"Beyond the Wit of Man to Foresee": Voluntaryism and Land Use Controls
by Carl Watner
Number 80 - June 1996
Introduction
The impetus for the research behind this article was a Spartanburg, S.C. HERALD-JOURNAL
editorial of June 25, 1995 (p. A15) headlined "Zoning isn't a loss of rights:
zoning is a protection rather than an elimination of property rights." In
"double-think" language right out of 1984, the writer justified zoning
controls because "zoning prevents surprises." According to the editorial,
without zoning there is nothing to prevent the value of one's property from being
diminished when a neighboring property is suddenly developed as a junkyard or
landfill. The author of this piece hadn't realized that there are ways of avoiding
land use surprises on the free market, such as deed restrictions, privately planned
developments, and purchase of buffers and development rights. Furthermore, the
writer didn't understand that in a free market, it is not monetary values that
are guaranteed, but rather the right to use one's property peacefully. The value
of your property is a function of what other's will pay for it. No political
statute can change the law of supply and demand.
As I began reading about the history of land use controls in the United States,
I discovered that one of the justifications behind early 20th Century zoning
laws was that "zoning protected property rights." New York City's Fifth
Avenue merchants wanted to be protected from the invasion of the garment industry,
and San Francisco businessmen wanted to be insulated from the spread of Chinese
laundries throughout their city. Probably few, if any, of the early supporters
of zoning understood that zoning was actually a violation of property rights:
that political controls over private land use constituted a gross violation of
the free market concept. Researching the topic further, the same conclusion was
constantly buttressed: total private property rights have never existed in this
country. There have always been political controls on the use of one's land and
property. These laws have always gone beyond the common law rule which recognized
that one should not use one's own property in a manner to physically invade another's
property. These political controls have included nuisance and public health laws,
taxes on the value of real property, and the legitimization of property confiscation
for "public use" via the Fifth Amendment. In short, government "protection"
of property rights is one of those political myths which the government uses
quite effectively to legitimize its conquest over us. Governments and property
rights are like oil and water; they don't mix. Despite all the propaganda and
rhetoric to the contrary, governments can only negate property rights, not protect
them.
Up to this point, my research had been primarily negative, focusing on the
statist aspects of zoning. Voluntaryism, however, is a philosophy of living peacefully
with others; the advocacy that all human affairs should be by mutual consent.
In the absence of a coercive government, how would the problems addressed by
nuisance and zoning laws be handled on the free market? Were there good historical
examples of common law rules which provided the basis for peaceful land use and
development, without neighboring property owners feuding with one another? Yes
there were, and prime examples of voluntaryist land use controls were found in
such private developments as Levittown, N.J., Reston, Virginia, and Columbia,
Maryland (developed by The Rouse Company). In Columbia during the early 1960s,
The Rouse Company bought over 15,000 acres of land between Baltimore and Washington.
This was done without the use of eminent domain or resort to condemnation proceedings.
Nevertheless, there were five "holdouts," property owners who would
not sell. Imagine what would have happened to these property owners if The Rouse
Company had been a government entity. Despite these objectors, Columbia became
one of the largest and finest private communities in the world. Everything proceeded
on the basis of mutual consent. Rouse purchased the land from willing sellers,
placed deed restrictions upon its future use, and then resold the land to willing
buyers. In short, I discovered that there were various ways that private communities
have provided "public goods" without interference by coercive governments.
Thus, the purpose of this paper is not only to explicate the negative history
of political zoning, but to shed light on the positive, voluntaryist approach
to private land use controls.
Zoning: A Police Power
There are basically four ways that governments exercise power and control over
"privately owned" land. Zoning is a subcategory of one of them. The
four methods are: 1) the power of eminent domain (the power of the government
to take title to private property by paying a compensation of its own determination);
2) regulation of land use via zoning and nuisance laws which are derived from
the state's police power to protect the public; 3) taxation of land; and 4) government
expenditures on infrastructure - such as its provision of water, sewerage, and
highway systems. Although the last two modes of government operation are as pervasive
(and pernicious) as the first two, they are not a matter of concern in this article.
What distinguishes the power of eminent domain from the power of regulation
is whether or not government takes title to the land in question. When eminent
domain is exercised, the private land owner is dispossessed of the title to the
land and is offered some monetary compensation. When a government agency builds
an airport runway, it will condemn, and must pay for, the land upon which the
runway is situated. Owners of land near the airport will be prevented from building
high-rises on their land so that airplanes may approach the runway. Both the
original owner of the condemned land and the adjacent property owners lose property
rights. In the former case, the original owner loses all right and title to the
property in return for whatever compensation the government awards; in the latter,
the owner retains title. The portion of his building rights that have been forfeit
is not a compensable loss.
