union. Upon meeting the individualist philosopher Herbert Spencer in 1873, however, Herbert became cemented in his decision not to seek re-election. In an essay posthumously published in his book The Voluntaryist Creed (Oxford University Press, 1908), Herbert explained Spencer’s impact upon him:

    As I read and thought over what he taught, a new window was opened in my mind. I lost my faith in the great machine [government]; I saw that thinking and acting for others had always hindered not helped the real progress; that all forms of compulsion deadened the living forces in a nation; that every evil violently stamped out still persisted, almost always in a worse form, when driven out of sight, and festered under the surface. I no longer believed that the handful of us however well-intentioned we might be spending our nights in the House, could manufacture the life of a nation, could endow it out of hand with happiness, wisdom and prosperity, and clothe it in all the virtues.

Herbert fully embraced the radical individualism Spencer expressed in his brief work The Man versus the State (1884). In the Illustrated London News (February 15, 1936) English author G.K. Chesterton wrote,

    Herbert Spencer really went as far as he could in the direction of Individualism…. He left only the gallant and eccentric Auberon Herbert to go one step further; and practically propose that we should abolish the police; and merely insure ourselves against thieves and assassins, as against fire and accident.

Herbert also began to argue vigorously against the privileges of his own class. His book A Politician in Trouble about his Soul (1884), issued by the prestigious Chapman and Hall, who also published Charles Dickens, was dedicated to “The Workmen of Nottingham,” In the dedication, he wrote,

    May the day come, for us and for every other nation, when the politician, as we know him at present, shall be numbered amongst the fossils of the past, when we shall cease to desire to rule each other either by force or by trick, when we shall dread for the sake of our own selves the possession of power, when we shall recognize that there are such things as universal rights….

Published by mainstream periodicals such as Nineteenth Century, The Humanitarian, and Fortnightly Review, Herbert became the most influential British libertarian of his time. Today, however, he is perhaps best remembered for popularizing Voluntaryism – a political tradition maintaining that all human interaction should be voluntary and rejecting the initiation of force. The only justification for force is self-defense, including the defense of property.

The role of government

To the extent there is debate about Herbert’s beliefs, the focus is generally upon whether he was
an anarchist. He consistently rejected the label. He wrote,

    My charge against Anarchism is that it sees many forms of crime existing in the world, and it refuses to come to any settled opinion as to what it will do in the matter. If it says it will do nothing, then we must live under the reign of the murderer…; if it says it will have some form of local jury, then we are back into government again at once.

By contrast, “[in] voluntaryism the state employs force only to repel force – to protect the person and the property of the individual against force and fraud; under voluntaryism the state would defend the rights of liberty, never aggress upon them.”

In short, Herbert believed defensive force and the protection of property were legitimate roles for government or “a central agency.” The government would be financed solely by a “voluntary tax.” Payees would gain the privilege of voting; nonpayees would not have the franchise but could set up their own associations. Herbert doubted they would do so because the benefits of a “central agency” would be apparent to all. Thus, he called himself a “governmentalist” and, in 1879, once more attempted to join the House of Commons but failed.

The focus on the anarchism question loses the true importance of the man. During decades of toil for liberty, Herbert was one of the most influential anti-war voices in England; he was an eloquent and unique advocate of the working man; he acted as a foil to the emerging power of socialism; and, he argued against the worst aspects of 19th-century American libertarianism, including its rejection of capitalism, especially in the form of rent and interest. Although it is speculation, Herbert’s presence at the head of British libertarianism may have been what kept that movement on course in terms of embracing sound economic theory.

The foundation of Herbert’s political convictions was “the rights of self-ownership” which “express the limits of rightful and wrongful action.” These were the natural rights that a person had over his own body and the products thereof (property) against which no one else could properly aggress. Since they were based in man’s nature, these rights were possessed in equal measure by every man. Herbert declared, “If we are self-owners (and it is absurd, it is doing violence to reason, to suppose that we are not), neither an individual, nor a majority, nor a government can have rights of ownership in other men.”

“The way of force and strife”

Herbert argued with particular vigor against the idea of majority rule, saying that “what one man cannot morally do, a million men cannot morally do, and government, representing many millions of men, cannot do.” Regarding the phrase “the good of the greatest number,” Herbert exclaimed,

      There never was invented a more specious and misleading phrase. The Devil was in his most subtle and ingenious mood when he slipped this phrase into the brains of

 

    men…. It assumes that there are two opposed “goods,” and that the one good is to be sacrificed to the other good – but … liberty is the one good, open to all, and requiring no sacrifice of others; this false opposition (where no real opposition exists) of two different goods means perpetual war between men – the larger number being for ever incited to trample on the smaller number. I can only ask: Why are 2 men to be sacrificed to 3 men? We all agree that the 3 men are not to be sacrificed to the 2 men; but why – as a matter of moral right – are we to do what is almost as bad and immoral and shortsighted – sacrifice the 2 men to the 3 men?… [Liberty] does away with all necessity of sacrifice.” (Free Life, July 1898)

Herbert expressed his rejection of majority rule and “tribalism” through his active opposition to war. In the introduction to the 1978 edition of The Right and Wrong of Compulsion by the State, the philosopher Eric Mack observed,

      Following Spencer’s distinction between industrial and militant societies, Herbert continually emphasized the differences between two basic modes of interpersonal coordination. There is the “way of peace and cooperation” founded upon respect for self-ownership and the demand for only voluntary association. And there is the “way of force and strife” founded upon either the belief in the ownership of some by others or the simple reverence of brute force.

 

War was the pure expression of “the way of force and strife.” Herbert’s anti-war sentiments had a long history. Like many British aristocrats, he had held commissions in the army and served in India; in letters home, he criticized the British occupation.

During the Prusso-Danish war (1864), he spent time observing action near the front line and was subsequently decorated by the Danish government for rendering aid to the wounded. He also directly observed the American Civil War (1861–1865), of which he wrote, “I am very glad that slavery is done away with, but I think the manner is very bad and wrong.”

In the 1870s, “jingoism” swept England in reaction to the Russo-Turkish War. Jingoism is extreme patriotism coupled with an aggressive foreign policy. The term came from the chorus of a popular
pub song: “We don’t want to fight but by Jingo if we do/We’ve got the ships, we’ve got the men, we’ve got the money too/We’ve fought the Bear before, and while we’re Britons true/The Russians shall not have Constantinople.”

When the jingoists organized anti-Russia rallies in Hyde Park, Herbert became a driving force in organizing anti-jingoist ones. His anti-war stance was not only visceral from having witnessed the savagery of war, but also ideological. Mack explained,

    Herbert repeatedly took anti-imperialist stands. He consistently called for Irish self-determination. In the early 1880s, he opposed British intervention in Egypt as a use of the power of the nation to guarantee the results of particular speculations. And, later, he opposed the Boer War.

Herbert was also cognizant that wars benefited the ruling class at the expense of common men, who were overwhelmingly the ones to fight and die.

Herbert and the working man

On other issues, Auberon Herbert predictably sided with working people. In 1869, he acted as one of the presidents of the first national Co-operative Congress. As its name suggests, the Co-operative movement focused on establishing cooperative societies and arrangements, such as mutual insurance agencies.

When Herbert’s Right and Wrong of Compulsion by the State first appeared, Benjamin Tucker reviewed it in Liberty (May 23, 1885). The book, he explained, “consists of a series of papers written for Joseph Cowen’s paper, the Newcastle Chronicle, supplemented by a letter to the London Times on the English factory acts. Dedicated to Mr. Cowen’s constituents, ‘The Workmen of Tyneside,’ it appeals with equal force to workmen the world over, and their welfare and their children’s will depend upon the readiness with which they accept and the bravery with which they adhere to its all-important counsel.”

In 1877, as an outward manifestation of his support of labor, Herbert founded the Personal Rights and Self-Help Association that opposed the increasingly popular socialist “solution” to labor. Whereas the socialists called for more laws, especially factory legislation, the Personal Rights Association advocated the repeal of laws and called for free trade as the way to empower labor. The “Self-Help” aspect of the Association referred to the working man’s need to protect himself through voluntary association rather than authority. In advocating free trade, Herbert went so far as to defend sweatshop owners (sweaters), who were almost universally reviled by the co-operative movement. He wrote,

    The sweater may or may not be a very evil person, but he has no power to compel those he employs to accept his terms. He is not a user of force. You have therefore no moral right to employ force against him…. But apart from the moral argument, it is stupid in such a case to use force…. [It] is the circumstances that compel those in the sweater’s employment to accept the hard conditions. Is there not then something very left-handed in employing force against the sweater himself, who, as is confessed, is not the cause of the evil? The cause of the evil is in the circumstances, and it is in the circumstances that a remedy must be found. (Free Life, July 1898)

At podiums across England and in prominent publications, Herbert argued against other core ideas of socialism. For example, he dissected the concept of the state or society as being an independent organism in which individuals functioned as limbs or muscle; in essence, the socialists were denying the independent existence of individuals. In an early expression of methodological individualism, Herbert claimed the opposite was true.

      The State is created by the individuals. It is fashioned and re-fashioned by them at their own will and pleasure … for their use and service, and when it does not satisfy their requirements, they pull it to pieces and reconstruct it. Men throughout their lives are included in many wholes…. Schools, colleges, clubs, associations, joint stock companies, co-operative companies, political parties, village or town organisations, and then lastly comes national organisation or the State; but in all these cases, the organisation is created by the individuals themselves…. [How] is it possible for any constructed and reconstructed things to be greater than those who construct it and reconstruct it? To indulge in any such imagination is to imitate the carver of idols, who, when with his own hands he has fashioned the log of wood, falls on his knees before it and calls it his god. (Free Life, July 1898)

 

Objections to Herbert

Prominent socialists struck back. The economist and democratic socialist J.A. Hobson wrote a harsh critique of Herbert in the Humanitarian, entitled “A Rich Man’s Anarchism,” echoing the
accusation of anarchism and attacking Herbert’s defense of private property as a ploy to enslave the poor to the rich. During the 1890s, both Hobson and the socialist E. Belfort Bax engaged in lengthy published debates with Herbert, returning again and again to attacks based on Herbert’s advocacy of private property and to ad hominems accusing him of anarchism.

On the other side of the Atlantic, Tucker agreed with the “accusation” of anarchism but praised Herbert for it. The matter on which he took Herbert to task was his embrace of laissez-faire capitalism. Along with most other 19th-century American libertarians, Tucker accepted the labor theory of value, which claims that the value of a good results solely from the labor and the basic costs required to produce it. If a capitalist subsequently takes the good and sells it for twice what he pays the laborer, then the resulting profit is a form of theft. Tucker also considered charging interest on money to be usury. He believed the remedy was free banking and the elimination of all state support for business, including monopoly privileges. He opposed the charging of rent on the grounds that people did not rightfully own property they did not occupy.

To Herbert, selling goods for profit and charging interest on money were naturally occurring market phenomena that would exist whether or not the state did. The practice of collecting rent was an extension of ownership, which did not require constant use or occupation to be legitimate. Interesting enough, although Herbert was baited repeatedly on that issue within Liberty, especially by the periodical’s sometimes co-editor
Victor Yarros, Herbert – usually an ardent debater – chose not to respond.

After a fire destroyed Tucker’s offices in 1907, he left for Europe, and an era of America libertarianism ended. The same can be said of British libertarianism with the death of Herbert in 1906.

Shortly before his death, Herbert declared, “I venture to prophesy that there lies before us a bitter and an evil time.” He spoke not merely of the rapid rise of socialism. An avid observer of military matters, Herbert undoubtedly saw the early stirrings of World War I, which would erupt in 1914. It would sweep away the last remnants of classical liberalism in England and devastate a generation of young men. Herbert’s focus on the terrible impact that violence has upon those who commit it meant there could be no victors emerging from such a conflict.

Referring to the “victory” of three men who use force against two others, Herbert wrote,

    Nothing can be worse for the 3 men. To be told that for your convenience the rights of others are not to count must corrupt and make a beast of you, It is an untrue exaltation of yourself that human nature cannot withstand…. That is mere paganism – the paganism of numbers; and from it we must extricate ourselves as quickly as may be, if our people are not to live blindly worshiping force, and with as much peace and harmony in their lives as there is for two cats cruelly and wickedly tied together by their tails. (Free Life, July 1898)

Today, with wars and hate-mongering rampant, Herbert’s psychological insights on the brutalizing
nature of force upon all involved are particularly poignant. If we spotlight only his unique anti-war arguments, a Herbert revival is merited.

Herbert himself must bear some responsibility for his current obscurity, however. He neglected to organize his philosophy into a systematic expression. Indeed, much of his writing occurred in an ephemeral periodical entitled Free Life, which he published – at first weekly and then monthly – from 1890 to 1901. Although an anthology of Herbert’s work, The Right and Wrong of Compulsion by the State and Other Essays, was published in 1978, much more is needed to restore the legacy of this thinker, whom the Austrian economist Richard M. Ebeling once called “one of the most important and articulate advocates of liberty in the last 200 years.”

The Good Funding the Evil


By Larken Rose
[Reprinted with permission from THE MOST DANGEROUS SUPERSTITION by Larken Rose pp 87-92 (2011). Available from Box 653, Huntington, PA 19006 or amazon.com or by visiting http://www.larkenrose.com/store.html ]

Even if an individual is never personally victimized by “law enforcement,” never has a run-in with the police, and sees little if any direct impact by “government” upon his day-to-day life, the myth of “authority” still has a dramatic impact, not only on his own life but also on how his existence affects the world around him. For example, the millions of compliant subjects who feel an obligation to surrender a portion of what they earn to the state, to pay their “fair share” of “taxes,” continually fund all manner of endeavors and activities which those people would not otherwise fund–which almost no one would otherwise fund, and which therefore would not otherwise exist. By way of “taxes,” those claiming to be “government” confiscate an almost incomprehensible amount of time and effort from millions of victims and convert it into fuel for the agenda of the ruling class. To wit, millions of people who oppose war are compelled to fund it via “taxation.” The product of their time and effort is used to make possible something they morally oppose.

