Voluntaryism in the Libertarian Tradition
by Carl Watner
Voluntaryism figures prominently in the libertarian tradition in three distinct
ways. First, voluntaryism represents the final goal of all libertarians. After
all, libertarianism is the doctrine that all the affairs of people, both public
and private, should be carried out by individuals or their voluntary associations.
Secondly, voluntaryism is a realization about the nature of political society.
The voluntaryist approach rests on the crucial, theoretical insight that all tyranny
and government are grounded on general popular acceptance. The primary responsibility
for the existence and continuation of any political system rests on the majority
of the population, who willingly acquiesce in their own subjection. Thirdly, voluntaryism
represents a way of achieving significant social change without resort to politics
or violent revolution. Since voluntaryists realize that government rests on popular
consent, they conclude that the only way to abolish government power is simply
for the people at large to withdraw that consent. As a means, voluntaryism calls
for peaceful persuasion, education, civil disobedience, and non-violent resistance
to the State. To libertarians, voluntaryism thus represents a means, an end, and
an insight. Only voluntary means can be used to attain the truly voluntary society,
based on the insight that existing tyrannies depend on the voluntary submission
of the governed. The purpose of this essay is to elucidate the history, the development,
and the actual practice of these ideas within the context of the libertarian tradition.
These three aspects of voluntaryism mutually reinforce each other. The very
goal of an all-voluntary society suggests its own means. The means are the seeds
which bud into flowers and come into fruition. It is impossible to plant the
seed of coercion and reap the flower of liberty. Thus politics and government,
which libertarians view as essentially coercive processes, can never legitimately
be used to attain libertarian goals. The non-voluntaryist always proposes to
compel people to do something; usually by passing laws or electing politicians
to office. These laws and officials depend upon political action and physical
violence. Voluntaryistic means, like non-violent resistance, for example, violate
no one's rights. They only serve to nullify laws and politicians by ignoring
them. Voluntaryism does not require of people that they shall violently overthrow
their government or every use the electoral process to change it; but merely
that they shall cease to support their government, whereupon it will fall of
its own dead weight.
Etienne de la Boetie (1530-1563), the first libertarian political philosopher
in the Western world, was largely responsible for the original statement and
elaboration of the voluntaryist principle. In his Discourse On Voluntary Servitude,
probably written during the mid 1550's, la Boetie discussed one of the roost
critical problems of political philosophy; namely, the question of civil obedience.
"Why in the world do people consent to their own enslavement?", he
asked. "Why do the bulk of the people acquiesce in their own subjection?"
La Boetie answered these questions by explaining the governmental mystique created
by rulers and their intellectual apologists. By relying on custom, by providing
bread and circuses to the citizenry, and by creating a vast network of governmental
supporters dependent on political plunder, governments were able to engineer
and sustain their own popular acceptance among the populace.
La Boetie's voluntaryist insight, that consent is brought about largely by
government propaganda, speaks sharply to the problem of strategy. It leads directly
to the conclusion that mass civil disobedience and mass non-violent resistance
are the only true methods for overthrowing tyranny. Realizing the great value
of natural liberty, la Boetie called for a thorough process of educating the
public to the truth, a process which would give back to the people a knowledge
of the blessings of liberty and a knowledge of the myths and illusions fostered
by the State. The primary task of opponents of tyranny is an educational one;
to alert the public to their despotic condition, to demystify and desanctify
the entire State apparatus. La Boetie was thus the first political philosopher
to move from an emphasis on the importance of consent to the strategic importance
of toppling tyranny by leading the public to withdraw their consent.