Since the power of eminent domain has been discussed in an earlier issue of
The Voluntaryist (see Whole No. 32, "Property Rights or
Eminent Domain?") no extended discussion is necessary here. However, a few
additional comments about the contradictory nature of government in the United
States are in order. In contrast to most of the constitutions of the fifty states,
there is no explicit grant of the power of eminent domain in the United States
Constitution. Nevertheless, the courts have always viewed its exercise as an
inherent attribute of the federal government's sovereignty. Thus the Fifth Amendment
to the Constitution legitimizes the exercise of a power which is not even mentioned
in the document it amends. To claim, as the Fifth Amendment does, that private
property shall not be taken for public use without just compensation, means that
property rights are not absolute and that the government may take property from
an owner without his or her consent. The fact that compensation is to be offered
is beside the point. (How can the compensation be termed "just" if
the original owner does not want to sell?) Any time that the power of eminent
domain is exercised, a theft has occurred. The government has stolen land from
a person unwilling to sell.
The constitutions of the fifty states are also the basis for the exercise of
each state's police power, and all "private" property in the United
States is held subject to the police power. The police power refers to government
actions for "the promotion and maintenance of the health, safety, morals,
and general welfare of the public. It is grounded in the belief that an overriding
public interest of general, widespread benefit asserts a superior claim over
private property. Zoning is a perfect example of this principle. When the police
power is applied to all citizens and landowners in like manner for broad public
benefit, no monetary compensation is due those whose property is 'used' or taken."
(For example, the police power is the basis for state seizure and slaughter of
diseased animals, and the seizure and destruction of buildings in order to put
out large fires.) Since the federal and state courts have consistently upheld
zoning as a proper extension of the police power, they have also determined that
governments need not be responsible for changes in the value of property due
to zoning laws. In other words, the loss of potential market value caused by
zoning classifications, does not impair the validity of zoning legislation or
impose any obligation upon the legislature to compensate the land owner. Supreme
Court Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes summed up the statist view of the police
power in two different cases. In 1922, in the Pennsylvania Coal Case he wrote
that, "Government could hardly go on if, to some extent values incident
to property could not be diminished without paying for every change [caused by]
the general law" (269 US 393 at 413). Six years later he wrote: "Property
must not be taken without compensation, but with the help of a [legal] phrase
(the police power) some property may be taken or destroyed for public use without
paying for it, if you do not take too much" (277 US 189 at 209).
Zoning may be defined as the method by which the legislature of a political
jurisdiction exercises control over land by dividing or classifying it into certain
areas and then subjecting it to particular planning restrictions. Zoning laws
now control such matters as how the land may be used (residential, commercial,
agricultural, etc.), the type of buildings that may be erected, the size of lots,
the width of streets, the height of buildings, and setback requirements (minimum
distance of buildings from property lines). In some municipalities there is still
no formal zoning, even today. Nevertheless, in a city like Houston, Texas, where
this is the case, there are subdivision controls, a minimum housing ordinance,
a building code, and seventeen separate land-use ordinances covering things such
as trailer parks, rendering plants, and commercial landscaping. In other areas
without zoning, there are performance standards. For example, if you have a junkyard
on your land, the local government requires you to screen it off from public
view. In most cases, even if there is no zoning, these government regulations
amount to the same thing: government control over privately owned resources.
In other countries, this is something we call fascism. In short, zoning "permits"
the owner to retain title to his land, while dictating the owner's "right"
to do certain things if he wishes to develop or use the land.
In areas where zoning only permits one use, government policy effectively dictates
how the land may be used, if the land owner is to develop the property. The free
market way of accomplishing this would be for neighbors and/or adjacent land
owners to negotiate a private covenant under which the property owner in question
would agree to forego certain future usages or to restrict the property to a
specific use in the future. The difference between this free market approach
and that of legislative zoning is that on the free market a person's neighbors
would not be able to force the owner to make such promises. Under zoning legislation
they do; the majority uses the police power to impose their view of development
on the neighborhood. If a landowner uses his land in a manner not consistent
with the law, he will either be fined, jailed for contempt (until such time as
the landowner agrees to cease and desist the illegal usage), or the land itself
will be seized and confiscated by the public authorities in their efforts to
end the illegal use. Ultimately, the police power means the courts will uphold
the right of the police to kill a person who refuses to abide by the will of
the legislature .