The same is true of state-controlled wealth redistribution programs (e.g., “welfare”), Ponzi schemes (e.g., “Social Security”), the so-called “war on drugs,” and so on. Most of the programs of “government” would not exist if not for the belief among the general population in a moral obligation to pay one’s “taxes.” Even “government” programs purported to have noble goals– such as protecting the public and helping the poor– become bloated, inefficient and corrupt monstrosities, which almost no one would willingly support if there was no “law” requiring them to do so.

In addition to the waste, corruption, and destructive things which “government” does with the wealth it confiscates, there is also the less obvious issue of what the people would have done with their money otherwise. As “government” takes the wealth of the producers to serve its own purposes, it also deprives the producers of the ability to further their own goals. Someone who surrenders $1,000 in “taxes” to the ruling class may not only be funding a war he morally opposes, but he is also being deprived of the ability to put $1,000 into savings, or donate $1,000 to some charity he considers worthwhile, or pay someone $1,000 to do some landscaping work. So the damage done by the myth of “authority” is twofold: it forces people to fund things that they do not believe are good for themselves or society, while simultaneously preventing them from funding things that they do view as worthwhile. In other words, subservience to “authority” causes people to act in a manner which is, to one extent or another, directly opposed to their own priorities and values.

Even the people who imagine that their “tax” dollars are doing good by building roads, helping the poor, paying for police, and so on, would almost certainly not fund the “government” version of those services, at least not to the same degree, if they did not feel compelled– by moral obligation and the threat of punishment– to do so. Any private charity that had the inefficiency, corruption, and record of abuse that AFDC, HUD, Medicare, and other “government” programs have, would quickly lose all of its donors. Any private company as expensive, corrupt, and inefficient as “government” infrastructure programs would lose all of its customers. Any private protection service which was so often caught abusing, assaulting, and even killing unarmed, innocent people would have no customers. Any private company that claimed to be providing defense, but told its customers it needed a billion dollars every week to wage a prolonged war on the other side of the world, would have few, if any, contributors, including among those who now verbally support such military operations.

The feeling of obligation to pay “taxes” seems to be little hampered by the fact that “government” is notoriously wasteful and inefficient. While millions of “taxpayers” struggle to make ends meet while paying their “fair share” of “taxes,” politicians waste millions on laughably silly projects–everything from studying cow farts, to building bridges to nowhere, to paying farmers to not grow certain crops, and so on, ad infinitum–and billions more are simply “lost,” with no accounting of where they went. But much of what people make possible through payment of “taxes” is not just wasted but is quite destructive to society. The “war on drugs” is an obvious example. How many people would voluntarily donate to a private organization which had the stated goal of dragging millions of non-violent individuals away from their friends and families, to be put into cages? Even the many Americans who now recognize the “war on drugs” as a complete failure continue, via “taxes,” to provide the funding which allows it to continue to destroy literally millions of lives.

Even the most vocal critics of the various abuses being perpetrated by the evergrowing police state are often among those making that abuse possible, by providing the funding for it. Whether the issue is blatant oppression, or corruption, or mere bungling bureaucratic inefficiency, everyone can point to at least a few things about “government” that do not meet with his approval. And yet, having been trained to obey “authority,” he will continue to feel obligated to provide the funding which enables the same bungling, corrupt, oppressive “government” activities that he criticizes and opposes. Rarely does anyone notice the obvious inherent contradiction in feeling obligated to fund things that he thinks are bad.

Of course, people who work for non-authoritarian organizations can also be inefficient or corrupt, but when it comes to light what they are doing, their customers can simply stop funding them. That is the natural correction mechanism in human interaction, but it is completely defeated by the belief in “authority.” How many people are there who are not currently being forced to fund some “government” program or activity that they morally oppose? Very few, if any. So why do those people keep funding things which they feel are destructive to society? Because “authority” tells them to, and because they believe that it is good to obey “authority.” As a result, they continue to surrender the fruits of their labors to fuel the machine of oppression– a machine which otherwise would not and could not exist.

“Governments” produce no wealth; what they spend they first must take from someone else. Every “government,” including the most oppressive regimes in history, has been funded by the payment of “taxes” by loyal, productive subjects. Thanks to the belief in “authority,” the wealth created by billions of people will continue to be used, not to serve the values and priorities of the people who worked to produce it, but to serve the agendas of those who, above all else, desire dominion over their fellow man. The Third Reich was made possible by millions of German “taxpayers” who felt an obligation to pay up. The Soviet empire was made possible by millions of people who felt an obligation to give to the state whatever it demanded. Every invading army, every conquering empire, has been constructed out of wealth that was taken from productive people. The destroyers have always been funded by the creators; the thieves have always been funded by the producers; through the belief in “authority,” the agendas of the evil have always been funded by the efforts of the good. And this will continue, unless and until the most dangerous superstition is dismantled. When the producers no longer feel a moral obligation to fund the parasites and usurpers, the destroyers and controllers, tyranny will wither away, having been starved out of existence. Until then, good people will keep supplying the resources which the bad people need in order to carry out their destructive schemes.

To Steal or Not to Steal?


By F. A. Harper

 

[Editor’s Note: Dr. Harper was a long time staff member of the Foundation for Economic Education, and founder/president of the Institute for Humane Studies. These excerpts are taken from his article, “Morals and Liberty,” published in the July 1971 issue of THE FREEMAN (pp. 426-441. Excerpts are from pp. 436-439).]

As a means of specifically verifying my impression about the basic, intuitive morality of persons, I would pose this test of three questions:

1. Would you steal your neighbor’s cow to provide for your present needs? Would you steal it for any need reasonably within your expectation or comprehension? It should be remembered that, instead of stealing his cow, you may explore with your neighbor the possible solution to your case of need; you might arrange to do some sort of work for him, or to borrow from him for later repayment, or perhaps even plead with him for an outright gift.

2. Would you steal your neighbor’s cow to provide for a known case of another neighbor’s need?

3. Would you try to induce a third party to do the stealing of the cow, to be given to this needy neighbor? And do you believe that you would likely succeed in inducing him to engage in the theft?

I believe that the almost universal answer to all these questions would be: “No.” Yet the facts of the case are that all of us are participating in theft every day. How? By supporting the actions of the collective agent which does the stealing as part of the Welfare State program already far advanced in the United States. By this device, Peter is robbed to “benefit” Paul, with the acquiescence if not the active support of all of us as taxpayers and citizens. We not only participate in the stealing-and share in the division of the loot-but as its victims we also meekly submit to the thievery.

Isn’t it a strange thing that if you select any three fundamentally moral persons and combine them into a collective for the doing of good, they are liable at once to become three immoral persons in their collective activities? The moral principles with which they seem to be intuitively endowed are somehow lost in the confusing processes of the collective. None of the three would steal the cow from one of his fellow members as an individual, but collectively they all steal cows from each other. The reason is, I believe, that the Welfare State-a confusing collective device which is believed by many to be moral and righteous-has been falsely labeled. This false label has caused the belief that the Welfare State can do no wrong, that it cannot commit immoral acts, especially if those acts are approved or tolerated by more than half of the people, “democratically.”

This sidetracking of moral conduct is like the belief of an earlier day: The king can do no wrong. In its place we have now substituted this belief: The majority can do no wrong. It is as though one were to assert that a sheep which has been killed by a pack of wolves is not really dead, provided that more than half of the wolves have participated in the killing. All these excuses for immoral conduct are, of course, nonsense. They are nonsense when tested against the basic moral code of the five postulates. Thievery is thievery, whether done by one person alone or by many in a pack-or by one who has been selected by the members of the pack as their agent.

“Thou Shalt Not Steal, Except..”

It seems that wherever the Welfare State is involved, the moral precept, “Thou shalt not steal,” becomes altered to say: “Thou shalt not steal, except for what thou deemest to be a worthy cause, where thou thinkest that thou canst use the loot for a better purpose than wouldst the victim of the theft.”

And the precept about covetousness, under the administration of the Welfare State, seems to become: “Thou shalt not covet, except what thou wouldst have from thy neighbor who owns it.”

Both of these alterations of the Decalogue result in complete abrogation of the two moral admonitions-theft and covetousness-which deal directly with economic matters. Not even the motto, “In God we trust,” stamped by the government on money taken by force in violation of the Decalogue to pay for the various programs of the Welfare State, can transform this immoral act into a moral one.

Herein lies the principal moral and economic danger facing us in these critical times: Many of us, albeit with good intentions but in a hurry to do good because of the urgency of the occasion, have become victims of moral schizophrenia. While we are good and righteous persons in our individual conduct in our home community and in our basic moral code, we have become thieves and coveters in the collective activities of the Welfare State in which we participate and which many of us extol.

Typical of our times is what usually happens when there is a major catastrophe, destroying private property or injuring many persons. The news circulates, and generates widespread sympathy for the victims. So what is done about it? Through the mechanisms of the collective, the good intentions take the form of reaching into the other fellow’s pocket for the money with which to make a gift. The Decalogue says, in effect: ‘Reach into your own pocket-not into your neighbor’s pocket-to finance your acts of compassion; good cannot be done with the loot that comes from theft.” The pickpocket, in other words, is a thief even though he puts the proceeds in the collection box on Sunday, or uses it to buy bread for the poor. Being an involuntary Good Samaritan is a contradiction in terms.

When thievery is resorted to for the means with which to do good, compassion is killed. Those who would do good with the loot then lose their capacity for self-reliance, the same as a thief’s self-reliance atrophies rapidly when he subsists on food that is stolen. And those who are repeatedly robbed of their property simultaneously lose their capacity for compassion. The chronic victims of robbery are under great temptation to join the gang and share in the loot. They come to feel that the voluntary way of life will no longer suffice for needs; that to subsist, they must rob and be robbed. They abhor violence, of course, but approve of robbing by “peaceful means.” It is this peculiar immoral distinction which many try to draw between the Welfare State of Russia and that of Britain: The Russian brand of violence, they believe, is bad; that of Britain, good. This version of an altered Commandment would be: “Thou shalt not steal, except from nonresisting victims.”

Under the Welfare State, this process of theft has spread from its use in alleviating catastrophe, to anticipating catastrophe, to conjuring up catastrophe, to the “need” for luxuries for those who have them not. The acceptance of the practice of thus violating the Decalogue has become so widespread that if the Sermon on the Mount were to appear in our day in the form of an address or publication, it would most likely be scorned as “reactionary, and not objective on the realistic problems of the day.” Forgotten, it seems, by many who so much admire Christ, is the fact that he did not resort to theft in acquiring the means of his material benefactions. Nor did he advocate theft for any purpose-even for those uses most dear to his beliefs.

[Editor’s Addendum: I continue to harp on the fact that taxation (for whatever purpose) is theft, and this piece reinforces my contention that even the most limited government must violate the stealing commandment. The purpose behind the stealing is immaterial. It does not matter if the stealing is for government protection from criminals or government provision of welfare. Note Harper’s description that many have become “victims of moral schizophrenia,” meaning that such a person acts honestly in his day-to-day commercial activities, but sees no dishonesty when it comes to “forcing” people to pay taxes. I also like his declaration that one should reach into one’s own pocket – “not your neighbor’s pocket” – to finance acts of compassion and assistance. For further writings on this topic see my articles, “Moral Challenge,” and “Moral Challenge II,’ in Numbers 138 and 141 of THE VOLUNTARYIST.]  ( To Steal or Not to Steal? )

 

A Self-Educated Chicken


By Debbie Harbeson

[This article first appeared in issue 150 of THE VOLUNTARYIST]
I was never much of a rebel. I always did pretty much what I was told and followed mainstream thought. I didn’t want to get into trouble. I didn’t want to stick out. I think the only thing I ever did that would be considered rebellious was underage drinking. But even that’s not particularly rebellious is it?

But something changed when I had my first child. I was a college graduate but realized I was not educated at all about pregnancy, childbirth or parenting. So I began to read and learn all I could about the topic.

I eventually found a group called La Leche League, which is a support group for breastfeeding mothers. Through them, I began learning about other parenting ideas that made sense to me but were fairly counter-culture to anyone outside that group. But now it didn’t matter. I didn’t care because it was working for our family.

I continued to read, listen, discuss and learn. I was completely free to draw my own conclusions and make the decisions my husband and I thought fit our family best. None of these decisions required government permission.

But that ended when my children became school-age and I decided to try homeschooling. Suddenly our lives were affected by the state. I could now not be trusted to do what was best for my children.

At the time, we happened to live in a school district that was going outside of what the law required. We received a letter from the Office of the Prosecuting Attorney telling us that if we did not comply and fill out all the forms, we would be charged with educational neglect, a felony.

This official government letter, on official government letterhead, explained to us that they had primary authority over the education of our children. This official letter telling us they knew best how to educate our children had three words spelled wrong.

I circled the spelling errors in red and wanted to mail it back to them with a big F on it. But I didn’t of course. I’m a chicken.

In reality, I was scared and worried. Not that I would actually be charged because I knew I’d do what they wanted before that would happen. My main goal was to not do anything that might jeopardize my ability to homeschool. Eventually others with more experience and courage got this district straightened out, we turned in the form that was in the law, and were left alone.

But when it all settled down, I just got mad. Mad at how we were treated, how we were disrespected, how they were willing to use force against us if necessary. That’s probably the root point at which I began to lose respect for any government authority.

I wanted to forget about government and politics and concentrate on raising my family, but I couldn’t. I needed to stay informed about the law, at least as it related to education, because any change in the law had the potential of drastically changing our family’s entire life.

At this time, online message boards were beginning to grow and I participated in online discussions about homeschooling freedom. I subscribed to Home Education Magazine, which has a monthly column called Taking Charge written by Larry and Susan Kaseman. They kept me informed and thinking about homeschooling freedom. I read books by education reformer John Holt and realized how much a child benefits when given freedom to learn and became a proponent of unschooling.