The value of la Boetie's insights were somewhat lost to the 16th and 17th Century
English, yet voluntaryism played a significant part in the struggle between
Church and State during these centuries. During the mid-17th Century, the English
Independents were moving towards a completely voluntaryistic conception of the
Church. They considered that maintenance of churches by tithes and State support
ought to be done away with. This was no new idea and for a long period there
had been Independents who realized that this was the logical outcome of their
views of separation of Church and State. For example, a petition circulated
in London in 1647, demanded that "tithes and all other enforced maintenance
may be forever abolished, and nothing in the place thereof imposed; but that
all ministers be paid only by those who voluntarily chose them and contract
with them for their labors." By substituting 'taxes' for 'tithes' and 'governmental
officials' for ministers', we realize how close these early religious dissenters
were to espousing the ideas of a truly voluntary State. The early advocates
of church-state separation were in the vanguard of the libertarian tradition
because they took one of the first steps necessary to separate the State from
all the rest of society.
In these religious controversies, the term 'voluntaryism' was representative
of those who advocated complete separation of Church and State. The term itself
came into common usage during the extensive disputes between the Churchmen and
dissenters in Scotland during the second decade of the 19th Century. It was
then picked up by the English non-conformists during the 1830's, and applied
to their agitation to keep the English government out of the educational process.
The 'voluntary educationists' saw a religious threat in State controlled education
and many believed that the law of supply and demand, or the voluntary principle,
as they termed it, would provide for the education of the whole English people.
Auberon Herbert attempted to repopularize the term during the 1880's and the
1890's in his voluntaryist journal, Free Life. William Godwin, author of an
Enquiry Concerning Political Justice in 1793, offers a good example of voluntaryistic
thinking in late 18th Century England. It is interesting to note that revolutionary
violence never became a serious threat to England because of the Influence of
the religious non-conformist teachings among the working classes. Godwin, among
other extreme political thinkers of that era, believed that physical force was
too uncertain in its results and that peaceful resistance was more desirable
and effective. Godwin argued for reasonable discussion and disciplined non-cooperation
as the means of fighting against authority. In Political Justice (Book II, Chap.
III, and Book IV, Chap. 1) he urged that "all government is founded in
opinion. Men at present live under any particular form, because they conceive
it their interest to do so. ... Destroy this opinion, and the fabric which is
built upon it falls to the ground." "Make men wise and by that very
operation you make them free. Civil liberty follows as a consequence of this;
no usurped power can stand against the artillery of opinion."
Godwin, in one important particular, was at variance with the main tradition
of dissent in the 18th Century. A large body of dissenters thought in terms
of politics; they tended to see problems as political and to seek political
solutions. They favored associations and the normal methods of bringing political
pressure to bear; they looked to legislative action for a solution of problems.
Godwin, on the other hand, looked only to the reformation of the individual,
objected to political parties, and had no faith in political solutions of what
were for him simply moral problems. The voluntaryistic dissenters believed that
moral agitation was always more effective and more proper than political activity.
The 19th Century abolitionists both in England and the United States, struggling
to abolish slavery and the slave trade, were faced with similar problems. Was
slave-holding to be abolished by moral suasion or political means? Should abolitionists
participate in party politics or should they hold aloof from such controversies?
Should they create their own third party organizations to propagate the abolition
of slavery? The radical abolitionists were on the cutting edge of the libertarian
movement because they viewed slavery as the worst form of stealing. Slavery
was called 'man-stealing' because it reflected the theft of a person's self-ownership
rights. The problems faced by the 19th Century abolitionists, both in terms
of goals and strategy, have much to say about the place of voluntaryism in the
libertarian movement today.
William Lloyd Garrison led one wing of the abolitionist movement, and it is
his views which we shall first examine. By the mid 1840's, Garrison and his
chief lieutenants, Wendell Phillips and Henry Clarke Wright, had come to the
conclusion that all office-holding and voting was wrong and morally reprehensible.
These men arrived at their views in two different ways. During the 1830's, Garrison
had addressed himself to the issues of perfectionism and non-resistance. He
and his fellow non-resistants rejected not only war, but the entire apparatus
that sustained government in power. He summarized their position in the 1838
Declaration of Sentiments adopted by the Peace Convention held in Boston that
year. Non-resistants renounced all allegiance to human governments and disabled
themselves from holding any political office. This carried with it a rejection
of voting. "If we cannot occupy a seat in the legislature or on the bench,
neither can we elect others to act as our substitutes in any such capacity."