Nuisance Law versus Zoning
The Latin legal maxim, 'Sic utere tuo ut alienum non laedas', epitomizes the
common law approach to land use controls: "Use your own thing so as to not
harm that of another." At English common law, the basic limitations on the
use of property were incorporated in the law of nuisance, the action that a landowner
could bring if his right to the use of his land was being interfered with. Thus
the common law of nuisance was used to resolve land use disputes. At common law,
a nuisance was defined as "the substantial interference with the plaintiff's
use of his land by the unreasonable conduct of the defendant." Nuisances
extended to "everything that endangered life or health, gave offense to
the senses, violated the laws of decency, or obstructed the reasonable and comfortable
use of property." The general principle (based upon the idea of homesteading,
or "a prescriptive easement," as the common law terms it) was that
land use prior in time would prevail over latter ones. For example, if neighbors
of a landfill found its operation offensive, they would only be able to prevail
against it as a nuisance, if their housing development predated the development
of the landfill. If the landfill was in operation before their homes were built,
its operation would not be prohibited or be deemed a nuisance. Thus, noise, smoke,
and offensive odors are not necessarily, in and of themselves, nuisances. Under
certain circumstances, one may have an affirmative easement to maintain a nuisance
on one's own land (either by "grant, implication, or prescription").
During the late 19th Century, the State and its judicial courts took over the
law of private nuisance and created a new concept of "public nuisance."
This became the bridge that linked the law of private nuisance to the 20th Century
law of zoning. In bringing a suit of private nuisance, one or more affected landowners
are generally the plaintiffs. In a public nuisance suit, a public officer (zoning
or health official) brings suit to abate a nuisance that affects a large number
of people. A public nuisance is further removed from that of private nuisance
when legislative bodies declare certain kinds of land use to be a public nuisance,
even though there are no harmful consequences traditionally regarded as a nuisance.
An example of this might be the operation of a hair salon in one's home, thus
violating a law which prohibits businesses in a residential district.
The key regulatory device for the enforcement of zoning regulations is the
requirement that all new construction or new land uses (and even substantial
rehabilitation of existing structures) may not be undertaken until official authorization
is given. Zoning or building permits must be obtained before anything is done
on the land. Failure to obtain a permit, or failure to comply with the zoning
or building codes automatically makes the property a public nuisance. Building
codes include regulations regarding the types of materials used in construction,
fire safety, and the use of gas, water, and electricity within the building.
In addition, housing codes often exist, and are frequently made retroactive.
Such codes set out minimum requirements for any buildings in which human beings
reside, whether or not newly constructed. Although it may not happen often, people
have been evicted from their habitations for failure to meet the specifications
of a housing code. At other times, buildings have been torn down by the political
authorities because their owners would not obtain building permits or bring their
buildings into compliance with the building code. Zoning codes may be applied
retroactively, so as to outlaw preexisting, nonconforming uses. The police power
of the state, exercised under the guise of zoning, building, and housing codes,
is one of the most coercive elements of political government.
A Very Brief History of Zoning
The record of land use controls in the Anglo-American legal system is one of
the triumph of the State over private property. The English Parliament, as early
as 1588, and again in 1592, passed national land use legislation regarding the
size and location of housing. In 1606, in "The Case of the King's Prerogative
in Saltpetre," it was decided that a private landowner was obligated to
build military fortifications and trenches upon his own land, at his own expense.
The "King's prerogative" or "police power" mandated that
his efforts were noncompensable since they were in the "public interest"
and for "the general welfare."
In the American colonies, a similar ideology prevailed. Colonial land controls
took various forms, from the requirements that the colonists construct fences
and plant shade trees, to the restrictions in Boston in 1692 that certain industrial
uses be confined to particular areas of the city. New York City in the same period
approved legislation prohibiting animal slaughterhouses altogether. Government
controls existed throughout the 1700s, but came into their own during the 19th
Century. In 1811, the New York City Commissioner's Land Plan compulsorily divided
the city into lots 25' x 100'. In 1826, New York City authorities prohibited
a church from using its burial ground. "The church sued; and the court,
citing protection of community health, upheld the law." During the 1860s,
tenement housing reform originated in New York City, where the first regulations
outlawing public privies and prohibiting basement occupancy were passed in 1867.