I discovered the Separation of School and State organization and joined. I became rabid in my belief of freedom in education. I was definitely becoming an educational anarchist, though I never thought of it that way at the time.

I eventually ran into people online identifying as libertarian. Once again I found myself learning about a whole new idea that was outside mainstream thought.

When I began asking more questions about it, someone online recommended Harry Browne’s Why Government Doesn’t Work. It was the first book about liberarianism I bought and I remember really being hit for the first time with a moral argument against the state as he explained that government is force and it is back up by a gun.

I eventually found the Libertarian Party and my husband and I started the affiliate in our county. Still being a chicken, I convinced my husband to take the chairman position fearing that I could not handle any publicity.

The state party had an online message board and I began once again to educate myself about a new topic. The typical energetic purist/pragmatic debates were going on and I loved it. However, state party leaders became uncomfortable with the image these debates might be giving to potential members so they shut it down.

I was learning so much and really enjoying the debates so I decided to start my own list and made it clear there was no affiliation with the party. It was about this time I discovered Murray Rothbard. I read his book For a New Liberty and found myself consulting this book often as we debated and discussed various topics. I also received good information from the Advocates for Self Government, which is where I discovered Mary Ruwart. I bought two of her publications, Healing Our World and Short Answers to the Tough Questions. I consulted these often too. These were not the only books I read, I was also very ignorant about economics and read a lot of books in that area beginning with Economics in one Lesson by Henry Hazlitt.

It should be no surprise that I was all about using the Libertarian Party as an educational tool. I remained involved in the LP for a few years, even running for state senate at one point, running an educational campaign. After that campaign experience, the problems inherent in making changes through politics became even clearer to me.

During discussions, I began to get more frustrated that others in the party didn’t seem to be reaching the same conclusions as I did. I kept on reading and thinking about the philosophy but others did not appear to be doing the same. They seemed to be more concerned and busy with the details of operating a political party.

Then one day someone said I was not a libertarian, I was an anarchist, Me? An anarchist? How can a chicken be an anarchist? Talk about out of the mainstream.

At some point I found the online site, Strike the Root and began reading their “non-voting archive.” I found every single article interesting but when I read George Smith’s LP Dialogue, I was completely fascinated because it mirrored many discussions I had been involved in for so long.

I noticed this article came from a site called Voluntaryist.com and that’s when my life took another turn. I felt like this time, I really did find a place where others had reached the same conclusions as I did. So much of what I read on the site matched my thinking. But most of all, the suggestion that one needs to simply focus on the improvement and education of the self resonated strongly. Self-education is where it all started for me and where my life continues to focus.

What I do now is still focused on education. I have a weekly column, “The Suburban Voluntaryist,” in the local daily paper where I write about local issues from a voluntaryist perspective, as much as that is possible. I do this mostly for myself because it helps me think and learn. If my writing helps someone else to do the same, then I’m very enthused, but if not, it’s still okay.

What’s odd now is that many readers are surprised at what I say and how I say it. They think it’s either courageous, crazy or just plain stupid to be so forthright. They don’t believe me when I say I’m still a chicken. But I am. I’m still not living my life in a manner as consistent to voluntaryist ideals as I would like.

I know I can improve though which has led me to another project. I want to read all of The Voluntaryist issues, in context, from the beginning. I feel like there’s a treasure in those pages and all I have to do is start reading. Carl Watner has done so much for voluntaryism by keeping this publication going for so long and I want to really get a feel for the publication as it developed.

I want to see what else I have to learn – about voluntaryism, about myself – and since writing is a big part of how I learn, I’m going to blog about it as I go through the process. Carl said he will participate if he has the time and as long as it is valuable to him so hopefully I will get more insight from his current perspective as well. We’ll see how it goes.

If you are interested in following and perhaps even participating in this project along with me, then by all means join me. Share your thoughts of agreement, or disagree and set me straight. Add your unique perspective. Let’s learn together. The blog is here: http://debbieandcarl.blogspot.com/

On Power and Trust


 

By Carl Watner

I have been reading some very old back issues of THE FREEMAN and have already shared at least one gem with you.

Here is another interesting commentary.

In an October 1977 book review, Henry Hazlitt observed that the problem with ever-expanding democratic government is not a problem limited to the democratic form of government. “Is it not rather that of all government?” In other words, all forms of government tend to break beyond their limits.

And isn’t this the problem that has so far proved intractable? Writers from time immemorial have tried to solve it with facile and question-begging phrases. Aristocracy must be the best form of government, because it means government by the wisest and the best. Ah yes; but how do you get the people to recognize and choose and put into power the wisest and the best? Well then, in any case, the government, however chosen, should be only given very limited powers, so it cannot abuse them. Ah yes, again. But what powers? Can we draw a precise line around them? Can we get enough people to agree on that line? And even if we can once draw such a line, giving neither too little nor too much, how can we prevent whoever the government is from using whatever powers it already has, to extend its powers still further?

We come back to the fundamental dilemma: To prevent chaos, violence, rapine, or rule by the gangsters, somebody must be trusted with some power; but nobody can be completely trusted with much power. [From Henry Hazlitt’s book review of POPULAR GOVERNMENT, THE FREEMAN, October 1977, p, 640]

How is a voluntaryist to respond?

“Yes,” we will always have people with us who act in a criminal manner. “Yes,” peaceful individuals will always need protection from criminals.

The question thus becomes: how do we best protect ourselves from the criminal element? The usual answer to this question is: Some form of government is necessary to establish peace and maintain law and order in society. Otherwise violence and chaos will ensue. The voluntaryist rejects this answer as a false alternative.

As we know, the government way is to monopolize protection by placing the most serious means of protection (police, courts, and army) in the hands of those who work for the government. The government way is to outlaw any competition in the production of security and to collect its revenues by way of taxation. In practice and theory, this means that any one not wanting protection, or choosing to reject the government service, or choosing to protect themselves is imprisoned for failure to pay for a government service which they do not desire. These arrangements place very dangerous powers in the hands of government agents. They are only limited by how much uproar, clamor, and ultimately, evasion and resistance, their subjects will exercise. Paraphrasing the ancient Romans: Who is to protect us from our protectors?

The voluntaryist way does not rely on trust in the production of security any more than it does in the production of food, shelter, clothing, or other necessities of life. Yes, a grocer may turn venal or criminal or even be negligent. But the grocer cannot force you to trade with him; nor place you in jail, nor confiscate your property if you refuse. Competition and the general societal respect for private property is what keep people honest and trustworthy. When the grocer knows you can turn elsewhere to buy your food, he is forced by that knowledge to satisfy your wants (if he wants to trade with you). He knows that he can no more command you to trade with him at terms he chooses, than you can force him to sell you his goods at prices you set.

The government operates within a totally different environment. Legislators know they can have other government employees use violence to enforce their statutes. Internal Revenue agents will eventually turn up at your door if you do not pay your federal taxes. If you do not pay the IRS, armed federal marshals will show up next – to haul you off to court. If you refuse to go, you will be attacked and possibly murdered like the recalcitrant people at Waco, TX and at Randy Weaver’s house in Idaho. The crimes of the lawmakers are legion. Who wouldn’t act this way if there were no serious consequences? History has proven, time and time again, that governments expand their powers and break whatever constitutional limits are designed to constrain them. As Lord Acton noted, government power corrupts because government agents are not held to the same standards of accountability that we apply to private individuals. The commandment says thou shall not steal and kill, though government agents act as though it says, “Unless you are the government.”

The voluntaryist way relies on competition in the production of security. Different people may choose different levels of defensive protection, depending on their ability to pay and their demand for protective services. They will hire protective agencies just as they hire purveyors of food, shelter, and clothing. What will the poor do? They will do just as they did in the days before government assistance. They will look for charitable relief to protect them.

Is it possible that private protection agencies may turn criminal? “Yes,” but the institutional structures of a free society minimize the chance, whereas in a government society the government already acts in a criminal manner (though only a minority of people recognize it to be so). The voluntaryist way, as F. A. Hayek once pointed out, “is a system under which bad men can do least harm” because some people are not compelled to follow the legislative mandates of others.* Given that people in private service are no more angelic than men and women in government service – what are we to do if some protection agency tries to act like a government and ‘force’ people to buy its services, and then locks them up if they refuse? First, we are not to sanction and legitimate their crimes (by calling their stealing ‘taxation’ or their murders ‘resistance to court orders’). Second, we are to totally boycott and ostracize those who disrespect and violate our lives and property. Third, we are to keep in mind that it is always our primary duty to ourselves and our family to be able to protect ourselves, in the event that our protectors turn on us. (This may mean training in nonviolent resistance or violent forms of self-defense.) Fourth, we are to keep our wits about us. Just as it requires vigilance and diligence to buy the right product at the right price, it requires these same two traits to see that those we hire to protect us do not do not turn on us. We have to be aware that our night watchman may become a thief and try to rob us.

There are no guarantees in life. We have to be careful, but if we rely on the right set of institutional incentives we will get the best possible – though not perfect – results. Paraphrasing Murray Rothbard, a free society discourages the criminal tendencies of human nature and encourages the peaceful and removes the only legitimated channel for crime and aggression .* “Yes,” there will still be criminals in a voluntaryist society, but they will be fewer and less powerful than those in a statist society. Voluntaryists will always choose to rely on voluntary methods of protection, knowing “if one takes care of the means, the end will take care of itself.”

*cited in Murray Rothbard, “Myth and Truth About Libertarianism,” MODERN AGE, Winter 1980, in Myth 5, and reprinted in THE VOLUNTARYIST, Whole No. 95, December 1998, pp. 5-6.

NONVIOLENCE: A REVIEW OF MARK KURLANSKY’S 2006 BOOK BY THAT NAME


By Ned Netterville

I seldom come across a book by an Earthling (voluntaryists and Austrian economists are from Mars or Venus, depending on their gender) that sends me to my feet pumping my fist like Tiger Woods when with talent and force of will he sends a forty-foot put curling into the cup. But that’s what I caught myself doing as I read Mark Kurlansky’s 2006 book, Nonviolence, subtitled Twenty-Five Lessons from the History of a Dangerous Idea. This is a must-read for anyone desiring world or local peace but perplexed by how to achieve it.


The clarion-clear message of this narrowly focused history of the use of violence versus nonviolence is that when it comes to throwing off forcible oppression, nonviolent resistance beats violence hands down. Yet so little is understood regarding its effectiveness and accomplishments that there is no word in any language for the opposite of violence beyond the negative, nonviolence. Kurlansky shows that failure to understand that nonviolence is an efficacious means and a potent force in the hands of peacemakers or the oppressed is a serious mistake benefiting only warriors and tyrants. The author points out, “it has always been treated as something profoundly dangerous” by the rulers of states. His concise history traces the concept of nonviolence among ancient people of various religions up to the recent past. He deduces from his examination that “Though most religions shun warfare and hold nonviolence as the only moral route towards political change, religion and its language have been co-opted by the violent people who have been governing societies.”


Kurlansky distinguishes between pacifism and nonviolence: “Pacifism is passive; but nonviolence is active. Pacifism is harmless and therefore easier to accept than nonviolence, which is dangerous… . Nonviolence, exactly like violence, is a means of persuasion, a technique of political activism, a recipe for prevailing.” And, I might add, nonviolence has a potent spiritual component that the initiators of violence cannot comprehend and have no means to counter.

Kurlansky’s narrative points to the almighty state as the ultimate villain in causing wars, although he doesn’t explicitly say so. He does say that when church and state combine, both become depraved. Jesus was both a pacifist and so dangerously nonviolent that the Roman Empire murdered him. His early followers adopted his ways, but when the Christian church was subsumed by the Roman Empire during Constantine’s reign, Christianity betrayed the teaching of Jesus. Augustine concocted a theory to justify war, and Christians have been warring ever since. Kurlansky refers to its amalgamation with Rome as “a calamity from which the Church has never recovered.” And he adds, “One of history’s greatest lessons is that once the state embraces a religion, the nature of that religion changes radically. It loses its nonviolent component and becomes a force for war rather than peace.”

Kurlansky’s narrative illuminates twenty-five lessons from the history of nonviolence, which he enumerates at the conclusion of the book, but there are certainly others to be found therein by the discerning reader. Here are a few of the enumerated lessons that have not already been mentioned:


———Nations that build military forces as deterrents will eventually use them.
———Practitioners of nonviolence are seen as enemies of the state.
———A propaganda machine promoting hatred always has a war waiting in the wings.
———People who go to war start to resemble their enemy.
———A conflict between a violent and a nonviolent force is a moral argument. If the violent can provoke the nonviolent into violence, the violent side has won.
——— The problem lies not in the nature of man but in the nature of power.
———The state imagines it is impotent without a military because it cannot conceive of power without force.
———All debate ends with an “enforced silence” once the first shots are fired.
———Violence never resolves. It always leads to more violence.
———Once you start the business of killing, you just get deeper and deeper without limits.
———Violence always comes with a supposedly rational explanation.
———Violence is a virus that infects and takes over.
———The hard work of beginning a movement to end war has already been done.

Here are a few other lessons extracted from Kurlansky’s work:


———Government propaganda makes war out to be a holy crusade for freedom.
———It is much easier to start a war than to stop it.
———A war will never end wars; it always leads to the next one.
———If one doesn’t stand up for what’s right, what’s wrong will never change.

I find only one flaw in Kurlansky’s brave book. He fails to notice the obvious connection between the violent nature of the state, which causes every war, and the predatory means by which the state obtains funds that are vital to its wars and to its very existence. I am referring, of course, to taxes, without which a state must whither and die. The collection of taxes requires the initiation of force, or threat thereof, against otherwise peaceful, harmless, innocent individuals. Force is but another word for violence, and violence begets only its kind–more violence. Directly and indirectly, then, taxes cause wars. No war has ever been fought without taxes or an equivalent other form of state plunder.