In 1841, Garrison and his followers underwent a further transformation, which
led to a reinforcement of their beliefs against political action. The Liberty
Party, which had been purposely formed as an anti-slavery party in 1840, appalled
Garrison, both as a matter of theory and tactics. He claimed that an anti-slavery
third party would split the movement and dilute anti-slavery principles by dragging
them into the political gutter. Nearly at the same time, the Garrisonians came
to the realization that the Constitution was actually a pro-slavery document
and that disunion should be the rule of the day. They came to see the Constitution
as "a covenant with death and an agreement with hell" and therefore
advocated personal disallegiance from the federal government and sectional disunion
from the South.
This outlook on the Constitution was only developed after the Garrisonians
had been preaching their non-resistance and no-voting theories for a number
of years. Since Garrison took all of these demands seriously, he came to condemn
voting not only for all non-resistants but for all enfranchised citizens. He
took the ground that to vote for any public officer, local, state, or federal,
would be to endorse someone who would have to take an oath to uphold the United
States Constitution which supported slavery. Any act of allegiance to a government
whose constitution supported slavery "means either to undertake to execute
the law which I think wrong or to appoint another to do so" for me.
The Garrisonian ideas were propagated in many forums. Garrison himself engaged
in a debate with James Birney, soon to be head of the Liberty Party, in the
late 1830's. In this "Letter on the Political Obligations of Abolitionists",
Garrison maintained that the political reformation which would bring about the
abolition of slavery "is to be expected solely by a change in the moral
vision of the people; - not by attempting to prove that it is the duty of every
abolitionist to be a voter, but that it is the duty of every voter to be an
abolitionist." It was, in his opinion, the general object of the antislavery
movement to so "affect public sentiment ...and alter the views and feelings
of the people in regard to the crime of slave holding, that all classes of society...
may be induced to rally together en masse for the entire abolition of slavery."
Garrison's field was not the field of political action but that of moral suasion.
In seeking to reform public sentiment that lay behind laws and constitutions,
Garrison was striking at the heart of the problem.
Both of Garrison's chief helpers, Phillips and Wright, independently expressed
their anti-political views. Phillips wrote of his "No-Voting Theory"
in the Liberator during the 1844 and then further clarified his views in his
1845 pamphlet, "Can Abolitionists Vote or Take Office under the United
States Constitution?" Henry Clarke Wright had earlier formulated his views
in his 1841 booklet on "Ballot Box and Battle Field". Wright maintained
the non-resistant position, claiming that the ballot box was at most only a
make-shift substitute for the violence of bullets on the battle field. According
to his lights, no man could honestly accept the office of voter and then vote
against the existence of government. "May a man consent to be invested
with power to do an evil and swear to do it, even for the purpose of abolishing
that evil?", he asked. Wright claimed that a man may never rightfully consent
to do what he thinks wrong. He who would do it proves himself dishonest. "He
consents to be vested with power to do what he acknowledges to be wrong, and
swears to do it, and then gravely assures us that he never intended to do it.
Such a man is unworthy of any trust." Thus Wright concluded the fact that
any man, knowing the nature and duties of a Congressman or President, "will
consent to hold these offices, is of itself sufficient evidence that he is not
a true and good man." Wright summarized his argument by stating that he
would not vote, even if by his one vote he could free all the slaves.
Wendell Phillips in his consideration of the question: can abolitionists vote
or take office under the Constitution? came to a very simple conclusion; namely,
that they could not. The position of non-voter,and conscientious objector to
the government was to be jealously guarded. In a land where the ballot is idolized,
the non-voter "kindles in every beholder's bosom something of the warm
sympathy which waits on the persecuted, carries with it all the weight of a
disinterested testimony to truth and pricks each voter's conscience with an
uneasy doubt, whether after all voting is right. There is constantly a Mordecai
in the gate." Phillips sustained his claim that "it is by no means
necessary that every man should actually vote, in order to influence his times,"
by citing the historical examples of conscientious objectors who wielded a moral
influence widely disproportionate to their numbers.