A city law of Modesto, California in 1885 was probably the first modern zoning
ordinance in this country. It prohibited the establishment of public laundries
or wash houses in certain parts of the city. A similar situation existed in San
Francisco, where city authorities objected to the lack of drainage, and the nuisance
resulting from the laundry water being turned onto city streets. There, laundries
were prohibited, too, unless licensed by the city. On December 28,1885, a Chinese
laundryman, Yick Wo, was arrested and prosecuted for operating an unlicensed
laundry. The case was appealed to the Supreme Court of California, where his
conviction was upheld. Other California litigation, as well as cases decided
by the United States Supreme Court, "established the right of municipal
authorities to restrict practically any kind of business, the operation of which
might be a menace," or a threat to public safety, sanitation, or morals
within city boundaries. Under this reasoning, the operation of livery stables
was restricted in St. Louis in 1893.
By the beginning of the 20th Century, the agitation for more comprehensive
land use controls began. In 1904, Baltimore City passed an ordinance limiting
the height of city buildings. Similar laws were passed in Indianapolis, New York,
and Boston, where height districts were created that covered the entire city.
The most fully zoned city of the time was Los Angeles, where district zoning
went into effect in 1909. This legislation, upheld by the state courts in 1911,
"established the right of the city to regulate any lawful business, by holding
that the power to regulate the carrying on of certain lawful occupations in a
city includes the power to confine their operation to certain limits, whenever
such restrictions may reasonably be found to protect the public health, morals,
safety, and comfort." The Los Angeles law also included a retroactive provision,
under which nonconforming uses could be terminated.
By 1913, homeowners and real estate men in Wisconsin, Minnesota, and Illinois
had lobbied their respective state legislatures to empower cities of certain
size to "establish residential districts from which manufacturing and commercial
establishments would be banned." In New York, the cities of Syracuse and
Utica legislated "residence districts" in which buildings other than
single or two-family dwellings were prohibited. In December 1913, another official
New York City document was released which supported zoning (REPORT ON THE HEIGHTS
OF BUILDINGS). In 1914, the New York State legislature amended the charter of
New York City to permit the City's Board of Estimates to zone the city. It took
two years of further agitation by the Fifth Avenue merchants before a zoning
resolution was passed on July 25, 1916. (The Fifth Avenue Association, representing
those who owned or occupied the city's most expensive retail land, "demanded
that the city protect their luxury block from encroachment by the new tall buildings
of the garment district.")
During the first two decades of the 20th Century, business and professional
groups were instrumental in bringing about local zoning ordinances. For example,
the Los Angeles Realty Board was highly supportive of the first city-wide zoning
in their city. J.C. Nichols, a nationally prominent builder and developer from
Kansas City who relied upon private deed restrictions in his residential subdivisions,
pointed out that this was not enough. He said that residential developers required
municipal assistance (in the form of zoning laws) to control unregulated development
around their privately created communities. Other architects, city planners,
engineers, and real estate men all believed in the desirability and "necessity
to bring some order out of the chaos that has resulted from the anarchistic development
of our cities." Such groups as the National Association of Real Estate Boards,
the Chamber of Commerce of the United States, the American Society of Civil Engineers,
the American Society of Landscape Architects, and the National Housing Association
all banded together to push zoning. Zoning (and building codes) not only eliminated
many of the problems traditionally associated with the operation of private deed
restrictions, but was a way of eliminating many small competitors in the land
development and building industries. These professionals and large scale developers
and builders were also joined by city politicians and bureaucrats, who expected
that their sphere of influence would be broadened under zoning regulations. Future
development could be "regulated" so that city authorities would not
be overwhelmed by the demand for municipal services. Most backers of zoning were
probably sincerely interested in promoting orderly land use and better communities,
but they also saw zoning as a tool to buttress their personal profit and power.
Court Cases on Zoning
Although the courts have occasionally challenged the application of a zoning
law to a particular piece of property, they have always upheld the exercise of
the government's police power, and have "never held against zoning in any
basic sense. This carries forward a tradition from the earlier days, both in
this country and England, in which the rule of government" prevailed over
private property rights. The authors of this statement, Linowes and Allensworth,
conclude that in Anglo-American law there is no right to use your property as
you like: "[H]ere are important constraints on the use of property that
suggest that property rights do not exist."
An early 20th Century example of this is the California case of Hadacheck v
Sebastian, which was eventually decided by the United States Supreme Court (239
US 394). In 1902, J.C. Hadacheck acquired 8 acres of land, outside the city of
Los Angeles. The land, which contained clay deposits, was devoted to the manufacture
of brick. Around 1909, after the city had annexed the land on which the brickyard
was located, a municipal ordinance was passed which limited brickmaking to certain
areas of the city. Hadacheck challenged the law, on the basis that denying him
the use of his land as a brickyard lowered the value of his real property by
several hundred thousand dollars. Both the California Supreme Court (in 1913)
and the US Supreme Court (in 1915) decided that the city had the right to prohibit
what hitherto had been a lawful use. "The police power was available to
stop nonconforming uses, to deal retroactively with uses incompatible with those
allowed by law." According to this reasoning, there is no such thing as
private property rights in the United States. At any time, the political authorities,
may, under the guise of zoning and the police power, declare a hitherto legal
use "nonconforming" and prohibit its exercise. And the prohibition
against "ex post facto" laws does not apply because most zoning enforcement
is a civil action, not a criminal one.