When Kurlansky writes that the hard work of beginning a movement to end war has already been done, he wasn’t referring to his book, but to the words and deeds of the practitioners of nonviolence, such as the Chinese rebel, Mozi (470 – 390 B.C.), Jesus, Gandhi, and Martin Luther King (among the most famous). With the publication of his book, Nonviolence, Kurlansky joins that illustrious group of workers who have shown us the whys, the how’s, and the ways of nonviolence.

K. I. S. S. A Pig! – Anarchist or Minarchist?


By Carl Watner

In recent years, there have been countless words exchanged between free market anarchists and limited government minarchists concerning such questions as

  1.  Must every human society have a government?
  2.  Is government necessarily coercive?
  3.  Can government be financed voluntarily (i.e., without coercion)?

Debates over these questions have been going on for well over a hundred years and include such authors as Charles Lane (A VOLUNTARY POLITICAL GOVERNMENT, [1843]), Herbert Spencer (“On the Proper Sphere of Government” [1842/1843] and “The Right to Ignore the State” [1850]), Benjamin Tucker (INSTEAD OF A BOOK [1897]), and Auberon Herbert (TAXATION AND ANARCHISM: A Discussion Between the Hon. Auberon Herbert and J. H. Levy [1912]). Although I am familiar with these authors, and have written about some of them (my Introduction to Lane’s book [1982], and my overview of “The English Individualists as They Appear in LIBERTY” [1985]), the article you are now reading was originally sparked by a December 20, 2009 interview with Dr. Tibor Machan in which he stated:

Rothbard said governments are necessarily coercive and I disagree; he thought government must be a coercive monopoly and I disagree. … I’m a principled minarchist like Rand. … I am convinced that minarchism can avoid all coercion and Rothbard was wrong claiming otherwise. … If all citizens select a group of them to administer the just laws of the land, coercion is absent. [1]

Dr. Machan then adds a parenthetic note to see his essay, “Reconciling Anarchism and Minarchism,” in ANARCHISM/MINARCHISM: Is a Government Part of a Free Country? (2008), the book he co-edited with Roderick T. Long. Of course, Dr. Machan has a long list of contributions he has made to this controversy, including his discussion of “The Anarchist Thesis” in HUMAN RIGHTS AND HUMAN LIBERTIES (1975); “Financing Government without Coercive Measures” in THE LIBERTARIAN READER (1982); and “Defining Government, Begging the Question: An Answer to Walter Block’s Reply” in JOURNAL OF LIBERTARIAN STUDIES (Spring 2007).

Undoubtedly many readers are familiar with the general principle of logic behind Occam’s razor or its popularized version, Keep It Simple, Stupid! Referred to as the “Law of Economy, or Law of Parsimony” it points out that entities and questions “are not to be multiplied beyond necessity.” So to cut to the quick and cut through the thousands of words of controversy, generated by anarchists and minarchists alike, I would like some minarchist to answer the following question:

What would their defense service organization do if it could not attract enough voluntary customers?

If the minarchist acknowledges that his limited government organization would go bankrupt or disappear, then the discussion is ended, and the anarchist argument prevails. For if the government’s response to a loss of customers is to go out of business (like every other business that loses patronage and cannot sustain itself financially), then it is clear that such a government has no coercive monopoly on the administration of justice and protection of property within the area in which it operates. Other defense agencies may arrive to take its place, and there is nothing the bankrupt defense agency can do about it, since it is no longer in existence. In short, as Gustave de Molinari described it in 1849, there would be a free market in “the production of security.”

This is nearly the exact question I presented to Dr. Machan in an email of February 21, 2010:

What happens to a minarchist government if its citizens for whatever reason withdraw their financial support and boycott it?

Such reasons might reflect the fact that they have all become pacifists, or that they all have decided to choose personal self-defense in lieu of minarchist protection, or that they have decided to choose another agency to provide them with protection.

In other words, what happens to a limited government organization if its citizen/customers choose not to patronize it? Will it go bankrupt? Will it disappear – if not, by what means will it survive?

To which Dr. Machan replied:

“Such a country would vanish, as any other establishment lacking support would.”

Enough said!

There are two other comments worth making. First, in the last line of the quoted interview, Dr. Machan pointed out that “If all citizens select a group of them to administer the just laws of the land, coercion is absent.” True enough, if there is unanimous consent and every “citizen” has a voluntary contract with the service provider. John Hospers made this same point in a written debate with Murray Rothbard in 1973. Here is how Rothbard responded:

Dr. Hospers maintains that if one private agency should “predominate in a certain area, it would in effect be the government. … [T]here would be very little difference” between that and a single government agency of protection. … It must be pointed out that even in these conditions, it makes a great deal of difference, because (a) individuals can always have the right to call in another, competing defense agency, and (b) the private agency would acquire its income from voluntary purchases of satisfied customers, rather than from the robbery of taxation. In short, the difference between a free society and a society with built-in legalized aggression. Between anarchism and archy. [2]

The second comment regards the answers to the three questions with which I opened this article. In order to do so, it is necessary to define “government” and distinguish its essential characteristics from other types of defense service organizations. In his article on “Defining Government,” Dr. Machan makes the following comments.

“The gist of my case is that the anarchists’ defense-insurance agencies or justice services are a version of noncoercive governments.” [p. 91]

“Why are we to accept that the concept ‘government’ necessarily implies coercion (e.g. taxation)? The fact that most governments have been coercive is no more of a defense of this position than it would be to claim that the concept ‘marriage’ necessarily implies adultery because most marriages throughout human history have involved adultery … . [p. 92]

“Some … libertarians chose to retain the term ‘government’ for the institution that would maintain law and order in society; others came up with new terms such as ‘defense-insurance agency.’ But both meant the same thing, namely, legal authorities who would proceed to establish, maintain, and uphold justice via a legal order without ever officially using coercive force.” [p. 92]

“Defense-insurance agencies are governments of a certain type.” [p. 94]

Apparently, Dr. Machan views government as a broad class of institutions that maintain law and order in society, and which can be either coercive or voluntary. Although I have not seen him use the terminology, he might describe the coercive versions of government as “political governments” and the non-coercive versions as “voluntary governments.” He clearly rejects political government because it is coercive, and supports only voluntary government.

But how, we ask, are we to distinguish voluntary governments from all other voluntary institutions and non-coercive organizations in society? There are many, such as the family, the church, the various businesses we patronize, the various clubs we belong to, various associations, such as the Red Cross, the American Baseball League, etc., etc., all of which contribute to the maintenance of law and order. Every legitimate property owner and every peaceful person in society help maintain law and order by their exercise of self-control (not violating other people’s bodies or other people’s property). The spontaneous, free interaction among peaceful people is the only true form of law and order that is possible. Political governments can only produce “political” law. As John Hasnas explains in his “The Myth of the Rule of Law,” coercive governments purposefully associate “law” with “order” as a way to deliberately obfuscate the fact that a voluntary social order can be had without the presence of a political government. As John Blundell and Colin Robinson write in REGULATION WITHOUT THE STATE (2000), “Rules are an essential part of life. But making them is not necessarily a [political] government function: they can be (and usually are) established through voluntary action.” The so-called law and order fashioned by political governments is not really true law or true order because it is not based on the voluntary interaction and the voluntary consent of the participants. Furthermore, whatever legitimate contribution political governments make to the voluntary social order could be provided in a far less costly and far more moral manner by private defense agencies. In short, just as we need food, shelter, and clothing, we need rules for peacefully interacting with others; but it is no more necessary that political government provide us with food, shelter, and clothing, than it provide us with the rules and regulations for peaceful interaction with our fellow man. Political government not only negates property rights, but rents asunder the peaceful fabric of society.

Finally, Dr. Machan asks “Why are we to accept that the concept ‘government’ necessarily implies coercion (e.g., taxation)?” In reply, let us quote Ayn Rand who asks: “Who has the final authority in ethics? … Who ‘decided’ what is the right way to make an automobile … ? Any man who cares to acquire the appropriate knowledge and to judge, at and for his own risk and sake.” By Dr. Machan’s own admission “most governments have been coercive.” Governments have been construed as coercive institutions because that is the way their representatives and leaders have acted historically; because that is the way they behave today; and because there is no better way to view the difference between criminal institutions and voluntary ones than to identify those as governments which exercise coercive power. A government which resorts to no coercion is not a government because it is a voluntary organization claiming no special powers of obedience. To describe some governments as non-coercive is like painting the word ‘dog’ on the side of a pig, and then calling the pig a ‘dog.’ A pig is still a pig regardless of what you call it or how many times you kiss it or how many times you bathe it. It’s the same with governments. As long as they continue to imprison people and/or confiscate the property of those who refuse to pay their taxes, they are coercive. Only when they stop doing these things and allow competition in the production of security will they have exchanged their essential coercive features for voluntary ones.

End Notes

[1] 4th and 6th paragraphs from the end of “Tibor Machan on the Free-Market, the Problems of ‘Mixed’ Economies and the Virtues of Minarchism,” December 20, 2009, in the email newsletter THE DAILY BELL, from Appenzell, Switzerland.

[2] Murray Rothbard, “Will Rothbard’s Free-Market Justice Suffice?” REASON Magazine, May 1973. Reprinted in Carl Watner (editor), I MUST SPEAK OUT, San Francisco: Fox & Wilkes, 1999, pp. 47-48 at p. 48.

Quote to accompany this article:

“In the real world, there is never any difficulty identifying a voluntary-funded firm and a coercive, tax-funded government agency. You simply look at how the organization obtains its funding – if the funding comes from voluntary payments, it is a firm or charity, while if the funding comes from sticking a gun to men’s heads, it is a government agency or a criminal gang.”

– Mark Crovelli, April 2010

From Slingshot to Nukes


By Carl Watner

[Author’s Prologue: This article was written in April 2005, and remained unpublished until this issue. My reason for hesitation is stated in my opening sentence: how could an advocate of nonviolence extend the argument for property rights to include nuclear bombs? What prompts publication at this time is the appearance of John Gatto’s book, WEAPONS OF MASS INSTRUCTION: A Schoolteacher’s Journey Through the Dark World of Compulsory Schooling (2009). First, a bit of humor and an example of serendipity. When I first read Gatto’s book, I took the title to be WEAPONS OF MASS DESTRUCTION, which is how I view government, tax-supported, schools. It was only after discussing the book with friends that I realized my error.

Then, as I read the book, I found a section titled “Building Bombs” (pp. 117-119), which made me think of this old article and gave me reason to publish it. Gatto explains that information on “how to produce powerful explosives cheaply and with ordinary materials” was widely available a hundred years ago. Why so?

For anyone who understands what the miracle of America once was (and is no more), that it was a forge to convert slaves, serfs, peasants and proletarians into free men and women, explosives were an important part of self-reliance and liberty. They were important tools in clearing land, digging foundations, constructing ponds, building roads, moving stones, digging gold mines – perhaps in the gravest extreme defending your family’s liberty from agents of the political state. Isn’t that how we got a United States in the first place? Has the possibility of a tyranny here miraculously vanished? But violent conflict aside, and melodrama with it, the tool aspect alone ought to be the common right of free citizens. And whether you agree or not isn’t as important as realizing that less than a hundred years ago, perfectly ordinary people were trusted to handle power like this with responsibility. (pp. 118-119)

Exactly my sentiments, and while one might argue that the only purpose of a nuclear bomb is an aggressive threat, one must keep in mind the similarity of the concluding word of Gatto’s quote and my article: “responsibility” and “responsibly.” Remember, one can make an aggressive threat with a tree branch. Should the ownership of trees be outlawed? As a wag once observed: the reverse side of the coin of freedom is responsibility. It is not the objects we act with, but rather how we act with them that determines whether or not they are invasive and threatening.]

It might seem strange that a voluntaryist who has published many articles advocating nonviolence would write a subsequent one arguing for private property rights in heavy armaments, even nuclear bombs. Odd as this may appear, let me explain the genesis of this article and the logic that links the right to gun ownership and voluntaryist resistance together. First of all: the genesis of this article. My sons, William and Tucker, have been interested in hunting and target shooting for a number of years, and a friend gave us a copy of the December 2004 issue of the National Riflemen’s Association magazine, AMERICAN RIFLEMAN. In that issue Wayne LaPierre, NRA Executive Vice President, had a column in which he mentioned his debate in London, England on gun control with Rebecca Peters of IANSA (the International Action Network on Small Arms). The debate was on video; I obtained a copy; and, as might be expected, Mr. LaPierre and Ms. Peters were asked: “Where would you draw the line in regulating weapons ownership?” If you “allow” small hand-held sporting weapons, what about semi-automatic rifles, shotguns, shoulder-fired rockets, and suitcase-size nuclear weapons? My answer was that ownership rights to properly homesteaded property extend all across the weaponry spectrum; from slingshots to nukes.

I then wondered if any other libertarians had taken this position, publicly or privately. Robert Heinlein, the well-known science fiction writer, noted in his 1966 novel, THE MOON IS A HARSH MISTRESS that it is still “some” lone individual, whether in his capacity as a private citizen or government official, that ultimately controls the disposition of nuclear weapons.

“History’s most important lesson is that it has not been possible to make coercion compatible with truth.” – John Langbein in Alfred McCoy, A QUESTION OF TORTURE (2006) p. 204

“Too much power in the hands of individuals — surely you would not want … well, H-missiles for example — to be controlled by one irresponsible person?”