Other wings of the radical abolitionist movement supported the no-voting stance
taken by the Garrisonians. Nathaniel Peabody Rogers, long-time editor of the
New Hampshire Anti-Slavery Society journal, Herald of Freedom, noted that men
in this country have been brought up to believe that nothing can be accomplished
except by political methods. "They cannot understand how any sane mind
can discern any other way to any end." The only object of party politics,
for Rogers, was Power. "To get it or preserve it is the only possible motive."
Rogers realized that the vote which a man casts is but a very insignificant
emblem of his political power. "The influence which goes out from every
man, whether for good or evil, can be but very imperfectly measured by the standard
of a ballot. What he seems to lose by the withdrawal of his single vote, is
gained 100 fold in the increased force which is given to the testimony of the
lips and of the life by that disinterested act. ... We only know that we are
following the dictates of plain, practical common sense, in refusing to commit
what we see to be a crime, in order to extirpate another crime. We will not
consent to obtain power by false pretenses, even for the purpose of abolishing
slavery." Rogers realized the futility of gaining power temporarily; for
what can be voted up today, may be voted down tomorrow.
Lysander Spooner was another radical abolitionist who totally rejected voting
and political party activity. Prior to the Civil War, Spooner had been asked
to lend his support to the Liberty Party. He refused in no uncertain terms in
his letter of March 12, 1856:
I feel at liberty standing outside of the constitution and knowing that government
of some kind will be carried on in the name of the constitution - to interpret
the constitution, on those points wherein it is right, and then appeal to those,
who professed to be governed by it, to act up to their own standard. I do this
on the same principle that, standing outside the Mohammedan religion, I should
feel at liberty to interpret the Koran, and appeal to believers to act up to
their own creed, wherein it was right. It is on this ground that I write about
the constitution, and not because I ever intend to take any part, directly or
indirectly, in administering it. I think no robbery is more flagrant or palpable
- nor hardly any more unjustifiable - than taxing men for the support of government,
without their personal consent. ... Such taxation is not only robbery in itself,
but it supplies the means for, and is the legitimate parent of, nearly all the
other tyranny, which governments practice. You will see therefore that it is
impossible for me to support any government that acts on that principle, or
to act with any party that adopts it.
Spooner echoed Henry Clarke Wright's analysis of voting and consent. Wright
wrote that "when a man consents to receive and exercise the right of suffrage
... he consents that a majority shall rule and pledges himself to aid in executing
the will of the majority. Whether he votes with the majority or not, by consenting
to vote at all, he becomes responsible for whatever it does." Spooner wrote,
"I would advocate natural law and constitutional law, wherever I could
get an audience to listen; because all men in office and out of office are bound
by them without regard to minorities or majorities among the people. But I do
not rely upon 'political machinery' (although it may or may not do good, according
as its objects are, or are not legal and constitutional) - but I do not rely
upon it as such - because the principle of it is wrong. For it admits (and this
is my objection to it) that even under a constitution, the law depends upon
the will of majorities, for the time being, as indicated by the acts of the
legislature. It admits the right of majorities - even under a constitution which
purports to fix men's rights - to make and unmake laws at pleasure - or at least
with very little limitation."
After the Civil War, Spooner wrote in his No Treason pamphlets that voting
and tax-paying were not legal evidence of assent to the Constitution. Both were
done under duress and were, in effect, acts of self-defense. Spooner never maintained
that people should vote or that voting was proper. Rather he argued, that when
and if people vote, their actions were not to be interpreted as unquestioning
obedience to the Constitution. Spooner eventually concluded that no one should
have the right to vote or make laws. "No human being, nor any number of
human beings, have any right to make laws, and compel other human beings to
obey them. To say that they have is to say that they are masters and owners
of those whom they require obedience." In the final analysis, Spooner rejected
the Constitution and politics entirely: "This much is certain - the Constitution
either authorized such a government as we have had, or has been powerless to
prevent it. In either case, it is unfit to exist."