By the early 1920s the national zoning movement had achieved remarkable results.
In September 1921, Secretary of Commerce Herbert Hoover appointed an Advisory
Committee on Zoning. Within a year, the Department of Commerce issued a Standard
Zoning Enabling Act, which furnished state and local governments a model law
under which to empower their towns and cities to exercise the police power to
zone. By 1925, over one-quarter of the states had passed similar enabling acts.
(Zoning also received a "boost" in 1934, when the Federal Housing Administration
was created. Only builders in municipalities with zoning regulations were qualified
to receive FHA mortgage insurance.) The supporters of zoning believed that when
a test case went before the Supreme Court that the Court would be more inclined
to support zoning if it had seen widespread adoption throughout the country.
By the end of 1925, zoning had been brought before the highest judicial tribunals
in twelve states, and nine of them had upheld the police power. Only in Maryland,
New Jersey, and Missouri had zoning been declared unconstitutional.
The constitutionality of comprehensive zoning was upheld in 1926, when the
United States Supreme Court decided the case of Ambler Realty v the Village of
Euclid (272 US 365). This test case originated in Ohio, where the federal district
court judge had "held that zoning ordinances were necessarily unconstitutional
because they 'took' property without compensation." The case was a classic
one of commercial real estate being rezoned residential, with a resulting loss
of potential property value to the property owner. The Supreme Court had already
heard arguments in the case, when Alfred Bettman, a well-known national supporter
of zoning and friend of Chief Justice Taft, filed a friend of the court brief.
Bettman pointed out that the question before the court was the constitutionality
of comprehensive land use regulations, not whether the Village of Euclid had
exercised the power of eminent domain (which would require compensation). The
Euclid ordinance was "frankly and expressly an exercise of the police power."
"The community," Bettman wrote, "was not taking or destroying
any property or property rights for public use but was invoking a general power
over private property, which [was] necessary for the orderly existence of all
government."
"Bettman's brief saved the day for zoning. One justice who had previously
been persuaded that use-zoning was unconstitutional changed his mind, and on
November 22, 1926, the high court upheld this form of regulation in a momentous
four-to-three decision." Justice George Sutherland, who delivered the majority
opinion, believed that the exclusion of buildings devoted to business from residentially
zoned areas bore "a rational relation to the health and safety of the community."
The problem with this justification is that "the health and safety of the
community" is as open-ended a concept as "the general welfare."
Sutherland justified the exclusion of businesses from residential areas on the
grounds that there would be less traffic, children and pedestrians would be safer,
that there would be less disorder, and that municipal fire and police protection
would be made less difficult and less costly to provide. He also added that "the
construction and repair of streets may be rendered easier and less expensive,
by confining the greater part of the heavy traffic to streets where business
is carried on."
In 1948, the Supreme Court was called upon to adjudicate the issue of public
policy versus private covenants. It took a very statist view, upholding the right
of the government to abrogate private agreements. In Shelley v. Kraemer (334
US 1), the Court held that it would not enforce a private covenant designed to
exclude members of the Negro race from a neighborhood. Private covenants contrary
to public policy (such as nondiscrimination laws) were not illegal, but the parties
to them could not use the state's judicial system to enforce them.
Private Places and Contractual Communities
A covenant is usually a promise not to do something, and in the real estate
world a restrictive covenant usually refers to restrictions recorded in the deed
of a property. The law of equitable restrictions on land, sometimes termed easements
or servitudes, has often been used by real estate developers to assure that the
land is used according to a certain scheme. Typically such agreements might provide
for residences only, or allow houses of a specified value, certain size, or style
of architecture, or protect against the conduct of objectionable businesses,
and restrict building to a specified distance from the street and other property
lines. Some covenants "run with the land," (an old practice under the
English common law) and others are set out in the sale or purchase agreement.
One of the earliest uses of private covenants was found in St. Louis, Missouri,
where during the 1850s and 1860s, nearly one hundred subdivisions or private
places were formed within the city. "A private place could encompass one
or more streets and was governed by an elected lot association. Not only did
each private place own and maintain its streets, but in many cases it also owned
the sewers, water mains, and utility easements."