“My point is that one person is responsible. Always. If H-bombs exist — and they do — some man controls them. In terms of morals there is no such thing as ‘state.’ Just men. Individuals. Each responsible for his own acts. [Book One, Sec. 6]

Hans-Herman Hoppe in his essay on “The Idea of a Private Law Society” noted that in a libertarian society “no restrictions on the private ownership of firearms or other weapons would exist.” [http://www.mises.org/story/ 2265] [paragraph 23] Concomitantly, he observes that the statist provision of law and order “has led to the successive disarmament of the population.” All governments have a natural inclination to disarm their subjects because, as Hoppe puts it, “it is less dangerous to collect taxes from an unarmed man than from an armed man.” In a free society, where protection services are provided by insurance companies and private defense agencies, there would be an incentive for private citizens to be well-trained and certified in the use of weaponry of all sorts. Hoppe points out, that just as home owners with alarm systems often receive insurance discounts, so, too, “those able to certify some level of training in the handling of arms” would be charged “lower premiums reflecting the lower risk they represent.”

The main proponent of private ownership of nuclear weaponry, however, is the libertarian newspaper writer Vin Suprynowicz. In his book, THE BALLAD OF CARL DREGA (Reno, 2002), Mr. Suprynowicz relies on the United States Constitution, and its Second Amendment, to defend gun ownership. For example, he argues, “All federal lawmaking authority is vested in Congress. Is the Congress authorized to permit or ban or allow or infringe the private ownership of arms? … Under our [constitutional] system, th[e federal] government can acquire no right, power, or authority except those delegated to it by the people [via the Constitution].” [pp. 340-341] He concludes that any Congressional regulation of the private ownership of firearms is, ipso facto, unconstitutional. Instead of questioning the legitimacy of the Constitution, Mr. Suprynowicz blithely asserts that, “The founders were careful to note that they found mankind’s natural rights to be pre-existing” and “insisted that the ‘securing’ of those pre-existing rights [wa]s the only legitimate purpose of government.” [p.468]

In summary, Mr. Suprynowicz argues that since the federal government possesses nuclear warheads, it must have derived that right from somewhere. That “somewhere” he finds is in the individual American’s right to own them. In other words, since individual Americans have the “right, power, and authority to own nuclear weapons,” they may delegate that right to their protector, the American government. [p. 341] In response to a reader’s question: “Do ‘I advocate the unrestricted right to own weapons of mass destruction’?” he replies, “No, I acknowledge this pre-existing right of all individuals to own such weapons.” [pp. 419-420, emphasis in the original]

“So long as there is government, there shall be no peace and no justice.” – John Simpson

As I pointed out in my article about the Bill of Rights, “The Illusion Is Liberty – the Reality is Leviathan,” [I MUST SPEAK OUT (San Francisco, 1999)] the first ten amendments to the Constitution were essentially a legitimizing device used by those favoring a strong central government. James Madison believed that the amendments were needed to forestall Anti-Federalist criticism of the Constitution. Under the English common law “basic, natural, and fundamental individual rights were protected whether enumerated specifically in the Constitution or not,” so there was really no reason to have a Constitution or Bill of Rights. Depending upon the Second Amendment to defend individual ownership of weapons has only led to insuperable difficulties (as evidenced by the question: where do you draw the line?). The Second Amendment is at most superfluous to the case for gun ownership for two reasons. First, it implies that gun ownership rights may be be subject to change if enough votes are garnered to amend the Constitution. Second, it ignores the point that weaponry ownership is not a special case, but rather depends upon the justification of property ownership in general.

As a voluntaryist, my starting points are the libertarian self-ownership and homesteading axioms. Each person has the absolute right, by virtue of being a human being, to own his or her own mind and body; that is to control that body and mind free of coercive interference. Similarly, each person, by virtue of his or her owning his or her own labor, owns previously unused natural resources which he or she is the first to claim and transform by that labor. Nuclear weapons are the end product of the application of human labor to natural resources. If they were conceived, invented, and built on the free market (a big assumption, indeed – the development of such weapons was strictly the outgrowth of government wars) then there can be no objection to the ownership and sale of such property. From a straight property rights/property title view point, so long as the property has been homesteaded or voluntarily transferred, there is every reason to argue for unrestricted ownership of weapons, of whatever type. The caveat is that the owner is always liable for their responsible use, just as the owner of a car or a knife is responsible for its safe use and handling. One well might ask: Can nuclear weapons be used responsibly and in a strictly defensive manner? But that question is irrelevant to the considerations of proprietary justice and ownership. (One might well own something, without ever using it.)

At one point, Vin Suprynowicz refers to a “God-given constitutionally guaranteed right to self defense.” [p.376] Voluntaryists would recognize a natural right to self-defense, which includes using their bodies and properties in a defensive manner, albeit, violently or non-violently. If the right to self-defense is “constitutionally guaranteed” does not this imply that such a right might be changed by constitutional amendment? Individuals have the right to use their bodies and property to resist what we collectively view as evil or wrongdoing. As the voluntaryist insight points out, no ruler exists without the cooperation and/or acquiescence of the majority of his subjects. The revolutionary implications which stem from this simple observation are earth-shattering. Non-violent resistance, which flows directly from the self-ownership and homesteading axioms, is the political equivalent of the atomic bomb. From sling shots to nukes to nonviolent resistance, these choices all flow from the individual’s right to use his or her body and property responsibly.

In Defense of Our Own Freedoms


By Carl Watner

Hans Sherrer, a long-time subscriber and contributor to THE VOLUNTARYIST lives in Seattle, and mentioned a new book that he heard about which documents the evacuation of all people of Japanese ancestry from Bainbridge Island, Washington in early 1942. The book is titled IN DEFENSE OF OUR NEIGHBORS: The Walt and Milly Woodward Story, written by the Woodward’s daughter, Mary Woodward. The Woodwards were coeditors and copublishers of the BAINBRIDGE REVIEW from 1941 until 1963. “During World War II, they used the paper to speak out against the exclusion of their Japanese American friends and neighbors” of whom there were some 270 among 50 families on the island. (Woodward, p.16) The Japanese Americans had few defenders at this time, so this extended report of their support is welcome. Nonetheless, the story of the internment of American citizens of Japanese ancestry in concentration camps on US soil is just another proof that “war is more destructive of freedom than any other human activity.” (Linfield, p. xvii)

For those not familiar with this history the brief facts are: Pearl Harbor was bombed by the Japanese Air Force on December 7, 1941. As documented in declassified information and numerous books, President Roosevelt and his foreign policy advisers maneuvered Japan into striking an American port in the Pacific, in order to justify the United States’ entry into World War II. Executive Order 9066 was issued by President Franklin Roosevelt on February 19, 1942. It established defense zones within the United States, and gave military commanders authority to exclude people from such areas. (Linfield, p. 92) On March 19, 1942, both houses of Congress approved Public Law No. 503 (77th Congress). This legislation made it a federal offense for any person to violate restrictions issued by a military commander in any defense zone established under the earlier Executive Order. (Weglyn, p. 72) Subsequently, over 110,000 Japanese Americans were removed from their residences to a number of camps in the western United States, and many of them were held there for the duration of the war.

This episode presents a number of interesting anomalies: Among others –

…..The Japanese bombing of Pearl Harbor not only brought about America’s entry into the war, but served as a catastrophic excuse to imprison Japanese Americans and confiscate their property.

….. Italian and German Americans were not rounded up en masse during the war.

….. The confinement was racially motivated. As Lt. General De Witt wrote in 1943, “A Jap’s a Jap. It makes no difference whether he is an American citizen or not …”. (Weglyn, p. 201)

….. When several Japanese Americans challenged their confinement in the civil courts, government officials responsible for the internment lied to the courts (and the American public) about the military dangers presented by the Japanese in this country.

….. Both the Executive Order and Congressional law clearly violated the constitutional requirements that “the writ of habeas corpus shall not be suspended, unless when in cases of rebellion or invasion the public safety may require it”; and that no person shall be deprived of life, liberty, and property without due process of law. Not only is this an example of the government violating its own constitutional rules, it goes far in demonstrating that limited government is not possible, because every government always seeks to expand its powers.

….. Leaders of the Japanese American community supported the government crack down, hoping that their willing cooperation would prove their loyalty. (This is reminiscent of what Hannah Arrendt observed about the leaders of the Jewish community: they, too, willingly cooperated with the Nazis and urged their co-religionists to peacefully enter the ghettos.)

….. After being imprisoned, the American-born males were required to register for the draft. Those who refused to register or report for induction were given extended criminal sentences.

….. The Constitution and constitutional safeguards it embraced were held in disdain by government officials. “Assistant Secretary of War [John] McCloy clearly stated his position: ‘[I]f it is a question of the safety of the country [and] the Constitution . . . . Why the Constitution is just a scrap of paper to me.'” (Hirase, pp. 149-150)

….. Military officials explained the absence of sabotage by those of Japanese ancestry on the west coast as evidence that they were planning attacks. No evidence has ever surfaced supporting such a bizarre explanation. As Lt. General DeWitt wrote: “The very fact that no sabotage has taken place to date is a disturbing and confirming indication that such action will be taken.” (Rostow, p. 521)

From a voluntaryist perspective, this bit of American history supports Theodore Lowi’s contention that “every action … of government … contribute[s] to the fulfillment of its fundamental purpose, which is to maintain conquest.” While other governments “have used war and the threat of war to stifle freedom” in their own countries, the United States has been at the head of the pack, in “proclaiming freedom to be our national purpose.” (Linfield, p. xv) If ever the American citizenry were to see through the facade of governmental legitimization, they would soon realize that the greatest threat to their freedoms comes from their own government.

In my article “Vices Are Not Crimes” defending Walter Block’s book, DEFENDING THE UNDEFENDABLE, I recounted the story of H.L. Mencken (so far as I know he never criticized the internment of Japanese Americans) who was accused of being a Nazi supporter because he never spoke out against Hitler. When he was asked if he was an anti-semite, Mencken replied:

I believe in only one thing and that thing is human liberty. If ever a man is to achieve anything like dignity, it can only happen if superior men are given absolute freedom to think what they want to think and say what they want to say. I am against any man and any organization which seeks to deny or limit that freedom.

When questioned whether he would limit that freedom to superior men only, Mencken replied: “The superior man can be sure of his freedom only if it is given to all men.” Or as Benjamin Constant wrote in “On Conquest and Usurpation,” “Freedom cannot be denied to some men and granted to others.” The message is clear: We need to take a principled stand against all violations of individual rights; we need to defend our own freedoms, as well as those of our neighbors regardless of their race, ancestry, creed, political belief, or religion. There will always be criminals among us, but our hope, as voluntaryists, is to rid ourselves of criminal institutions by abandoning our reliance on coercive governments. When that occurs, both our freedom and the freedom of our neighbors will become far more secure than it is now.

Short Bibliography

Joanne Hirase, “The Internment of Japanese Americans: The Constitutional Threat Fifty Years Later,” 19 JOURNAL OF CONTEMPORARY LAW (1993), pp. 143-183.

Michael Linfield, FREEDOM UNDER FIRE: U.S. Civil Liberties in Times of War, Boston: South End Press, 1990.

Edward S. Miller, WAR PLAN ORANGE: The U.S. Strategy to Defeat Japan, 1897-1945, Annapolis: Naval Institute Press, 1991.

Eric L. Muller, FREE TO DIE FOR THEIR COUNTRY: The Story of the Japanese American Draft Resisters in World War II, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 2001.

Eugene Rostow, “The Japanese American Cases – A Disaster,” 54 THE YALE LAW JOURNAL, June 1945, pp. 490-533.

Michi Weglyn, YEARS OF INFAMY: The Untold Story of America’s Concentration Camps, New York: William Morrow and Company, Inc., 1976.

Mary Woodward, IN DEFENSE OF OUR NEIGHBORS: The Walt and Milly Woodward Story, Fenwick Publishing Group, 3147 White Point Drive # 100, Bainbridge Island, WA 98110, www.fenwickpublishing.com, 2008, ISBN 978-0-9749510-7-2

[Thanks to Jim Russell and Hans Sherrer for their helpful suggestions.]

Liberty, The Mother of Order – A Book Review


By Carl Watner

Nobody, not even those in the government, knows what is going to happen in life. People are not automatons. There is a certain regularity to life; the earth revolves on its axis such that the sun “rises” every morning and “sets” every evening, but neither my life nor yours repeats itself exactly as the day before. I can leave my place of businesses wondering whether we will have work to do the next day. When I return the following morning, before we even open, people appear: one needs chicken feed, another horse feed; two have cars that need repair; one wants a transmission flush; another needs four new tires. All this unscheduled work appears overnight. People’s desires change; babies are born; people die; there are new inventions; people have accidents; people make new discoveries (they have a flat tire, they have run out of feed). If one were a government planner, one could either react to this with amazement and wonderment or disgust. Should people have the liberty to do what they want with their bodies and property or should there be some central institution that tells them what to do and controls all this activity? Does private property provide us with a means to a peaceful and prosperous world? Or should things be “dictated” by the State and its directives? Is liberty the mother of order in our human societies? As Wendell Berry once wrote, is the “attempt at total control … an invitation to disorder [and disaster]” or just what humans need?*

Butler Shaffer in his new (2009) book, BOUNDARIES OF ORDER: Private Property as a Social System, argues that “individual liberty and social order are obverse sides of the same coin.” (xiii) A harmonious society can only come about if people are not coerced by thieves, muggers, murderers, gang members, or government agents, who in the process of exercising violence force people to do what they would not otherwise choose to do. In other words, voluntary exchanges take place only because both parties expect to benefit. The spontaneous actions of millions of individuals aim at nothing less than the improvement in their well-being. But people can only act if they have property to act with. They must use their bodies in some specific space (even if they do nothing but think with their mind, they are somewhere). That is why private property constitutes a social system, and why such a system brings about higher standards of living. People are not always successful, but in the vast majority of exchanges they do better themselves.