Henry David Thoreau, the famous civil resistant, was most sympathetic to the
abolitionist cause. Thoreau was influenced by his friendship with Ralph Waldo
Emerson, who in turn was an admirer of William Lloyd Garrison. All three shared
in common the idea of individual conscience standing in opposition to the State.
The core of Thoreau's argument is that men become machines when they obey orders
without thinking or when they give the government authority to speak or act
on their behalf. "Must the citizen ... resign his conscience to the legislator?",
Thoreau asked. "Why has every man a conscience, then? I think that we should
be men first. ... It is not desirable to cultivate a respect for the law, so
much as for the right. ... Law never made a man a whit more just; and, by means
of their respect for it, even the well-disposed are daily made the agents of
injustice." Thoreau was speaking out against slavery as well as against
the American invasion of Mexico, which took place in 1846.
Thoreau was particularly out-spoken against voting. He saw voting as a sort
of gaming. "The character of the voters is not staked. ... Even voting
for the right is doing nothing for it. ... A wise man will not leave the right
to the mercy of chance, nor wish it to prevail through the power of the majority.
There is but little virtue in the action of masses of men." Thoreau recognized
the importance of civil disobedience, both as an individual moral statement
and tactical position. Referring to his own short imprisonment and his influence,
Thoreau wrote: "If any think that their influence would be lost [in prison],
and their voices no longer afflict the ear of the State, ...they do not know
how much truth is stronger than error, nor how much more eloquently and effectively
he can combat injustice who has experienced a little in his own person."
Adopting la Boetie's strategic outlook, he then wrote:
"Cast your whole vote, not a strip of paper merely, but your influence.
A minority is powerless while it conforms to the majority; it is not even a
minority then; but it is irrestible when it clogs by its whole weight. ... If
a thousand men were not to pay their tax-bills this year, that would not be
a violent and bloody measure, as it would be to pay them, and enable the State
to commit violence and shed innocent blood. This is, in fact, the definition
of a peaceable revolution, if any such is possible. If the taxgatherer, or any
other public of ficer, asks me, as one has done, 'But what shall I do?' my answer
is, 'If you really wish to do anything, resign your office. 'When the subject
has refused allegiance, and the officer has resigned his office, then the revolution
is accomplished."
Thus concludes our brief survey of voluntaryism in the libertarian tradition.
Voluntaryism in the hands of 20th Century libertarians has a revolutionary potential
that has not been adequately recognized. If we wish to remain true to our libertarian
heritage, it is clear that voluntaryism as a means, an end, and an insight,
deserves our support at this time.
Short Bibliography
- Etienne de la Boetie, The Politics of Obedience: The Discourse of Voluntary
Servitude, Introduction by Murray N. Rothbard, Translated by Harry Kurz, New
York: Free Life Editions, 1975.
- Chambers's Encyclopedia, "Voluntaryism", Vol. X, p. 23, Philadelphia:
J.B. Lippincott & Co.,1882.
- William Godwin, Enquiry Concerning Political Justice And Its Influence on Morals
And Happiness, Critical Introduction by F.E.L. Priestley, Toronto: University
of Toronto Press, 1946.
- Lewis Perry, Radical Abolitionism: Anarchy And The Government Of God In Anti-Stavery
Thought, Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1973. See esp. pp.198-205 on Spooner.
Nathaniel Peabody Rogers, A Collection From The Miscellaneous Writings Of Nathaniel
Peabody Rogers, Boston: Benjamin B. Mussey, 1849.
- Lysander Spooner, The Collected Works Of Lysander Spooner, Introductions by
Charles Shively, Weston, Mass.: M & S Press, 1971.
- Henry David Thoreau, Walden And On The Duty Of Civil Disobedience with an Afterward
by Perry Miller, New York:The American Library, 1960.
- William Wiecek, The Sources Of Anti-Stavery Constitutionalism In America, 1760-1848,
Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1977. See esp. Chap. 10 on "The Garrisonian
Critique".
- eorge Woodcock, Civil Disobedience, Toronto: Canadian Broadcasting Corp., 1966,
Esp. good on Thoreau, Gandhi, and the "Tradition of English Dissent".