The rules for each private-place association were laid down in its "indenture,"
or restrictive covenant. Most covenants were framed by the initial subdivider
and contained house set-back requirements, restrictions against multi-family
housing, and private building codes. Covenants authorized the collection of annual
assessments to pay for the upkeep of the streets, water mains, parks, and other
common areas. If a lot owner refused to pay annual assessments, the association
had the power to place a lien on the property and sue in a court of equity. In
this respect, the private-place is similar to the modern condominium .
David Beito, author of the foregoing quote, adds "The private places carried
on functions that everywhere else have been considered essential government services."
But of course, they were not governments in the traditional sense. The rights
and powers of the homeowner's association ended at the boundary line of the subdivision.
They seldom had any control over vacant land bordering their neighborhood. In
contrast to the politically coercive methodology of zoning, the developers and
owners of private-places respected the property rights of everyone, whether they
were inside or outside the boundary of the development.
The private places of St. Louis, and other early subdivisions like Tuxedo Park,
New York (1885), Riverside, Illinois (1869), Country Club District (Kansas City,
1906), and River Oaks (Houston, 1925) were the forerunners of today's "new
towns." They paralleled the construction of new company towns, such as Gary,
Indiana (U.S. Steel, 1906), Kohler, Wisconsin (The Kohler Company, 1916), and
Chicopee, Georgia (Chicopee Manufacturing Company, 1924). In time, they have
been followed by such mammoth places as Irvine Ranch (93,000 acres in Orange
County, California developed by The Irvine Company), California City (90,000
acres in Riverside County, California developed by Kaiser-Aetna), and Valencia
(44,000 acres near Los Angeles, California built by Newhall Land and Farming
Company). The essential element that links all of these projects is their reliance
upon private enterprise. The entrepreneurs who built these places all realized
that contractual communities were the key to creating and maintaining value,
both for investors and those who chose to live in their new towns.
The Rouse Company and Columbia
Columbia, Maryland, the planned development of The Rouse Company of Baltimore,
Maryland, is one of the finest examples of a contractual community in the United
States. As of April 1995 there were nine major villages and a Town Center in
Columbia, where 81,00 people lived. "Columbia exploded three myths about
new towns." The giant developments in California had nearly all started
from farm lands owned by family or corporate interests. James Rouse proved that
it was possible to assemble enough land to start a new town. Furthermore, he
demonstrated that new towns could be financed by private enterprise. Rouse did
not resort to federal loan guarantees provided by Congress in 1966 to private
developers of new towns. Earlier developments, by contrast, like the three Levittown
locations (Long Island, NY, Bucks County, PA, and Burlington County, NJ), relied
heavily upon government mortgage money under FHA and Veteran's Authority programs.
Finally, Rouse showed that it was possible "to win zoning approval from
development-shy suburbanites."
From the very beginning of Columbia, Rouse realized that creating a private
community that would be "truly in scale with people" depended upon
the profit-motive. "Profit," said Rouse, "hauls dreams into focus
with reality. It moderates the temptation toward imposing one's bias on others.
You hav[e] to estimate at every step of the way how people are really going to
choose, not the way you want them to [choose]." Rouse was convinced that
"if you can create an environment that is good enough, people will pay for
it." He once stated that "Unless Columbia makes an outrageous profit,
it [will be] a failure." Columbia not only had to attract enough inhabitants,
who wanted to live and own there, but it had to earn "an outrageous profit,"
as Rouse termed it, to show the financial community that "new cities are
[not] a pointless risk." (Rouse proved his point. The Baltimore SUN reported
on October 10, 1995 [page 6A] that his company "has earned about $100 million
in profits on land sales, primarily in Columbia.")
The idea for a new town midway between Baltimore, Maryland and Washington,
D.C. may have occurred to Rouse during the late 1950s. Howard County, Maryland
was predominantly farming land at the time. Beginning in 1962, through exceedingly
careful control and negotiations, Rouse was able to acquire over 15,000 acres
of county real estate with sufficient contiguity to be treated as one entity.
He obtained a loan of nearly $25 million from Connecticut General Life Assurance
to pay for the 169 parcels he purchased at an average price of $1500 per acre.
Once the Howard County government granted "new town" zoning to the
project in 1965, another $50 million of long term financing was obtained from
such sources as Chase Manhattan Bank and the Teachers Insurance and Annuity Association
of America.