The underlying theme of his book, as Shaffer describes it, is “that our traditional institutional model [of government] is not only no longer useful to, but actually destructive of, the purposes for which we have long embraced it. This book will suggest and explore an alternative model for the peaceful and productive conduct of society.” (25) This paradigm is based “on the principle of the private ownership of property; that freedom is possible only when private ownership claims are respected;” and that the very “existence of political systems” means that private property has been violated. (xiii) Using private property as a yardstick three critical questions need be answered in any social conflict – 1) Whose property is it? 2) Who has aggressed? and 3) Who has been aggressed against? With a slightly different twist, one can determine the amount of government aggression in society by asking – how much of a criminal does one become by minding one’s own business; and to what extent do government employees confiscate property? In short, if you can ignore the government, by using your own property as you choose, and if the government does not put you in jail or seize your property for failure to pay your taxes, then you’re probably facing an institution that possesses little coercive power.

One of the recurring observations throughout this book is that regardless of “[w]hatever system of ownership is in place, someone will exercise decisional authority over property.” (6) Whether one is living under Hitler’s national socialism, Stalin’s communism, Britain’s fabianism, or American democracy every political system must answer the question: “how are decisions to be made in the world, and who will make them?” (9) The reason for this is the “need of all living things to occupy space and ingest energy.” (133) “Each of us must be able to exclude others from the use and consumption of resources necessary for our survival.” (123) In other words, private property “is at the core of” our humanness and “our well-being.” (133) We must own ourselves and then the property that we require for survival.

A perfect example of how a collectivist system must answer the question “who decides on the use of scarce resources” is found in a short scene from Nien Cheng’s LIFE AND DEATH IN SHANGHAI (pp. 406-407 in the 1988 edition). The author, after having been imprisoned for six years, was released and wanted to have a brick wall constructed in order to create a small bedroom in her hallway. In order to do so, she had to bribe the driver of an electrical utility truck to help transport the bricks. In answer to the author’s query as to whether this was legal, and whether or not the mileage and gas consumption of the truck was checked, the driver answered

“Don’t forget, in a socialist state, everything belongs to the people. You and I are part of the people.” …

“Well to tell you the truth, I feel uneasy about using this truck, for my private purposes. I don’t really think it’s right.”

“We have public ownership in China. Right? Who is the public? We are. Right?”

So despite the long-standing claim of collective ownership in a communist society, the driver of the truck decided who could make use of it as a tool of transport. Someone has to decide, whether it is an individual, or a committee, or a politician, or a policeman. The idea that there can be societal-wide collective ownership is a propaganda myth. Furthermore, as Shaffer points out, the ultimate test of ownership comes down to this: “who can decide, without getting the permission of another, to destroy […]his property?” (171) The truck driver could not decide whether or not to destroy the people’s truck, nor could the utility manager. Ultimately, Mao Zedong or someone or some group of people within the Communist Party held that decision-making power.

As in his earlier works, Shaffer refers to chaos and complexity theory, and points out that an orderly system may arise out of apparent disorder. (65) “[T]he substance of social order is found in the regularities that arise, spontaneously and without any intention to do so, from the interplay of [voluntary] human behavior.” (73) Three important observations in this regard are: first, that each person’s capacity to obtain accurate information on which to make decisions is limited; second, that the further a person is from the actual source of knowledge, the more likely there is room for error; and third, that “when we allow the [S]tate to make decisions for an entire population, we run the risk of utter disaster should the” decision be wrong. (44, 280) Decision-making by those who risk their own property not only localizes the impact of wrong choices, but allows people everywhere the freedom to copy those who succeed. (42,84)

THE BOUNDARIES OF ORDER is the result of many decades of the author’s thinking about the interrelatedness of social order and private property. He clearly comes down on the side of voluntaryism, arguing “that liberty and order imply one another.” (297) In other words, voluntaryism comes about naturally if no one does anything to stop it. This book is not for a budding, or even beginning, voluntaryist. It requires deep concentration, patience, and assumes a basic familiarity with the concepts of self-ownership and homesteading. Although Shaffer embraces the idea that the first to claim and use an un-owned resource thereby becomes its legitimate owner, he also recognizes that without the support of one’s neighbors, one’s claim to ownership will never be respected. As Rose Wilder Lane explained in THE DISCOVERY OF FREEDOM (pp. 109-110 in the 1943 edition), the protection of our property ultimately depends upon human decency.

The only safeguards of property seem to have been possession of the property, individual honesty, and public opinion.

… [C]abins were never locked on the American frontier where there was no law. The real protection of life and property, always and everywhere, is the general recognition of the brotherhood of man. How much of the time is any American within sight of a policeman? Our lives and our property are protected by the way nearly everyone feels about another person’s life and property.

With that Butler Shaffer would surely agree.

*Numbers within parentheses refer to Shaffer’s book unless otherwise noted. The expression “Liberty, not the daughter, but the mother of order” was attributed to Pierre-Joseph Proudhon by Benjamin Tucker, who used it as the flag on his anarchist paper, LIBERTY, for many years. The quote by Wendell Berry is attributed (by James C. Scott in his book, SEEING LIKE A STATE [1998], p. 288), to his book THE UNSETTLING OF AMERICA.

Why Voluntaryism Is the Best and Only Legitimate Moral Philosophy


By Ross Kenyon

I explicitly refer to myself as a voluntaryist because I believe voluntaryism to be the only moral position worth assuming. It is my opinion that the only reason libertarianism is worth a damn is because it is a philosophy of non-aggression which acknowledges the incalculable value of individual sovereignty.

Non-coercion is infinitely preferable to coercion. Even statists will agree with this abstract statement, albeit befuddledly. Libertarianism and conservatism as a whole still endorse the concept of forcing others into systems based upon their respective ideologies. Voluntaryism isthe moral philosophy because it leaves room for Marxists, monarchists, theocrats, and everyone else to exercise their negative rights of self-ownership and self-determination. I completely respect the initiative of individuals who wish to form a socialist commune where the negative rights of the participants are neglected in favor of a collectivist ethic. This can be completely consistent with voluntaryism so long as everyone participating is doing so voluntarily and they are not violating the person or justly acquired property of those who remain outside of their preferred system. In other words, it is not consistent with voluntaryist values to coerce others into any form of libertarianism. Voluntaryists respect the fact that others might not wish to live as they live. “Anything that is peaceful” is a core value of voluntaryism. This is one of the first ways I broach this subject with statists and minarchists alike.

I declare that the individual has a legitimate right to govern him or her self and to voluntarily associate with any other individual so long as it is consensual and non-aggressive to those outside of the agreement. With self-admitted state socialists this is one of the first things I will proffer. In my experience, convincing someone who instinctively distrusts the free market and loves the state that the inverse is consequentially better is an arduous and frustrating process. Rather than trying to convince involuntaryists that my ideal system has better results than theirs, I will submit that there is room for both of our philosophies on this planet. The Earth is large, and all I request is that the negative rights and justly acquired property of individuals who prefer other systems be left unmolested and in full retention of their sovereignty. This is a very reasonable assertion and does not confront any competing philosophy on any grounds except for the element which is based upon coercion in the place of voluntary association. If they believe it is moral to force others into their system I would challenge them to explain on what grounds they have inherited the authority to rule others. I condemn this idea of authority as immoral and coercive.

In addition to the sovereignty argument, I will approach our close ideological allies of the minarchist movement with the point that they have made their peace with participating in systemic coercion so long as they can use the guns of the state to create their version of a just society. Pragmatically, many libertarians believe that statism is so thoroughly entrenched that it is better to try to work from within, solemnly protecting the few crumbs of freedom that remain. They simply underestimate the moderating and corrupting force state power has upon those who wield it.

There is no middle ground between coercion and non-aggression. Trying to dismantle systems of coercion by gaining the ability to use coercion is not only inconsistent with the ends of voluntaryism and a free society but our participation in electoral democracy signals our consent to be governed by democracy. I am a voluntaryist because I respect the wishes of individuals to live their lives as they see fit so long as they are non-aggressive, and I hope that the same courtesy will eventually be shown to me. I oppose coercion no matter what costume or badge is worn and I do not acknowledge the validity of involuntary relationships.

Without voluntaryism, individuals will continue to try to solve the complex ethical problems facing us by resorting to coercion through the state. They will be forever incapable of creating a just society because they start with the premise that aggression is an acceptable tool to address social problems. It is time for us to respect the self-determination of all people. Voluntaryism is not only the moral way; it is theonly way to peace and justice.

[The author is a senior of American History at Arizona State University. Contact him at rmkenyon@asu.edu. An earlier version of this essay appeared January 2, 2010 on www.libertariansolution.com.]

Declaration of Renunciation and Severance of U.S. Citizenship


by Jeff Knaebel, Sovereign Individual of the Earth

Jeff’s posthumous manuscript titled Message From a Moral Sovereign: The Life and Death Story of an American’s Journey from Warpath to Gandhi Path was published in India in Fall 2011. A 320 page paperback, it is now available from The Voluntaryist for (**) postage paid to US addresses or (**) elsewhere, sent to

The Voluntaryist
P.O. Box 275
Gramling, South Carolina 29348

You may send Federal Reserve notes, stamps, gold, or silver, but please No checks or money orders.

You can also send bitcoin to 1N9chGG4Dpp8Lw1eDye9wjiskAVqaiCi2Y, which you can click to email us your address.

(See Jeff’s autobiographical article, “How I Became A Voluntaryist,” at
http://www.voluntaryist.com/forthcoming/farewelltomurder.php)
This Declaration, made at New Delhi, India on 19 June 2009, WITNESSETH:

To the people of this Earth, my fellow human beings, my brothers and
sisters, in memory of Black Elk and Chief Joseph, and with special
respect to the Grandmothers and Elders of all indigenous communities,

I, Jeff Knaebel, hereby make this Declaration of Severance and
Dissolution of all bonds between myself and the Government of the
United States of America. I renounce my birth certificate – I renounce
my citizenship – and reject all claims of whatsoever nature made by
the United States against me. I am not government property, and I am
not a criminal. I am a peace-loving human being who is finished with
being a slave to the Corporate Warfare State. I am not a citizen of
any Government. I renounce all of them.

I hereby destroy my United States passport by which the United States
government claims control of my movement upon this earth, and thus
lays claim upon my right to exist. I will place the shredded remains
of my passport upon the monument of Mahatma Gandhi. I have chosen this
monument because it is a symbol that all mankind can recognize: of
nonviolent resistance to immoral, corrupt, and violent Governments.

By this deliberate act of rebellion and sedition, I hope to free
myself and alert mankind to the dangers it has created by obeying
Governments of the world. My refusal to remain a tax-compliant
accomplice to State murder will be considered treason against the
United States. The choice is this, or treason against human life
itself. My life is not about supporting the cold blooded murder of
women and children.

No permission is required to renounce that which I never sought in the
first place, for which I never entered a contract, and which is
imposed upon me against my will. Having declared myself not a
citizen, I am therefore not a citizen. Citizenship is either
voluntary, or it is forcible slavery.

The United States government is incomprehensibly malevolent and
destructive. It takes our money, our identities, and our lives. It
gives us back corruption, war, heinous crime, and lies. This
government has no moral right to exist. It ought to be abolished
without further human bloodshed.

The Nation State is a criminal organization which must be opposed in
its very concept. It is impossible to reform a system that is built
upon a foundation of lies and violence — one whose health and
continuance depends upon endless war. The system must be altogether
abolished. It is irredeemably evil.

The State represents a terminal disease of human consciousness that is
anti-life, anti-ethics, and suicidal for the human species. It is a
sick addictive co-dependency between its citizens and parasitic lying
murdering psychopathic politicians.

Blind obedience to incompetent, deceitful, violent and morally
depraved authority is a clear case of mental disease. Eckhart Tolle,
Gopi Krishna and other morally advanced beings have diagnosed the
United States government as pathologically criminally insane.

All political authority is arbitrary: arbitrary as to the form it
takes; arbitrary as to the boundaries it establishes; arbitrary as to
the limits of its jurisdiction; and arbitrary as to the taxation it
collects. If one refuses to bow, to obey, to pay one’s taxes, to use
Government travel documents, one will ultimately be placed in jail, or
die resisting arrest.

Even in its most equitable form, it is impossible for government to
disassociate itself from evil. The State has been conceived in
violence and is maintained by lies and violence. Its every act can
only be criminal. Unless the right to ignore the State is recognized,
its citizens become tainted accomplices in its deeds.

From the most democratic to the most totalitarian form of government
there is ultimately no difference among the powers they exercise. The
essence of the State is the threat and use of deadly force against
those who choose not to comply with its edicts.

No Government rightfully owns the territory its monopolizes. It has
stolen possession of whatever land it lays claims to. Everything it
has, the State has stolen or plundered. It prevents peaceful people
from establishing their own voluntary cooperative economic and social
relationships. The purpose of assigning nationality is to control a
mass of captive taxpayers in order to maintain the large military
establishment required to keep a citizenry in a state of fearful
submission to the Power Structure of money.

Why should a system of structurally compulsively violent political
authority be preferred to a cooperative system in which human beings
live according to the Natural Law of equal liberty? A coercive
government has no legitimate authority over me. None. Its only
authority comes through the barrel of a gun.

Is the arbitrary “legal” construct of the Corporate State more
precious than life? Is this guns-and-steel lifeless structure more
precious than living, breathing beings? This killing machine
fabricated of cunning deceitful words of legally piggily on corporate
parchment… Are we living beings or abstract symbols to be
manipulated by the Money Power? What is the “National Interest,”
other than the transfer of wealth and influence to the power elite?
What about humanity’s interest?

I write against the oblivion of humanity. I act in quest of goodness,
beauty and truth, that we may yet live.

I am not Government property. I bid farewell to the United States
Government and to the citizenship it has imposed upon me against my
will. I love life too much to be forced to participate in its murder.

The United States government is a stain upon humanity. It is a
grotesque distortion of human relations and the human conscience. It
is ugly beyond the power of words to describe. Only its end product
speaks clearly for what it is and what it does. “Shock and Awe” death
raining from the sky. Children’s blood flowing in the streets. Body
parts strewn across wedding festival grounds. A human genome
corrupted by depleted uranium and agent orange. Hiroshima. Los
Alamos Lab. The science of death versus the art of life. Torture.
Rape. Ecocide. Endless heinous crime. The most terrible Merchant of
Death in human history. Human species suicidal.