To attract industry and to provide jobs for the residents of Columbia, The
Rouse Company paid for a four-mile railroad spur and expanded the city beyond
its original scope. The General Electric Industrial Park was created on 2139
additional acres of farms and gravel pits, that Rouse purchased several years
after Columbia started. This land cost over $19 million, more than six times
the average price per acre Rouse had paid in late 1962 and 1963. With the addition
of the acreage for the General Electric Company, Rouse had bought a total of
17,868 acres for $44 million, at an average cost of $2485.
The Columbia Park and Recreation Association is the name of the homeowner's
association set up by The Rouse Company under the terms of its sales agreements.
The Association is a private, nonprofit corporation with a full time manager,
professionals, and grounds maintenance staff. The Columbia Association is responsible
for the community's buildings, swimming pools, lakes, pathways, parks, and landscaping.
To pay for this and other services, such as child and day care, arts and craft
classes, tennis and golf clubs, the Association is empowered by private covenant
to collect from every property owner in Columbia, an assessment of up to 75 cents
per year of $100 assessed valuation. Apartment dwellers have the Columbia Association's
levy included as part of their rent. Another arm of the Columbia Association,
and which falls under the covenants which govern the residents of Columbia, is
the Architectural Committee. This group functions as a review board and must
approve all construction plans in advance. It has the power to require changes,
or even reject building projects entirely. From a voluntaryist point of view,
the only major flaw in the planning for Columbia was that The Rouse Company did
not assume the responsibilities for certain public services within the community.
The local government of Howard County levies a property tax on homeowners in
Columbia, and maintains the streets, the roads, the schools, and provides fire
and police protection.
Unlike coercive political government, The Rouse Company could not resort to
condemnation proceedings in order to assemble and purchase the properties it
needed to form Columbia. In order to prevent land prices from rising as it bought
up more and more land, Rouse disguised its intentions by buying through many
intermediary agents. Despite the secrecy and their best efforts, the agents employed
by Rouse were not able to buy up all the properties in the proposed area. There
were five-holdouts, owning some 850 acres, who refused to sell under any conditions
or at any price. Finally by 1971, Rouse had paid $3,000 an acre for one 112 acre
holdout, which became the site of the Howard County Community College. As of
1995, one of the holdout properties was still undeveloped, and the rest had been
privately developed.
As Rouse found out, most people have a price for their land. As one of his
real estate agents put it, their "job [was] to find out what it [was] -
money, terms, a life estate. Everything can be acquired if you solve all the
difficulties." Farmers had to be satisfied that they would be able to harvest
their crops that were in the ground. "Several elderly couples insisted on
the right to live where they were until they died. One woman would agree only
to lease her land for 99 years, giving Rouse an option to buy after that."
Another farmer wanted to preserve a life estate on his property for his horse.
On one 810 acre property where a life estate had been preserved for the owner,
Rouse had not purchased the timber rights. When the elderly resident threatened
to sell his valuable stand of timber, Rouse bought the timbering rights and topsoil
for more than $40,000 and let the trees stand. All such problems were overcome
by human ingenuity and the respect for individual property rights.
Another example of a contractual community formed in the same manner as Rouse's
Columbia is Walt Disney World, an entertainment and resort complex that lies
southeast of Orlando, Florida. Disney World consists of 28,000 acres, which encompasses
a wildlife preserve of 8200 acres. "To avoid holdouts as well as to keep
the land prices in the area from escalating, Walt Disney had by 1964 acquired
the land in small parcels using various holding companies. Using middlemen, stealth,
and more than 100 dummy corporations, [Disney] went on a secret land-buying spree
near Orlando, paying about $400 an acre." One important aspect of the development
is that Disney purchased much more land than was needed for, or intended for,
Disney World. He wanted "to create a buffer zone" around the theme
park "and avoid the motels, fast-food stores and unsightly neon cacophony
that developed around Disneyland in California." By being able to control
the surrounding environment, Disney management would not only be able to guide
future development, but also assure itself of a profit as land around Disney
World increased in value. Like Rouse, Disney aimed to show "that through
free enterprise you could take virgin land and develop it without any government
subsidy."
Conclusion
As these examples of contractual community governance illustrate, there are
marketplace institutions that provide many, if not all, the normal services offered
by politically sovereign governments. Spencer MacCallum has argued that "there
are no longer any political functions being performed at the municipal level
and upward in our society that differ substantially from those that we can observe
being performed on a smaller scale entirely within the context of normal property
relations." There are two major differences between contractual communities
and the typical community political government. First, the governing body of
a contractual community (usually called a residential community association)
does not have the power to levy taxes like its political counterpart. The fees
that they charge are based on market place competition, not political whims.
Secondly, in a contractual community the relationship between the party that
owns the property and the people who live there is based upon an explicit contract
entered into by both parties. Such a contract cannot be changed unilaterally,
nor by the majority of residents. In political communities, the relationship
is non-contractual (what the government would call "constitutional")
in nature, and can be changed by the government or a majority of the voters.
The institutions of political governance reserve to themselves the right of final
constitutional interpretation and enforcement by liens, seizures, and imprisonment.
The whole point of contractual governance is to stabilize land uses and property
values to the benefit of all parties involved in owning or residing on the land.
It pursues this goal in a free market manner by linking ownership, management,
and the maintenance of property values. All the parties involved in these arrangements
are mutually satisfied or withdraw from them. "The slightest neglect of
the public interest or lapse in the form of corruption or oppression" in
the contractual community penalizes itself by a decline in rent and property
values. By contrast, zoning and political officials suffer no personal loss if
their controls don't work. In fact, they sometimes benefit from unworkable regulations,
which they themselves obviate through the receipt of payoffs, bribes, or other
forms of political intrigue and corruption.
The fact that many people do not view zoning as a destroyer of property rights
demonstrates how few people really understand the meaning of private property.
Zoning is simply stealing. Not only is its claim to promote the general welfare
bogus, but the exercise of the police power effectively negates all private property
in land in the United States. "In essence, zoning grants a cadre of public
official and favored private [interests] the free exercise of state power to
force their designs on the use of someone else's property." Zoning is "legal
mumbo jumbo for uncompensated takings under the exercise of the police power."
Furthermore, the history of zoning aptly illustrates the truth of Ludwig von
Mises' observation that one government intervention must lead to another. Early
zoning laws were not aimed at controlling undeveloped land. Later, zoning laws
were expanded to include all real property.
Contractual governance of communities, whether residential or commercial, often
goes far beyond the scope of public sector regulations. These restrictions, which
might include specifying what colors a homeowner can paint the house, do not
constitute a violation of property rights because they are contractually set
out in the sales and purchase agreement. In the area of land use and planning,
"private innovation" has usually preceded "public action."
Many features now common to zoning laws were first initiated by private developers.
This includes such planning items as the superblock, the cul de sac, set back
lines, planting strips, underground utilities, and design and placement of open
spaces and provision for recreational amenities.
Land use planners cannot predict all the changes that will come about in the
future. As Bernard Siegan noted, in 1913, when New York City planners began their
zoning work, they could not anticipate the impact of the automobile or the Great
Depression, or even foresee the advent of air conditioning or penicillin. In
a free society, land use controls and building codes would exist under the framework
of private covenants and insurance company standards (to be met as a precondition
to obtaining insurance coverage). Free market decision-making is usually wiser
than that of bureaucrats and politicians because the free market links authority
and responsibility: on the free market, the person or organization who makes
the decision has to pay for it. The most effective type of voluntary zoning is
the result of private covenants, market pricing, and competition. The social
potential inherent in the development of property and real estate under voluntaryism
is beyond the wit of man to foresee.
Short Bibliography
- David Beito, "Voluntary Associations and the Life of the City,"
HUMANE STUDIES REVIEW, Fall 1988.
- Gurney Breckenfeld, COLUMBIA AND THE NEW CITIES, New York: Ives Washburn,
Inc., 1971.
- Carol Christensen, THE AMERICAN GARDEN CITY AND THE NEW TOWN MOVEMENT, Ann
Arbor: UMI Research Press, 1978, 1986.
- Fred Foldvary, PUBLIC GOODS AND PRIVATE COMMUNITIES, Hants: Edward Elgar
Publishing, 1994.
- Robert Linowes and Don Allensworth, THE POLITICS OF LAND-USE LAW, New York:
Praeger, 1976.
- Spencer MacCallum, THE ART OF COMMUNITY, Menlo Park: Institute for Humane
Studies, Inc., 1970.
- Mel Scott, AMERICAN CITY PLANNING SINCE 1890, Berkeley: University of California
Press, 1971.
- Bernard Siegan, "No Zoning Is The Best Zoning," in Benjamin Bobo
(ed.) NO MAN IS AN ISLAND, San Francisco: Institute for Contemporary Studies,
1975.
- Seymour Toll, ZONED AMERICAN, New York: Grossman Publishers, 1969.
- Gordon Whitnall, "The History of Zoning,"' in ZONING IN THE UNITED
STATES, Vol. 155 THE ANNALS OF THE AMERICAN ACADEMY OF POLITICAL AND SOCIAL SCIENCE,
May 1931.