If you, people of the world, wish to support Government, then so be
it. But leave me alone. As a peaceful individual I reject your
authority imposed by violence. I reject all Government claims of
legitimacy. You and your Government do not have the right to do the
things that you do. Foremost among these tax-and-public debt financed
activities are the waging of war; the conscription of soldiers; and
the expenditure of citizens bread labor upon armaments which by now
can destroy our earth many times over. I call for an end to these
activities. I will not support such activities with my life, my
money, or my energy.

The laws of our natural world, the laws of the Great Spirit, the five
precepts of the Buddha, are morally and practically superior to
political laws. You must not kill and I must not kill. We must not
support killing. We must love our neighbors as we love ourselves. As
the Hopi have said, “From this one commandment, to respect and revere
life, come all the other commandments: to tell the truth, to share
with others, to life together in mutual support, to take care of our
children and old people, the sick and strangers, friends and enemies,
to abstain from intoxicants and adultery, not to cheat, steal, or
covet.”

It is up to the individual to discern his duty to his fellowmen and to
act accordingly. No other can know my moral conscience, let alone
“represent” it in decisions of war and peace. How can another
“represent” me in voting to murder children? The first duty of love
is to do no harm. Therefore my duty of love is to renounce the State,
to withdraw from it, to quit it, to abandon it, to refuse to pay its
taxes, to refuse participation in its charade of corporate money
controlled elections, and to live my own life in search of truth and
righteousness.

What do you do when you awaken to the awfulness of the lies of the
State and the State of the lie? How does one negotiate with
pathological liars? How does one come to peace with his tax payment
hiring of cold blooded murder for oil and money?

Against whom, then, shall I commit treason? The brotherhood of man?
My rational mind and common sense? My moral conscience? Or the
United States government? I prefer treason against the arbitrarily
imposed rule of an organized crime syndicate to treason against
humanity. To suffer in tax compliant silence the heinous crimes
against humanity perpetrated by the United States would be to negate
whatever is within me that can be called human.

The shredding of my government permission-to-exist documents is
offered as a prayer that the government of the United States —
perceived to be a criminal organization of incomprehensible scope —
may be without bloodshed dissolved and abolished from this earth
forever.

I no longer have a Government name; I have no country, no travel
papers, no passport, and no Government identification. Under the law
of every Government, I am an illegal human being. Against this
arbitrary “illegality” I claim my right to exist as a free and
sovereign individual.

What man — or group of men — can declare another to be “illegal?”
Such men, who cannot give life, would yet take it, as lying murderers
in God’s own temple. For Power, there is no tomorrow. There are no
grandchildren. Of the good earth, there is none. There is only
Power. Persons who aspire to this are degraded, deranged, diseased.
We are insane to submit to rule by the depraved.

What shall be done with me?

If deported to the United States, the Government will subject me to
draconian penalties. Having destroyed my passport, having renounced my
citizenship, having made this Declaration, I have become a seditious
rebel to the United States Government. The United States will have no
choice but to harass, persecute, and ultimately jail me for speaking
truth to power.

On the one hand, the natural wish to live, to grow, to move about, to
be free, to act as a man. On the other hand, in order to live in this
manner with the ordinary amenities of livelihood, I am forced by
taxation to finance the murder of children who have a sacred right to
life — innocent small children who cannot conceive of the wish to
harm me.

There comes a time when the abuses are so great, the mindless
destruction so wanton, the suffering so stupidly unnecessary, that one
must resist the Power of rulership with his life. I love Life too
much to participate in its murder.

I bid you farewell, those who would remain in voluntary bondage. Go
about your life peacefully, respecting yourself, all others, and the
earth upon which we live. Remember that means is to end as seed is to
tree. A violent means can never produce a good end. The truth shall
set us free. My efforts shall not have been in vain. Right always
overcomes might, even though I may not live to see the day.

Whatever happens to me, may you remember my message: Awaken from your
slumber. Realize that Government depends upon your consent. You
control yourself. You can withdraw your consent.

We must recover Respect — for life, and for each other.
Civilizations that get off the Path of Respect do not last, because
when a people get off the path, they also remove themselves from the
circle of life.

My prayer is to love and to serve. From my heart I seek to act in a
good way, in a sacred way, for the benefit of many, in support of
life, that the seventh generation of children may yet live and be happy.

The “why” of what I do is put completely to rest by the statement, “I
love.” The final answer to any question about my actions is “I
love.” What is the value of human life — this is the real question.

Executed at New Delhi this 19th day of June 2009

Jeff Knaebel

Why The West?


By Paul Rosenberg

[Editor’s Note: In early May 2009, I read a book, PRODUCTION VS PLUNDER, written by Paul Rosenberg, a subscriber to THE VOLUNTARYIST. (See www.VeraVerba.com for ordering information.)The short section entitled “The Foundation Is Established” (pp. 137-139) reminded me of an article that I considered writing a number of years ago (but which never came to fruition). The idea for such an article was sparked by another essay, one written by Jim Powell. It was titled “Why Has Liberty Flourished in the West?” and appeared in CATO POLICY REPORT, Volume 22, Number 5, Sept/Oct 2000. (Available in pdf format on the web.) One of the initial questions I had about Jim’s thesis was: Is it proper to assume that liberty did flourish in the West? Perhaps it is correct to say that it did, if you compare it to other world civilizations and cultures. The answer, however, would be much different if you compare it to an imagined world where there were no coercive governments. I wrote Paul to see if he was interested in addressing this topic. Here is his overview.]

TWO QUESTIONS AND THEIR IMPORTANCE

1) Has liberty flourished in the West?

2) Why was it at least in the running (compared to other civilizations)?

Before we examine the answers to these questions, it is important to understand that the West has led humanity forward in many ways. Consider the following recent improvements in human life:

·More food and more variety of foods. (Modern grocery stores.)

·The ability to store food. (Refrigeration.)

·Better cooking techniques. (Stoves, ovens, microwaves.)

·Healthy environments. (Central heat, central air, no open fires inside.)

·The availability of immense power, almost anywhere. (Electricity.)

·The ability to travel. (Affordable autos, airplanes, etc.)

·Increased knowledge. (Books, newspapers, the History Channel.)

·Increased communication. (Radio, cell phones, Internet, etc.)

·Machines that perform mundane chores. (Washing machines, etc.)

All of the above were developed in the West, and are (more or less directly) the result of increased liberty. So, this is not only an interesting question, but an important one.

WHAT IS LIBERTY?

We must begin with the contrast between liberty and coercive governments. The idea that a government provides liberty is false, although it is close enough to a true statement to confuse many people.

Governments, at their very best, provide protection against external military threats. This may certainly have benefits, but it is not liberty – it is military protection. It is important to separate the two. Consider it this way:

Hitler attacked the USSR in 1941. The USSR eventually drove the Nazis back and won military safety for their people, but those people were certainly not “free.” The military victory did not establish liberty – it established the rule of Stalin, probably the number two killer in world history.

Liberty is the ability to live without interference, restricted only by the equal rights of others.

Being militarily safe is useful, but it is not the same as liberty.

HAS LIBERTY FLOURISHED IN THE WEST?

The short answer is, “yes, it has.” The ideas of individual rights, secure private property, freedom of speech, a free press, freedom of religion, equality before the law and free trade are all Western ideas.

What I mean by “equality before the law,” is that justice applies to every person equally – rich or poor, from a good family or not, with powerful friends or without, and so on. Law, in general, can be useful in some forms and tyrannical in others. Law need not be conjoined with the State. Indeed, if law were separate from State (as was often the case in centuries past), it would be a great tool for justice and liberty. But, this is a long discussion, for another time and place.

While it is true that liberty flourished in the West, it most certainly has not flourished without restraint. We do have States, after all, and States are organizations that may only survive by forcibly taking the property of others – which is definitely contrary to liberty. Aside from a scattered few places – and for short moments at that – we have not had full liberty. We have, however, had partial liberties and have benefited from them.

Liberty has certainly not thrived as much as many of us would like, but it has thrived to a considerable and useful extent.

WHY IN THE WEST?

This is the interesting question. I have no single, absolutely certain answer, but there are many partial answers, some of them going back into pre-history. I’m arranging these in no particular order. I’m certain that all of these are significant, but I’m not sure how to rank them.

Language

Western (Indo-European) grammar, with its categories of gender, its sharp distinction of person and number, and its great emphasis on chronological tense, instills a certain level of logical attitude toward life. In contrast, the languages of the Far East emphasize relative class levels.

This is probably a larger issue than you would first think it to be. What people assume in their very speech has a powerful effect upon them, even if thoroughly unnoticed. This is especially true because language is acquired in early childhood, with many subsequent ideas being built upon its foundation.

This is a well-know issue among professional manipulators. One of their key phrases has long been, “Control the vocabulary and you control the argument.” For example, as John Hasnas explains in Voluntaryist #123 (page 8), by associating the idea of voluntary order with the State, the possibility of a non-State order is almost completely eliminated. When someone with a new idea comes along, he or she is derided as being “self-styled,” as if anything unapproved by the established order is evil. Again, this is powerful stuff, and most people shortcut their thinking by repeating slogans that they have heard others use successfully.

Separation

The Western tradition features heroes who separated themselves from everyone else. Abraham was commanded to separate himself. Moses commanded Israel to be separate from all other peoples. Jesus commanded his students to remain separate from the teachings of the other Jewish sects. And so on.

This is a potent idea. Separation allows new ideas to develop and permits people to move forward with much less internal restraint. After all, following the examples of Abraham, Moses and Jesus has been an effective moral defense at most places and times in the West.

And there is one more crucial element here: The separation ideal declares that the group is not to be followed and that unity is not a morally-superior strategy. This undermines collectives of all types and the ever-so-common intimidation that keeps most people tethered to the tribe. It is this “tether” that often destroys individuality before it is fully formed.

Subversive Religions

The religions of the West – Judaism and Christianity – are subversive religions, even though most of their leaders would rather not admit it. (They must generally support the State in order to get favors such as tax exemption.)

Abraham fought kings; Moses defied the Egyptian king, and the twelve tribe of Israel lived without one for several hundred years; the prophet Samuel warned against a king; Jesus died as an enemy of the State; the first Christians were all enemies of the State; and so on.

Judaism and Christianity are not good religions for rulers, nor are they good for State cohesion. These are religions that very specifically enthrone justice above rulership.

For this reason and others, people who adhere to these religions are more likely than most others to risk their safety for righteousness and progress. “Seeking the praise of God rather than men” is a powerful thing.

An excellent example of risking one’s safety for what is right is the English hero “Freeborn John,” A.K.A., John Lilburne. (Jim Powell goes into some detail on this hero in the article referred to above.) Lilburne was brought into the English justice system for unlicensed publishing, and refused to plead until he had heard the charges leveled against him. In other words, he refused to incriminate himself, as was common at the time.

Freeborn John was whipped, dragged by an oxcart, placed in stocks (where he handed out pamphlets), and finally thrown in jail. He still refused to surrender his “freeborn rights.” Lilburne actually spent most of his adult life in jail, but, thanks to him, both English and American law features the right not to incriminate one’s self. Not surprisingly, Lilburne was a very religious man, at various times a Quaker and a Puritan.

Farming

Westerners have almost always been farmers, as opposed to herdsmen or hunters.

Farmers tend to see the world as a positive-sum game and nomads as a zero-sum game. The important thing about this is that positive- or zero-sum assumptions form in human minds and – if not analyzed and adjusted – color wide areas of thought. This affects all sorts of opinions and judgments. People take these basic views of the world as givens: things they don’t need to waste time examining; things that are considered to be known. This builds great differences in the thoughts of the farmers and the nomads.

Young nomads were instructed to take, from a world of limited resources.

Young farmers were instructed to use the world intelligently and to create food.

Farmers learn to live cooperatively. They help build each other’s barns, share tools, lend their expertise for repairing their neighbor’s equipment, and so on. They also respect each other’s property lines. Herdsmen, on the other hand, tend to mistrust their neighbors and to hide information from them. If the nomad finds good grazing land, he does not share that knowledge. If he finds a hidden water hole, he does not disclose the location. Cooperation is less likely and plunder more common among nomads. Rather obviously, liberty is the fellow-traveler of cooperation and the opponent of plunder.

Cold

Most Western cultures are also northern cultures. There have been a number of interesting theories put forth as to why most advances are made in cold places. Certainly the inability to be lazy without freezing plays a major role. Active people, after all, produce more than inactive people, and in cold places, inactivity can be fatal. This is an interesting area of study.

New Continents

In the 17th Century, people in the West found an opportunity to flee all expectations and re-create civilization on a new continent. This was a very important and powerful force in the West. In our current situation, people with radically new ideas are considered dangerous to one extent or another. What if they could simply leave, go to some new, un-ruled place and try living their new way? What new strategies might be revealed as superior to thought-choking obedience?

In the 17th Century, freedom-seekers could leave their homelands. Bear in mind that this was a much more complete “leaving” than is possible in our time. A fitting example of this is the modern tax protester. We could say to him, “If you don’t like it here, go somewhere else,” but this is actually no choice at all for the tax protester – the deal is the same everywhere. If an American tax protester goes to Canada, he finds a nearly identical situation. If he goes to Germany, it is the roughly same, and the same can be said, more or less, for all of the earth’s two hundred States. If, however, there was an empty continent available, the same tax protester could simply leave and do his best to build a new life however he wished.

So, a great many such people came to the New World, bringing their wild new ideas and transformative energies with them. The New World of North America owes a much bigger debt to the ‘Crazies’ of Europe than many ‘respectable’ types would like to acknowledge.

Disasters

This answer goes fairly deep into speculation, but it is worth mentioning.

For the last half-million years, our planet has experienced a string of at least four ice ages. In each of them, a huge portion of the earth has been covered with ice and snow and the rest of the planet was much colder than it is now. In the last ice age, what are now Indianapolis and St. Louis were covered with glaciers – a lot like Greenland’s current condition. Even the areas where soil was exposed were much colder than they are now.

The Ice Ages were mega-disasters in the north, but not for the equatorial areas. The entry and exit from an ice age is problematic for tropical areas, but that was a very short time compared to the overall 100,000 year cycle, and still no comparison to areas farther from the Equator.

As mentioned earlier, Western culture is primarily northern culture as well, and it is certainly a culture with strong disaster images, as exemplified by the story of Noah’s flood. This type of image cultivates a feeling of non-stability – all things will not remain as they always have been. They have massively changed in the past and they will massively change again in the future.

It can be argued – though I’m not aware of any really pertinent evidence – that tropical cultures lacked this disaster model, and were more likely to accept the status quo, as “things have always been this way, and always shall.” A northern Christian, for example, would be far less likely to accept this argument; assured that – at the very least – the Second Coming would be likely to occur soon and totally reset everything. Even the Roman Catholic Church the grand enforcer of sameness during the Middle Ages – struggled with this problem.

God Versus State

Since the Judeo-Christianity of the West was a subversive religion (as mentioned above), it has very often struggled against the State. Normally this is thought of as the State preventing the Church from turning into an oppressive theocracy (which has certainly occurred), but that is only one side of the issue. When massive ideologies (like Church and State) oppose each other, it opens up cracks, where liberty can flourish. (And they do oppose each other, since both compete for the full respect and devotion of the people.)

God has been a significant idea throughout western history – the big idea at the top of the ideological “food chain.” That makes it very useful as a moral and intellectual weapon against other ideologies that wish to control men. The idea of God is very difficult to overpower. This allows “God” to serve as a protection from other dominators. Such uses of the God-idea provides open space in which liberty can prosper and grow. This is exactly what happened in the West between the 14th and 20th Centuries. Here are a few examples:

·The “rule of law” formed when the Church saw it as a tool they could use to keep princes in line. Remember that there was very little man-made legislation during the Middle Ages, and that “naturally” discovered law was not the handmaiden of the State. In those times, the law was actually sovereign above the prince. (But, again, this subject requires a more detailed explanation than we can give it here.)

·One of the pivotal elements in the growth of western civilization has been the role of personal initiative. Individuals took it upon themselves to pursue the things they wanted. They did not wait to get permission from the civil or religious authorities. One of the first places where this initiative surfaced was in the universities of Western Europe. For example, men like Peter Abelard (founding father of the University of Paris), took it upon themselves to create better ways of learning, and sold their services to individual customers. Although the universities eventually received charters from popes, emperors, and kings, they were originally self-governing private enterprises in which the teachers had to please their customers (the students) or otherwise lose their patronage.

·The medieval guilds played Church against State and existed in the gap between the two spheres, first aligned more with Church, then more with State, and always with a foot in each. Some of these guilds, such as the Merchant’s Guild, built massive trade networks throughout Europe, especially in the north. They were careful to publicly express their piety, which kept some princes at bay. (“We’re close with the Church, don’t mess with us.”) And being adaptable merchants, they were able to shift tactics frequently. Not all guilds were as effective and decent as the Merchant’s Guild, but they were able to create some open space between Church and State, within which they could operate.

These situations were always strained and hazardous, but they did provide free space for liberty to grow… and grow it did!

ADDITIONAL QUESTIONS

I am confident that this list contains most of the core reasons why liberty flourished in the West, but I would like to deal with a few loose ends before I finish:

Why Not The East?

I can give you two partial answers:

·The languages. Looking at the world in terms of status puts humans in mental chains and sometimes in physical chains as well. It keeps minds from functioning freely. This slows the growth of liberty to a very significant degree.

·Less farming. Nomadic civilizations are less conducive to liberty, and there have been more of them in huge areas of the East. The fact that large areas of the East were less than ideally suited to farming was merely chance.

Is The West The Ideal Culture?

No, it certainly is not. We have plenty of deeply ingrained problems in our midst. The difference with the West is that is was less bad, not that it was ideal.

Regardless of all the obstacles, liberty is always powerfully present in some men. In the majority, however, it is present to an extent, but is mostly suppressed. Even in the “less bad” West, liberty only flourished at moments, and was usually stomped-out at the earliest convenient time. Most modern Westerners would run in horror from full freedom; many would beg for a strongman to crush it.

Huge numbers of Westerners care more about six-packs and big-screen TVs than they do about liberty. They don’t even know what real liberty is; nor would very many be willing to sacrifice anything for it.

HUMAN NATURE

The truly stunning thing about liberty is that it harmonizes with the highest and best functions of human nature. A book would be required to address this subject decently, but the point is an important one: The parts of men’s natures that do not resonate with liberty are those which have been manipulated, corrupted, or left undeveloped.

Liberty is the essential soil for an advanced human existence. It can flourish in no other.

Thank God liberty found some cracks in the West. It is our job to understand this and to create new cracks, then to break up the pavements and let liberty thrive unhindered – in both the West and in the East.

We have been like plants that struggle to grow through the cracks of a concrete parking lot. Humanity will never rise toward its awesome potential until we clear space to spread our roots and branches. Liberty, and liberty alone, provides the fertile ground we need.

Get to it!

An Open Letter on Taxation to the Global Ethic Foundation


January 18, 2009

Doctor Hans Kung

Global Ethic Foundation

Waldhauser Strasse 23

72076 Tubingen

Germany

(email: office@weltethos.org)

Dear Doctor Hans Kung:

Re: Hans Kung and Karl-Josef Kuschel (eds.), A GLOBAL ETHIC: The Declaration of the Parliament of the World’s Religions, New York: Continuum, 1993.

I recently read your book and was glad to see its emphasis on non-violence, the Golden Rule, and the “fundamental demand [that] every human being must be treated humanely.” [p. 21] This includes the prohibitions that a person should not kill or steal. “Or in positive terms: Have respect for life!” [p. 25]

The purpose of this letter is to ask: How do you reconcile the directives of the Global Ethic with the institution of government, which relies on or resorts to force to collect its taxes?

As you realize all governments, whether democratic or totalitarian, collect at least part of their revenues coercively. Taxes are collected under the threat of the citizen going to jail, having his property confiscated, or both, if he or she does not pay the government the amount it claims is owed.

I hope that we both would agree that a robber is violating the global ethic when he steals from or kills a person in order to take their property. The purpose for which he intends to use the stolen property in no way affects how we judge the violence. It matters not whether he intends to use the stolen property for charitable purposes or for his personal use. Killing and/or stealing are wrong.

Question 1: Are not the actions of agents of the government violent in the same manner as that of the robber?

Question 2: Is not the Golden Rule applicable to this situation? Would not the agents of government prefer not to be robbed or killed themselves?

Question 3: Are not the agents of the government acting violently when they threaten and/or coerce the reluctant citizen? Are they not acting inhumanely toward the citizens?

Question 4: Is there not a humane way to collect money for the government? Is it not possible to remonstrate peacefully with the refuseniks: to explain to them the importance of paying taxes? Is it not possible to cut off some or all government services to those who will not pay their taxes? And in the very worst case, that they still insist on not paying, is it not possible that those who do see the importance of funding governments, dig deeper into their own pockets to make up the difference?

Question 5: Is there any possible justification for stealing, killing, or treating citizens inhumanely who refuse to pay their tax?

Question 6: Does not the government’s resort to violence in collecting taxes set a bad example, which some individuals in society might think is right to follow?

I have addressed these questions to family, friends, religious leaders, and have found that they generally apply a double standard to the actions of government agents despite the fact that the “Four irrevocable directives” of the Global Ethic apply to everyone equally. As Richard Maybury, in his book, WHATEVER HAPPENED TO JUSTICE?, explains: “This is what is meant by those five words in the (United States) Declaration of Independence ‘all men are created equal.’ No one gets any special privileges or exemptions from (these directives).” [p. 22] As you wrote in A GLOBAL ETHIC, “No one,” whether a citizen or government agent, “has the right” to “physically … injure, much less kill, any other human being.” [p. 25]

I wonder if you or one of your colleagues at the Global Ethic Foundation could discuss these questions relating to the conduct of government and its agents.

Sincerely,

Carl Watner

Box 275

Gramling, South Carolina 29348

U.S.A.

(email: “editor” “at” this site)

R. C. Hoiles Revisited


By Carl Watner

[Editor’s Note: Raymond Cyrus (R. C.) Hoiles (1878-1970) was the founder of the Freedom Chain of newspapers. For more than 35 years, in conversations, columns, and editorials, he stated his belief that human beings can enjoy happier and more prosperous lives where force and threats of force are absent from human relations. Although he started out as a supporter of limited government, he evolved into an able exponent of voluntaryism. One of his pet themes was the separation of State and education. For many years, he had a standing offer of $ 500 for any school superintendent in areas where his papers were published. He challenged public school officials to explain to him how State schools accorded with the Golden Rule. He was never seriously taken up on his offer. Hoiles also opposed the internment of Japanese-American citizens during World War II. He began as a printer’s devil and operated 20 newspapers by the time he died. He presented a rare mixture of worldly practicality and principle, which marked him as a philosophical businessman. “A man should be free to make his own decisions,” he used to say, “and to learn from his mistakes and to profit when his choice was wise and correct.” The following was reprinted from an unsigned editorial in the Colorado Springs GAZETTE-TELEGRAPH, July 11, 1972, p. 6-A, and is offered to our readers in the spirit of recognizing one of the unsung heroes of the 20th Century libertarian movement. For further information see an article by R. C. in THE VOLUNTARYIST, Whole No. 17 (“Unlimited Voluntary Exchanges,”) and “To Thine Own Self Be True: The Story of Raymond Cyrus Hoiles and his Freedom Newspapers,” in Whole No. 18.]

Since the death of R. C. Hoiles (head of the Freedom Newspapers group), we have encountered a surprising number of individuals who have volunteered such remarks as, “Well, I used to think Hoiles was all wrong with the trend of events, I’ve about changed my mind;” “Hoiles was much closer to reality than many folks gave him credit. Some of his positions evoked emotional antagonism but the passing of time is proving him more and more correct;” “By God, he saw it coming. With government taxes consuming close to half of everything produced, who can argue with his warning?”

It would have been out of character for R. C. (as associates and friends called him), to have said, “I told you so,” for his motive was never to be proven correct, but rather to stimulate people to see for themselves the consequences of ever-expanding government.

One can go back to the days when he authored a signed column, from about 1935 until the 1950’s, and find repeated warnings about the approaching leviathan state. Even prior to World War II, he continually explained the dangers of government deficits, pointing out that the inevitable result would be expanding credit to finance the deficits with resulting inflation. As more and more the federal government incurred deficits and financed itself by, in effect, repudiating its debt with inflation, R. C. warned that this “painless” sleight-of-hand, continued indefinitely, would give birth to a monster that could collapse the nation.

R. C.’s most controversial position related to what he thought would be the inevitable (he always thought of consequences in the long run) effect of government schooling the young. This was wildly distorted as being “against teachers” and against “people of little means” and an endless list of other emotional reactions that begged his points, which were:

1. The control of the schools would inexorably drift away from the “local control” concept to more centralized government control as the local units obtained funds from the larger government units. (As the state government offers more subsidy to the local school district, it demands more control. Then come federal funds and also the control attending such grants.) It would be illogical to conclude that once gaining this power, it would not teach that big government is the primary source of virtue and truth in order to perpetuate itself.

2. The foundation of a sound social order is rooted firmly in moral and ethical education, rather than training, and the government must by nature follow one of two courses: (a) neutrality because of differing views on what is sound moral and ethical reality; or (b) the advocating of views which are offensive to some individuals who are forced to submit their children and-or pay to support such views. This dilemma was answered largely by assuming a stance of neutrality which tends to produce children who have little or no basic philosophy of life unless obtained elsewhere. The result has been a reversal of some 2,000 years of educational philosophy which held that education was primarily for the purpose of inculcating a rational morality. Whether or not our present era is reaping the result of this could be disputed, but there are more and more people who sense something is seriously wrong with the grounding of the young.

Again, this was not meant to imply that the people – who manned the government school system – were “failing” in their job, but rather that their job just did not include and could not by its nature include this preeminent phase of a child’s rearing. The ancients well understood that the founding of a child in a sound morality is an almost full-time endeavor, with the most important place the educational process.

Further, he held it was just elementary justice that no one should be forced to support an educational system in which he did not believe, making no distinction between this and forcing people to support a religion they did not advocate.

Another position which R. C. clung to tenaciously was that it was immoral (in the sense of being out of harmony with natural order) for the government to tax some people for the benefit of other people. Call it welfare, subsidies, government sanctioned or encouraged monopolies, all these efforts were for the purpose of “robbing Peter to pay Paul.” These are distributions of wealth on an involuntary basis and create consequences that in the long run are inimical to everyone, particularly the beneficiaries of the “booty.”

R. C. ran it by thusly: if it is immoral for A and B, as individuals, to gang up on C and take his wealth by force, it is wrong for A and B to delegate to the government as their agent the right to rob C and split the loot with them. This was another way of saying what Mr. Jefferson meant when he contended “the same justice is owed from a million to one that is owed from one to a million.”

More and more we witness the government becoming, as has been said, “an illusion by which everyone endeavors to live at the expense of everybody else,” one out of six civilian employees is on the government payroll and by 1980 this ratio is supposed to drop to one in four.

Where will all this end?

One answer, possibly not far from the truth, is: “And the fall of Rome was mighty!”

But then, R. C. always held that the powers of regeneration are unbelievably great and that eventually men will understand the folly of forcing their fellow-man to labor to their advantage just because they have the political power to enforce such an action.

As R. C. would say, “It took men thousands and thousands of years to understand the folly of chattel slavery and it is going to take quite a spell to get people to understand that it is just as disastrous, in the long run, to be the slave of all-powerful government.”